Skip to main content
Log in

The Intermediate Scope of Consciousness in the Predictive Mind

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

There is a view on consciousness that has strong intuitive appeal and empirical support: the intermediate-level theory of consciousness, proposed mainly by Ray Jackendoff and by Jesse Prinz. This theory identifies a specific “intermediate” level of representation as the basis of human phenomenal consciousness, which sits between high-level non-perspectival thought processes and low-level disjointed feature-detection processes in the perceptual and cognitive processing hierarchy. In this article, we show that the claim that consciousness arises at an intermediate-level is true of some cognitive systems, but only in virtue of specific constraints on their active interactions with the environment. We provide ecological reasons for why certain processing levels in a cognitive hierarchy are privileged with respect to consciousness. We do this from the perspective of a prediction-error minimization model of perception and cognition, relying especially on the notion of active inference: the privileged level for consciousness depends on the specific dispositions of an organism concerned with inferring its policies for action. Such a level is indeed intermediate for humans, but this depends on the spatiotemporal resolution of the typical actions that a human organism can normally perform. Thus, intermediateness is not an essential feature of consciousness. In organisms with different action dispositions the privileged level or levels may differ as well.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. We use ‘consciousness’, ‘phenomenal consciousness’ and ‘phenomenal experience’ interchangeably to refer to the what it’s like to see, hear, touch, taste, etc. something (Nagel, 1974). Also, for reasons of length and focus, we wish to remain neutral on the distinction between phenomenal consciousness and access consciousness. If one accepts such a distinction, much of what we say in this article is directly relevant for access consciousness.

  2. Here the term “cognitive” is used in a broader sense as to encompass, perceptual, affective and evaluative processes.

  3. It should be noted, however, that Prinz (2012) engages with the mechanistic and functional questions as well, offering a detailed outline of what he takes to be the core neural mechanism realizing conscious experience, namely synchronization of some neural representations at the gamma frequency of 40 Hz. We do not engage with these further questions in this article.

  4. Of course, the contents in the example are token-content, but the fact that they differ in the rate of change shows that, for Marr, they belong to different content types. .

  5. We leave the nature of this relation unspecified, since we are not interested with the metaphysical question, as we clarify below.

  6. See Raftopoulos (2013) for a discussion of a minimal part of vision that might be considered completely encapsulated. However, Vetter and Newen (2014) argue that even such minimal part is not isolated form higher-level feedback (see also Newen & Vetter, 2017).

  7. Here it should be highlighted that while ILC theories are explicitly representationalist, the jury on the general representational commitments of PEM is still out (see for example Wiese, 2016; Dolega, 2017; Downey, 2018).

  8. PEM has been successfully applied to model and explain various phenomena in different perceptual and cognitive domains. Primary examples are binocular rivalry (Hohwy, et al. 2008), and the positive symptoms of schizophrenia (Fletcher and Frith, 2008). For an extensive review and discussion of successful applications of PEM see Clark (2015)

  9. To better illustrate this point, one may rely on Egan’s distinction between mathematical and cognitive content of a representational vehicle (Egan, 2013). The mathematical contents, which are the only real contents, at each level of the PEM internal model’s hierarchy are of the same type, while the intentional contents of hypotheses, such as objects and their properties (e.g. relative and general location in the example above), are part of the explanatory gloss we attach to the theory in order to relate the underlying computations to one’s explanatory goal, which is, in our case, understanding the scope of phenomenal consciousness. Different levels of the hierarchy may be ascribed different intentional contents in the gloss depending on the spatiotemporal resolution of hypotheses at those levels. See also Wiese (2016) for a non-instrumentalist take on Egan’s cognitive contents in PP.

  10. This point is neatly summarized by Clark (2015, p. 293), quoting Lawereyns when he talks about the contents of generative models: “The representations thus constructed [from the generative model] are ‘not actual re-presentations or duplicates of objects in the world but … incomplete, abstract code that makes predictions about the world and revises its predictions on the basis of interaction with the world (Lawereyns, 2012, p. 74)’”.

  11. Here we shall take into account only typically developed organisms.

  12. We are grateful to an anonymous referee for pressing this issue.

  13. There is evidence of expectations about weight (Brouwer et al. 2006), size and force (Brenner and Smeets, 1996) affecting the way the grasping action is performed.

  14. Gregory (1996, p. 377)

  15. We are grateful to an anonymous referee for pointing us to this line of research.

  16. We are grateful to an anonymous referee for raising this worry.

  17. We are grateful to an anonymous referee for raising this issue.

References

  • Beets, I., Hart, B., Rösler, F., Henriques, D., Einhäuser, W., & Fiehler, K. (2010). Online action-to-perception transfer: Only percept-dependent action affects perception. Vision Research, 50, 2633–2641.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brenner, E., & Smeets, J. (1996). Size illusion influences how we lift but not how we grasp an object. Experimental Brain Research, 111, 473–476.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, A., Georgiou, I., Glover, S., & Castiello, U. (2006). Adjusting reach to lift movements to sudden visible changes in target’s weight. Experimental Brain Research, 173, 629–636.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brownstein, (2018). The implicit mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2015). Surfing uncertainty. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crick, F., & Koch, C. (2000). The unconscious homunculus. Neuropsychoanalysis, 2(1), 3–11.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dolega, K. (2017). Moderate predictive processing. In T. Metzinger & W. Wiese (Eds.), Philosophy and predictive processing: 10. Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Downey, A. (2018). Predictive processing and the representation wars: A victory for the eliminativist (via fictionalism). Synthese, 195(12), 5115–5139.

    Google Scholar 

  • Egan, F. (2013). How to think about mental content. Philosophical Studies, 170(1), 115–135.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fletcher, P., & Frith, C. (2008). Perceiving is believing: A Bayesian approach to explaining the positive symptoms of schizophrenia. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 10(1), 48–58.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friston, K. (2010). The free-energy principle: A unified brain theory? Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 11, 127–138.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friston, K., Daunizeau, J., & Kiebel, S. (2009). Reinforcement learning or active inference? PLoS ONE, 4(7), e6421.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friston, K., Rigoli, F., Ognibene, D., Mathys, C., Fitzgerald, T., & Pezzulo, G. (2015). Active inference and epistemic value. Cognitive Neuroscience, 6(4), 187–214.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friston, K., Samothrakis, S., & Montague, R. (2012). Active inference and agency: Optimal control without cost functions. Biological Cybernetics, 106(8–9), 523–541.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friston, K., Schwartenbeck, P., Fitzgerald, T., Moutoussis, M., Behrens, T., & Dolan, R. (2013). The anatomy of choice: Active inference and agency. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 7, 598.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frith, C. D. (1995). Consciousness is for other people. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 18(4), 682–683.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2016). Other minds. New York: Farrar, Strauss, and Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gregory, R. (1996). What do qualia do? Perception, 25, 377–379.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayhoe, M., Shrivastava, A., Mruczek, R., & Pelz, J. (2003). Visual memory and motor planning in a natural task. Journal of Vision, 3(1), 49–63.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy, J. (2013). The predictive mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy, J. (2014). The self-evidencing brain. Nous, 50(2), 259–285.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy, J. (2016a). Priors in perception: Top-down modulation, bayesian perceptual learning rate, and prediction error minimization. Consciousness and Cognition, 47, 1–11.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy, J. (2016b). Prediction, agency, and body ownership. Where is the action? In A. Engel, K. Friston, & D. Kragic (Eds.), The pragmatic turn in cognitive science. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy, J., Roepstorff, A., & Friston, K. (2008). Predictive coding explains binocular rivalry: An epistemological review. Cognition, 108(3), 687–701.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hornsby, J. (2013). Basic activity. Aristotelian Society Supplementary, 87(1), 1–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Humphreys, G., & Riddoch, M. (2007). How to define an object: Evidence from the effects of action on perception and attention. Mind and Language, 22, 534–547.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackendoff, R. (1987). Consciousness and the computational mind. London: Bradford Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kentridge, R., Heywood, C., & Weiskrantz, L. (1999). Attention Without Awareness in Blindsight. Proceedings. Biological Sciences/the Royal Society, 266(1430), 1805–1811.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kentridge, R., Nijboer, T. C., & Heywood, C. (2008). Attended but unseen: Visual attention is not sufficient for visual awareness. Neuropsychologia, 46(3), 864–869.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koch, C. (2004). The quest for consciousness. Englewood: Roberts Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lavin, D. (2013). Must there be basic action? Nous, 47(2), 273–301.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawereyns, J. (2012). Brain and the gaze: On the active boundaries of vision. Cambridge: MIT press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Libet, B. (1985). Unconscious cerebral initiative and the role of conscious will in voluntary action. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 8, 529–566.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macpherson, F. (2011). Introduction to Hawley, K. and Macpherson, F. The admissible contents of experience (pp. 1–15). Hoboken: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mandelbaum, E. (2014). Thinking is believing. Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy, 57(1), 55–96.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mandelbaum, E. (2015). Attitude, inference, association: On the propositional structure of implicit bias. Nous, 50(3), 629–658.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marchi, F., & Newen, A. (2016). The cognitive foundations of visual consciousness: Why should we favour a processing approach? Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 15(2), 247–264.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marr, D. (1982). Vision. Cambridge: MIT press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? The Philosophical Review, 83(4), 435–450.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newen, A., & Vetter, P. (2017). Why cognitive penetration of our perceptual experience is still the most plausible account. Consciousness and Cognition, 47, 26–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parr, T., Corcoran, A., Friston, K., & Hohwy, J. (2019). Perceptual awareness and active inference. Neuroscience of Consciousness, 5(1), niz012.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perrykkad, K., & Hohwy, J. (2020). Fidgeting as self-evidencing: A predictive processing account of non-goal-directed action. New Ideas in Psychology, 56, 750.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. (2000). A neurofunctional theory of consciousness. Consciousness and Cognition, 9, 243–259.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. (2012). The conscious brain: How attention engenders experience. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. (2017). The intermediate level theory of consciousness. In S. Schneider & M. Velmans (Eds.), The Blackwell companion to consciousness (2nd ed., pp. 257–271). Wiley.

  • Raftopoulos, A. (2013). The cognitive impenetrability of the content of early vision is a necessary and sufficient condition for purely nonconceptual content. Philosophical Psychology, 27(5), 601–620.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riddoch, M., Humphreys, G., Hickman, M., Clift, J., Daly, A., & Colin, J. (2006). I can see what you are doing: Action familiarity and affordance promote recovery from extinction. Cognitive Neuropsychology, 23, 583–605.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandis, C. (2010). Basic actions and individuation. In T. O’Connor & C. Sandis (Eds.), A companion to the philosophy of action (pp. 10–17). Oxford: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, S. (2006a). Subject and object in the contents of visual experience. The Philosophical Review, 115, 355–388.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, S. (2006b). Which properties are represented in perception? In T. Szabo Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Perceptual experience. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, S. (2012). The contents of visual experience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Song, C., & Yao, H. (2016). Unconscious processing of invisible visual stimuli. Scientific Reports, 6, 38917.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vetter, P., & Newen, A. (2014). Varieties of cognitive penetration in visual perception. Consciousness and Cognition, 27, 62–75.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiese, W. (2016). What are the contents of representations in predictive processing? Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 16(4), 715–736.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiese, W. (2017). Action is enabled by systematic misrepresentations. Erkenntnis, 82(6), 1233–1252.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We are grateful to the Ruhr University Research School PLUS for supporting mutual visits between Ruhr-Universität Bochum and Monash University in the years 2016–2017 during which this paper was conceived. FM is supported by the Mercator Research Center Ruhr (MERCUR) project Pr-2016-0016 and by the Center for Mind and Cognition of the Ruhr Universität Bochum. JH is supported by the Australian Research Council DP160102770 and DP190101805 and by the Research School Bochum and the Center for Mind and Cognition, Ruhr-University Bochum.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Francesco Marchi.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Marchi, F., Hohwy, J. The Intermediate Scope of Consciousness in the Predictive Mind. Erkenn 87, 891–912 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-020-00222-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-020-00222-7

Navigation