Feminism Without Metaphysics or a Deflationary Account of Gender

Abstract

I argue for a deflationary answer to the question, “What is it to be a woman?” Prior attempts by feminist theorists to provide a metaphysical account of what all and only women have in common have all failed for the same reason: there is nothing women have in common beyond being women. Although the social kinds man and woman are primitive, their existence can be explained. I say that human sex difference is the material ground of systems of gender; gender systems serve to enable male control of female reproductive capacities. This explains the fact that most women are female, but it does not entail that all women are female or that all females are women. To clarify my position, I draw an analogy between the kind woman and the kind parent. While it is difficult to come up with necessary and sufficient conditions for being a parent, it is clear that the social institution or practice of parenting has its material ground in the biological facts about human reproduction together with facts about infantile dependency. Saying this does not entail that all and only biological progenitors are parents.

This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution.

Notes

  1. 1.

    Early on in the so-called “second wave” of feminist theorizing, Simone de Beauvoir published her groundbreaking and highly influential work, The Second Sex (de Beauvoir 1949/1953), presenting a critique of biological determinism from an existentialist point of view. Firestone (1970) argued that women’s natures were not only not determined by their biology, but that technological development could and should free women completely from pregnancy and childbirth through technological development. Influential feminist critiques from the 1980’s include those by Wittig (1981), Frye (1983), MacKinnon (1987), and Genevieve Lloyd. For a detailed history of feminist philosophical discussion of biological determinism, see Warnke (2010). See also Antony (1997).

  2. 2.

    Gould (1981), Hrdy (1981), Hubbard (1983), Lewontin et al. (1984), Bleier (1984) and Fausto-Sterling (1985). See essays in Bleier (1986). For an excellent review of this literature, see Wylie et al. (1989).

  3. 3.

    See especially Fausto-Sterling (1985).

  4. 4.

    Butler (1990) and Haraway (1989).

  5. 5.

    See essays in Nicholson (1990).

  6. 6.

    Jaggar (1983), Alcoff and Potter (1993) and Young (1990).

  7. 7.

    Such as Friedan (1963).

  8. 8.

    Hooks (1984), Mohanty (1984), Lugones (1987), Hoagland (1988), Collins (1990), and essays in Sargent (1981).

  9. 9.

    Spelman (1988) and Fuss (1989).

  10. 10.

    Witt (2011), Haslanger (2000), Ásta (2018) and Barnes (forthcoming).

  11. 11.

    Bettcher (2012).

  12. 12.

    Mikkola (2016) and Robin Dembroff (Dembroff, ms) defend similar lines of thought.

  13. 13.

    I’ll follow the typographical convention illustrated here: I’ll put an expression in quotation marks when I’m mentioning, rather than using it, and I’ll put it in all caps when I want to refer to the concept to which the expression corresponds. I will use the expressions “Xhood” or “being an X” to refer to the property expressed by the expression.

  14. 14.

    My position, which I’ve argued for in a number of papers concerned with the causal efficacy of the mental, is that there is no such thing, strictly speaking, as “disjunctive properties;” there are only disjunctive characterizations of properties. (See, for example, my “Who’s Afraid of Disjunctive Properties?”, Antony 2003). But here as elsewhere, I’ll speak with the vulgar.

  15. 15.

    I have argued for this claim in many of my earlier papers. For example, see Antony (1995).

  16. 16.

    For a defense of this claim about Austinian speech-acts, see Antony (2012, 2014).

  17. 17.

    Thanks to Richard Kimberly Heck for pressing me on this point.

  18. 18.

    I am, of course, insinuating that men came to dominate women in order to exploit their reproductive capacities. Richard Kimberly Heck pressed me to say whether I had any actual evidence for this particular speculation. I don’t, other than it’s being explanatory if true. I’m not sure that there could be evidence for this, since the pertinent developments are lost in human prehistory. That doesn’t excuse my asserting something without evidence. But my fallback position is, as I note, simply that somehow or other, at some point in prehistory, the domination of females by males became a generic trait of the species homo sapiens.

  19. 19.

    Boyd (1999).

  20. 20.

    See Marilyn Frye, “Sexism” in Frye (1983).

  21. 21.

    Andreasen (2005), Spencer (2014) and Hardimon (2017).

  22. 22.

    Diamond (1997). I rely here on Jared Diamond, Guns, Germs and Steel. This work has come under criticism from anthropologists and historians, but none of the criticism that I have seen calls into question the correctness of his central claim, which is that differences in rates of technological development among peoples inhabiting different parts of the world can be explained by differences in the material conditions present in their geographical locations, rather than by “innate” differences in temperament or intelligence.

  23. 23.

    The subsequent discussion about parenthood was inspired by considerations raised by Alex Byrne in personal conversation, and discussed by him in (Byrne forthcoming).

  24. 24.

    The term “progenitor” is usually reserved for a male, but as there seems to be no parallel term for females (big surprise), I’m going to use the term to refer to either the male and the female involved in an act of reproduction.

  25. 25.

    “Surrogate pregnancy” is an unhappy phrase that suggests that the actual pregnancy of the woman gestating the child is merely a proxy for some other, genuine pregnancy. That is not, of course, the case.

  26. 26.

    See Jadva et al. (2015).

  27. 27.

    See Moody-Adams (1991), Parks (2010) and Mitra (2018).

  28. 28.

    Shrage (2013).

  29. 29.

    In one case, a transman in the UK who had obtained a gender recognition certificate, applied for legal acknowledgement that he was the father of the child he bore. It was denied: https://www.theguardian.com/society/2019/jul/16/transgender-man-who-gave-birth-loses-high-court-privacy-case-fred-mcconnell

  30. 30.

    As reported, for example, on the US television show 20/20: https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=WwuRSS2whTg

  31. 31.

    Compare the notion of a “virgin birth.” I grew up a Catholic, so this idea was a familiar one to me. Nonetheless, I was told several times by Protestant friends that such a thing was impossible, a “contradiction in terms.” Of course, contemporary reproductive technology has shown that such a thing as a virgin birth can exist even without divine intervention.

  32. 32.

    Unfortunately, large numbers of the children being separated from their parents due to the evil and politically motivated immigration policies of the Trump administration are not being placed in the care of foster parents. See “Migrant Children are Spending Months in ‘Crammed’ Facility in a Temporary Florida Shelter,” Miriam Jordan, The New York Times June 26, 2019.

  33. 33.

    This account, because it appeals to functional relations, rather than biological difference, does not exclude the possibility that some male individuals may qualify as “women” or that some female individuals may qualify as “men.” MacKinnon recognizes this implication, and explicitly endorses it.

  34. 34.

    It is particularly important for Western feminists to recognize the agency of women under even very harshly oppressive conditions, and not to parochially conceive of them either as naive “dupes” or as helpless “victims” of patriarchy. See Narayan (2002).

  35. 35.

    See for example, Young (1985).

  36. 36.

    This is a (partial) response to a question raised by Jennifer Saul, and to a query from an anonymous reviewer. A complete answer to these questions would involve a theory of reference-fixing for terms picking out social kinds, and I don’t have one. I take refuge, however, in the fact that “parent” and PARENT face exactly the same question, as do many, if not all terms and concepts of social kinds. My thinking on this was helped by a talk by Esa Díaz Léon, at G.A.P. 10. Thanks to Díaz Léon for providing me a copy of the paper on which her talk was based (Díaz Léon forthcoming)

  37. 37.

    Haslanger (2000) and Ásta (2018).

  38. 38.

    Haslanger (2000) wants to allow for the possibility of successor systems of this sort. But it’s unclear to me what would make such systems, systems of gender.

  39. 39.

    Antony (1998).

  40. 40.

    Mallon (2006).

  41. 41.

    Alcoff (2006, p. 232).

  42. 42.

    Quine (1975).

  43. 43.

    Ereshefsky, Mark "Species", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2017 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2017/entries/species/>.

  44. 44.

    The California Department of Wildlife regards them both as subtypes of canis lupus: https://www.wildlife.ca.gov/Search-Results?q=dogs%20and%20wolves. Scholastic.com, a resource for elementary and secondary school teachers, classifies dogs (canis familiaris) as distinct species as different from wolves, as either animal is from coyotes (canis latrans): https://www.scholastic.com/teachers/articles/teaching-content/wolves-coyotes-and-dogs/

  45. 45.

    Or, to be precise, I should say “a simple concept that has women as its content.” I don’t mean to presume that there is an interpersonal criterion of lexical identity for systems of mental representation. That is, one person might “spell” a concept CORIANDER while another spells it CILANTRO. This raises the possibility—which I think is real—of interpersonal Frege cases. However, I’ll ignore this qualification in what follows.

  46. 46.

    For a delightful and convincing piece of evidence that this is so, consider the following anecdote related here: https://www.netfunny.com/rhf/jokes/90q3/baret.html about what happened when the son of two Cornell psychologists (Sandra and Darryl Bem) wore barrettes to school.

  47. 47.

    I do not want to be committed to there being interpersonal criteria of type-identity for systems of mental representation. As I said above, you might “spell” your concept of a certain plant CORIANDER while I “spell” it CILANTRO, and such differences need make no difference to the contents of each concept. For ease of exposition, though, I’ll continue to speak of “the concept WOMAN.”

  48. 48.

    This is the sort of problem that doomed compositional semantics in the 70’s—try saying what you add to RUMINANT to distinguish cows from horses. BOVINE and EQUINE will work nicely, but then why do you need RUMINANT? See Fodor (1977).

References

  1. Alcoff, L. M. (2006). Visible identities: Race, gender, and the self. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  2. Alcoff, L. M., & Potter, E. (Eds.). (1993). Feminist epistemologies. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Andreasen, R. (2005). The meaning of ‘Race’: Folk conceptions and the new biology of race. The Journal of Philosophy,102, 94–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Antony, L. (1995). Sisters, please, i’d rather do it myself: A defense of individualism in psychology. Philosophical Topics,23(2), 59–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Antony, L. (1997). ‘Human Nature’ and its role in feminist theory. In J. A. Kourany (Ed.), Philosophy in a feminist voice: Critiques and reconstructions (pp. 63–91). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Antony, L. (1998). Back to androgyny: What bathrooms can teach us about equality. Journal of Contemporary Legal Issues,9, 1–20.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Antony, L. (2003). Who’s afraid of disjunctive properties? Philosophical Issues,13(1), 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Antony, L. (2012). Against Langton’s illocutionary treatment of pornography. Jurisprudence,2(2), 387–401.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Antony, L. (2014). Pornography and the philosophy of language. In L. Coleman & J. M. Held (Eds.), The philosophy of pornography (pp. 147–176). Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Antony, L., & Witt, C. (Eds.). (1995). A mind of one’s own: Feminist essays on reason and objectivity. Boulder, CO: Westview Press. 2nd Edition (expanded) 2002 (Toronto: Perseus Books).

    Google Scholar 

  11. Ásta. (2018). Categories we live by. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  12. Barnes, E. (forthcoming). Gender and Gender Terms. Noûs.

  13. Bettcher, T. M. (2012). Trans women and the meaning of ‘woman’. In N. Power, R. Halwani, & A. Soble (Eds.), Philosophy of sex: Contemporary readings (6th ed., pp. 233–250). New York: Rowan & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Bleier, R. (1984). Science and gender: A critique of biology and its theories on women. Elmsford, NY: Pergamon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Bleier, R. (Ed.). (1986). Feminist approaches to science (pp. 119–146). New York: Pergamon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Boyd, R. (1999). Homeostasis, species, and higher taxa. In R. Wilson (Ed.), Species: New interdisciplinary essays (pp. 141–185). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Butler, J. (1990). Gender trouble: Feminism and the subversion of identity. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Byrne, A. (forthcoming). Are women adult human females? Philosophical Studies.

  19. Collins, P. H. (1990). Black feminist thought. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  20. de Beauvoir, S. (1949/1953/2009). Le Deuxième Sexe, 2 volumes, Paris: Gallimard. Printed in English 1953 as The Second Sex by H.M. Parshley (trans. and ed.), New York: Knopf. Retranslated 2009 by Constance Borde and Sheila Malovany-Chevallier, London: Jonathan Cape.

  21. Dembroff, R. Manuscript. Oppressive categories.

  22. Diamond, J. (1997). Guns, germs, and steel. New York: W. W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Díaz Léon, E. (forthcoming). On the conceptual mismatch argument: Descriptions, disagreement and amelioration. In T. Marques & A. Wikforss (eds.), Shifting concepts: The philosophy and psychology of conceptual variability. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  24. Ereshefsky, M. (2017). Species. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2017 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (Ed.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2017/entries/species/.

  25. Fausto-Sterling, A. (1985/1992). Myths of gender: Biological theories about women and men. New York: Basic Books.

  26. Firestone, S. (1970). The dialectic of sex: The case for feminist revolution. New York: Bantam.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Fodor, J. D. (1977). Semantics: Theories of meaning in generative grammar. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Fox Keller, E. (1983). Gender and science. Harding and Hintikka,1983, 187–205.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Friedan, B. (1963). The feminine mystique. New York: W. W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Frye, M. (1983). The politics of reality. Freedom, CA: The Crossing Press.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Fuss, D. (1989). Essentially speaking: Feminism, nature, and difference. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Gould, S. J. (1981). The mismeasure of man. New York: W. W. Norton Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Haraway, D. (1989). Primate visions: Gender, race, and nature in the world of modern science. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Hardimon, M. (2017). Rethinking race: The case for deflationary realism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  35. Harding, S., & Hintikka, M. B. P. (1983). Discovering reality: Feminist perspectives on epistemology, metaphysics, methodology, and philosophy of science (Synthese Library Book 161). New York: Springer Publishers.

  36. Hartsock, N. (1983). The feminist standpoint: Developing the ground for a specifically feminist historical materialism. Harding and Hintikka,1983, 283–310.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Haslanger, S. (2000). Gender and race: (What) are they? (What) do we want them to be?. Noûs 34:1 (March), 31–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. Hoagland, S. (1988). Lesbian ethics: Toward new value. Palo Alto: Frog in the Well.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  39. Hooks, B. (1984). Feminist theory: From margin to center. Boston: South End Press.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Hornsby, J. (2000). Feminism in philosophy of language: Communicative speech acts. In M. Fricker & J. Hornsby (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to feminism in philosophy (pp. 87–106). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Hrdy, S. (1981/1999). The woman that never evolved. Boston: Harvard University Press.

  42. Hubbard, R. (1983). Have only men evolved? In S. Harding & M. Hintikka (Eds.), Discovering reality: Feminist perspectives on epistemology, metaphysics, methodology, and philosophy of science (pp. 45–70). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Jadva, V., Imrie, S., & Golombok, S. (2015). Surrogate mothers 10 years on: A longitudinal study of psychological well-being and relationships with the parents and child. Human Reproduction,30(2), 373–379. https://doi.org/10.1093/humrep/deu339.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  44. Jaggar, A. (1983). Feminist politics and human nature. Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Allanheld.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Jordan, M. (2019). Migrant children are spending months in ‘Crammed’ facility in a temporary Florida shelter. The New York Times, June 26.

  46. Lewontin, R. C., Rose, S., & Kamin, L. J. (1984). Not in our genes: Biology, ideology and human nature. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Lloyd, G. L. (1984). The man of reason: ‘Male’ and ‘Female’ in western philosophy. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Lugones, M. (1987). Playfulness, ‘World’-traveling, and loving perception. Hypatia,2, 3–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  49. MacKinnon, C. (1987). Feminism unmodified. Boston, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Mallon, R. (2006). Race: Normative, not metaphysical or semantic. Ethics,116(3), 525–551.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  51. Mikkola, M. (2016). The wrong of injustice: Dehumanization and its role in feminist philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  52. Mitra, P. (2018). Invisible women in reproductive technologies: Critical reflections. Indian Journal of Medical Ethics,3(2), 113–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  53. Mohanty, C. T. (1984). Under western eyes: Feminist scholarship and colonial discourse. Boundary,2, 337–338.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Moody-Adams, M. (1991). On surrogacy: Morality, markets, and motherhood. Public Affairs Quarterly,5(2), 175–190.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Narayan, U. (2002). Minds of their own: Choices, autonomy and cultural practices. Antony & Witt,2002, 418–432.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Nicholson, L. (Ed.). (1990). Feminism/Postmodernism. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Parks, J. A. (2010). Care ethics and the global practice of commercial surrogacy. Bioethics,24(7), 333–340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  58. Quine, W. V. O. (1975). On Empirically Equivalent Systems of the World. Erkenntnis,9(3), 313–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  59. Sargent, L. (Ed.). (1981). Women and revolution. Boston: South End Press.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Scheman, N. (1995/2002). Though this be method, yet there is madness in it: Paranoia and liberal epistemology. In Antony and Witt (pp. 119–128).

  61. Shrage, L. (2013). Is forced fatherhood fair? The New York Times Opinionator Blog https://opinionator.blogs.nytimes.com/2013/06/12/is-forced-fatherhood-fair/?mtrref=www.google.com&gwh=BC66F5693B15E8F7D4AF11061E0BE101&gwt=pay&assetType=REGIWALL.

  62. Spelman, E. (1988). Inessential woman: Problems of exclusion in feminist thought. Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Spencer, Q. (2014). A radical solution to the race problem. Philosophy of Science,81(5), 1025–1038.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  64. Warnke, G. (2010). Debating sex and gender. Cambridge: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Witt, C. (2011). The metaphysics of gender. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  66. Wittig, M. (1981). One is not born a woman. Feminist Issues,1, 2.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Wylie, A., Okruhlik, K., Thielen-Wilson, L., & Morton, S. (1989). Feminist critiques of science: The epistemological and methodological literature. Women’s Studies International Forum,12(3), 379–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  68. Young, I. M. (1985). Humanism, gynocentrism and feminist politics. Women’s Studies International Quarterly,3, 173–183.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  69. Young, I. M. (1990/2012). Justice and the politics of difference. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Download references

Acknowledgements

This paper is based closely on a keynote address given at GAP.10 in Cologne, Germany, Sept. 17, 2018. An earlier version of his paper was presented to Richard Boyd’s seminar on social kinds at Cornell University in October 2016, and a later version of this paper was presented to my colleagues at the University of Massachusetts in December 2018. I’d like to thank all my audiences for their attention and their feedback. I owe particular thanks, for criticism and discussion, to Rachel Antony-Levine, Karen Bennett, Richard Boyd, Alex Byrne, Esa Díaz Léon, Elizabeth Harman, Sally Haslanger, Richard Kimberly Heck, Hilary Kornblith, Joseph Levine, Ned Markosian, Sally McConnell-Ginet, Mari Mikkola, and Jennifer Saul. (I have answered all objections except for the ones I haven’t.) Thanks also to two anonymous referees, and special thanks to editors Thomas Grundmann and Joachim Horvath for their advice, both philosophical and editorial, and for their patience!

Author information

Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Louise Antony.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and Permissions

About this article

Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Antony, L. Feminism Without Metaphysics or a Deflationary Account of Gender. Erkenn 85, 529–549 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-020-00243-2

Download citation