[I]n saying these words, we are doing something ...rather than reporting something.
Austin (1962, p. 13)
Abstract
Pierre Duhem’s influential argument for holism relies on a view of the role that background theory plays in testing: according to this still common account of “auxiliary hypotheses,” elements of background theory serve as truth-apt premises in arguments for or against a hypothesis. I argue that this view is mistaken. Rather than serving as truth-apt premises in arguments, auxiliary hypotheses are employed as (reliability-apt) “epistemic tools”: instruments that perform specific tasks in connecting our theoretical questions with the world but that are not (or not usually) premises in arguments. On the resulting picture, the acceptability of an auxiliary hypothesis depends not on its truth but on contextual factors such as the task or purpose it is put to and the other tools employed alongside it.
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
I’m not interested in diving into questions of what Duhem really meant, and will generally refer to the schematized “Duhemian” from now on; for a discussion of Duhem’s intended argument, see Ariew (2018).
This may seem obvious, but the issue of just how heterozygous populations are was a fraught one for mid-twentieth century biology; see, e.g., Lewontin (1974).
Of course, this description is idealized. The inclusion of other stochastic processes such as drift or complicating factors such as linkage disequilibrium mean that such inferences will necessarily be statistical. But the simple description suffices for our point.
Compare Filion and Moir (2018, p. 739), who employ a related notion of reliability in a more technical context.
I’m implicitly assuming a “materialist” account of induction here (see Norton 2003), but I don’t think that this claim relies on any controversial aspect of Norton’s account.
Of course, Edman’s condition is an idealization. We might expect an unreliable thermometer (like an unreliable clock) to be relatively close. How an instrument is broken matters, and we’ll rarely have no information on that front. The same point can be made about theoretical instruments, however, and so the idealization shouldn’t undermine the point.
References
Ariew, R. (2018). Pierre Duhem. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/duhem/. Retrieved July 07, 2019.
Austin, J. L. (1962). How to do things with words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Azzouni, J. (2000). Knowledge and reference in empirical science. London: Routledge.
Bokulich, A. (2018). Using models to correct data: paleodiversity and the fossil record. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1820-x
Bovens, L., & Hartmann, S. (2003). Bayesian epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Brenner, A. A. (1990). Holism a century ago: The elaboration of Duhem’s thesis. Synthese, 83(3), 325–335.
Cartwright, N. (1991). Replicability, reproducibility, and robustness: Comments on Harry Collins. History of Political Economy, 23(1), 143–155.
Currie, A. (2018). Rock, bone, and ruin: A optimist’s guide to the historical sciences. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Duhem, P. (1914/1951). The aim and structure of physical theory (P. P. Wiener, Trans.). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Edman, M. (1973). Adding independent pieces of evidence. In S. Halldén (Ed.), Modality, morality and other problems of sense and nonsense (pp. 180–188). Lund: Gleerup.
Edwards, P. (2010). A vast machine: Computer models, climate data, and the politics of global warming. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Elgin, C. (2017). True enough. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
Filion, N., & Moir, R. H. C. (2018). Explanation and abstraction from a backward-error analytic perspective. European Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 8, 735–759.
Hacking, I. (1983). Representing and intervening: Introductory topics in the philosophy of natural science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Houkes, W., & Vaesen, K. (2012). Robust! Handle with care. Philosophy of Science, 79(3), 345–364.
Lewontin, R. C. (1974). The genetic basis of evolutionary change. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.
Lloyd, E. (2012). The role of “complex” empiricism in the debates about satellite data and climate models. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 43(2), 390–401.
Longino, H. (1990). Science and social knowledge: Values and objectivity in scientific inquiry. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Mäki, U. (2005). Models are experiments, experiments are models. Journal of Economic Methodology, 12(2), 303–315.
Mayo, D. G. (1996). Error and the growth of experimental knowledge. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Mayo, D. G. (2018). Statistical inference as severe testing: How to get beyond the statistics wars. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Morgan, M. S., & Morrison, M. (1999). Models as mediating instruments. In M. S. Morgan & M. Morrison (Eds.), Models as mediators: Perspectives on natural and social science (pp. 10–37). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Morrison, J. (2010). Just how controversial is evidential holism? Synthese, 173(3), 335–352.
Morrison, M. (2015). Reconstructing reality: Models, mathematics, and simulations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Norton, J. (2003). A material theory of induction. Philosophy of Science, 70(4), 647–670.
Norton, S. D., & Suppe, F. (2001). Why atmospheric modeling is good science. In C. A. Miller & P. N. Edwards (Eds.), Changing the atmosphere: Expert knowledge and environmental governance (pp. 67–105). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
Odenbaugh, J., & Alexandrova, A. (2011). Buyer beware: Robustness analyses in economics and biology. Biology & Philosophy, 26(5), 757–771.
Orzack, S., & Sober, E. (1993). A critical assessment of Levins’s “The strategy of model building in population biology” (1966). The Quarterly Review of Biology, 68(4), 533–546.
Parker, W. S. (2009a). Confirmation and adequacy-for-purpose in climate modeling. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 83, 233–249.
Parker, W. S. (2009b). Does matter really matter? Computer simulations, experiments, and materiality. Synthese, 169(3), 483–496.
Parker, W. S. (2016). Reanalyses and observations: What’s the difference? Bulletin of the American Meteorological Society, 97(9), 1565–1572.
Quinn, P. (1974). What Duhem really meant. In R. S. Cohen & M. W. Wartofsky (Eds.), Methodological and historical essays in the natural and social sciences (pp. 33–56). Dordrecht: Reidel.
Schliesser, E. & Smith, G. E. (forthcoming). Huygens’s 1688 report to the Directors of the Dutch East India Company on the measurement of longitude at sea and the evidence it offered against universal gravity. Archive for the History of the Exact Sciences. http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/5510/.
Sober, E. (1984). The nature of selection: Evolutionary theory in philosophical focus. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Sober, E. (1999). Testability. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 38(2), 47–76.
Strevens, M. (2001). The Bayesian treatment of auxiliary hypotheses. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 52, 515–537.
Suppes, P. (1962). Models of data. In E. Nagel, P. Suppes, & A. Tarski (Eds.), Logic, methodology and philosophy of science: Proceedings of the 1960 international congress (pp. 252–261). Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Teller, P. (2001). Twilight of the perfect model model. Erkenntnis, 55(4), 393–415.
Tempelton, A. R. (2006). Population genetics and microevolutionary theory. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.
Wilson, M. (2006). Wandering significance: An essay on conceptual behavior. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Winsberg, E. (2010). Science in the age of computer simulation. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Winsberg, E. (2018). Philosophy and climate science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Woodward, J. (2006). Some varieties of robustness. Journal of Economic Methodology, 13(2), 219–240.
Acknowledgements
I would like to thank James Nguyen, Anjan Chakravartty, audiences at Notre Dame and at PSA 2018 in Seattle, and two anonymous reviewers for comments on earlier versions of this essay.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Additional information
Publisher's Note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Dethier, C. How to Do Things with Theory: The Instrumental Role of Auxiliary Hypotheses in Testing. Erkenn 86, 1453–1468 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-019-00164-9
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-019-00164-9