Perceptual Knowledge, Discrimination, and Closure

Abstract

Carter and Pritchard (Philos Stud 173(4):969–990, 2016) and Pritchard (Noûs 44(2):245–268, 2010, Epistemological disjunctivism, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2012, Epistemic angst: radical scepticism and the groundlessness of our believing, Princeton University Press, Princeton, 2016) have tried to reconcile the intuition that perceptual knowledge requires only limited discriminatory abilities with the closure principle. To this end, they have introduced two theoretical innovations: a contrast between two ways of introducing error-possibilities and a distinction between discriminating and favoring evidence. I argue that their solution faces the “sufficiency problem”: it is unclear whether the evidence that is normally available to adult humans is sufficient to retain knowledge of the entailing proposition and come to know the entailed proposition. I submit that, on either infallibilist or fallibilist views of evidence, Carter and Pritchard have set the bar for deductive knowledge too low. At the end, I offer an alternative solution. I suggest that the knowledge-retention condition of the closure principle is not satisfied in zebra-like scenarios.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in to check access.

Notes

  1. 1.

    The relevant alternatives intuition is shared by many philosophers who otherwise disagree about the relation between evidence and knowledge or the factors that determine whether an alternative is relevant. Taking a stance on these issues is certainly important to offer an account of knowledge. Fortunately, none of our arguments depends on how one fills in these details. See Cohen (1988, 1999), Dretske (1970, 1981), Lewis (1996), and Stine (1976) for different approaches. See Vogel (1999) for criticism.

  2. 2.

    See Hawthorne (2004: 34), Pritchard (2012: 68), and Williamson (2000: 117).

  3. 3.

    This assumption is relatively common in the literature. Examples include Schaffer (2005), Stine (1976), and Wright (2003). Dretske (1970: 39) has a more expansive conception of evidence but also thinks that it is not sufficient to know the denial of the cleverly disguised mule hypothesis. The present paper may be seen as an attempt to vindicate Dretske’s intuition without either rejecting the closure principle or relying on Dretske’s controversial theory of conclusive reasons.

  4. 4.

    But see Radford (1966), for a controversial counterexample to the claim that knowledge that p entails belief that p.

  5. 5.

    See Carter and Pritchard (2016: 977, 978, 980), Pritchard (2012: 68ff., 76, 80, 81, 86, 87, 95–98, 99–100, 102 n 6, 104 n 17, 105 n 19), and Pritchard (2016: 131, 132, 137). The qualification ‘normal adult human’ is meant to exclude infants and animals. There is some lack of clarity on how inclusive the class of normal adult humans is. Carter and Pritchard recognize that adult humans may sometimes be unable to know, via competent deduction, the logical consequences of their perceptual knowledge. They make room for cases involving adult humans who lack any background evidence (Pritchard 2012: 79, 83) or whose background evidence is defeated by the epistemic authority of their interlocutor (Carter and Pritchard 2016: 983). Nevertheless, their discussion is guided by the assumption that the evidence available to normal adult humans will often suffice to retain their initial knowledge and dismiss the target error-possibility. That assumption is the main target of this paper.

  6. 6.

    Ecumenism plays a key role in Pritchard’s defense of epistemological disjunctivism. He needs to defend closure without presupposing the truth of the latter (Pritchard 2012: 63, 64, 80, 82).

  7. 7.

    Pritchard formulates epistemological disjunctivism in terms of reasons, which may not be equivalent to evidence. This difference does not matter in the current context.

  8. 8.

    If seeing that p entails knowing that p, then one cannot retain one’s seeing that p without knowing that p (Williamson 2000). Pritchard (2012) rejects the entailment. I am granting Pritchard’s controversial view for the sake of the argument.

  9. 9.

    Hereafter, I abbreviate ‘recognize as…’ to ‘recognize’.

  10. 10.

    I owe this objection to a referee for this journal.

  11. 11.

    A referee for this journal urged me to discuss this argument.

  12. 12.

    See Dretske (1970: 33). For similar formulations, see Cohen (1988: 93; 1999: 62), DeRose (1995: 31 n 33), Dretske (2005: 13), Nozick (1981: 204ff.), Stine (1976: 249), and Vogel (1990: 13; 1999: 156).

  13. 13.

    Some of them come from the distinction between propositional and doxastic justification. See Sect. 3.

  14. 14.

    Of course, one could have pre-deductive knowledge of the denial of the cleverly disguised mule hypothesis. What seems wrong is to construe that knowledge as a necessary requirement to have knowledge of the zebra proposition. Otherwise, we would have trouble accommodating the idea that deduction can provide new knowledge.

References

  1. Austin, J. L. (1946). Other minds. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 20, 148–187.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Carter, A., & Pritchard, D. (2016). Perceptual knowledge and relevant alternatives. Philosophical Studies, 173(4), 969–990.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Cohen, J. (1988). How to be a fallibilist. Philosophical Perspectives, 2, 91–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Cohen, J. (1999). Contextualism, skepticism, and the structure of reasons. Philosophical Perspectives, 13, 57–89.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Conee, E. (2005). Contextualism contested. In M. Steup & E. Sosa (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology (pp. 47–57). Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  6. DeRose, K. (1995). Solving the skeptical problem. Philosophical Review, 104, 1–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Dretske, F. (1970). Epistemic operators. Journal of Philosophy 67, 1007–1023. Reprinted in his Perception, knowledge, and belief: Selected essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (pp. 30–47).

  8. Dretske, F. (1971). Conclusive reasons. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 49(1), 1–22. Reprinted in his Perception, knowledge, and belief: Selected essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (pp. 3–29).

  9. Dretske, F. (1981). The pragmatic dimension of knowledge. Philosophical Studies, 40, 363–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Dretske, F. (2005). The case against closure. In M. Steup & E. Sosa (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology (pp. 11–26). Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Feldman, R. (1999). Contextualism and skepticism. Philosophical Perspectives, 13, 91–114.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Firth, R. (1978). Are epistemic concepts reducible to ethical concepts? In A. Goldman & J. Kim (Eds.), Values and morals (pp. 215–229). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Goldman, A. (1976). Discrimination and perceptual knowledge. Journal of Philosophy, 73(20), 771–791.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Harman, G. (1986). Change in view. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Hawthorne, J. (2004). Knowledge and lotteries. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Lewis, D. (1996). Elusive knowledge. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74, 549–567. Reprinted in his Papers in metaphysics and epistemology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999 (pp. 418–445).

  17. MacFarlane, J. (2000). What does it mean to say that logic is formal? Ph.D. Dissertation, University of Pittsburgh.

  18. Nozick, R. (1981). Philosophical explanations. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Pritchard, D. (2010). Relevant alternatives, perceptual knowledge and discrimination. Noûs, 44(2), 245–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Pritchard, D. (2012). Epistemological disjunctivism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Pritchard, D. (2016). Epistemic angst: Radical scepticism and the groundlessness of our believing. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Pryor, J. (2000). The skeptic and the dogmatist. Noûs, 34, 517–549.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Radford, C. (1966). Knowledge—By examples. Analysis, 27, 1–11.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Schaffer, J. (2005). Contrastive knowledge. In T. S. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Oxford studies in epistemology (Vol. 1, pp. 235–271). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Schaffer, J. (2007). Closure, contrast, and answer. Philosophical Studies, 133, 233–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. Stine, G. C. (1976). Skepticism, relevant alternatives, and deductive closure. Philosophical Studies, 29, 249–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Vogel, J. (1990). Are there counterexamples to the closure principle? In M. Roth & G. Ross (Eds.), Doubting: Contemporary perspectives on skepticism (pp. 13–27). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Vogel, J. (1999). The new relevant alternatives theory. Philosophical Perspectives, 13, 155–180.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Williams, M. (1991). Unnatural doubts: Epistemological realism and the basis of scepticism. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Wright, C. (2003). Some reflections on the acquisition of warrant by inference. In S. Nuccetelli (Ed.), New essays on semantic externalism and self-knowledge (pp. 57–77). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Arturs Logins, Davide Fassio, and two anonymous referees for their detailed and challenging comments on an earlier draft of this paper.

Funding

Funding was provided by Schweizerischer Nationalfonds zur Förderung der Wissenschaftlichen Forschung (Grant No. FNS P300P1_161061/1).

Author information

Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Santiago Echeverri.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and Permissions

About this article

Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Echeverri, S. Perceptual Knowledge, Discrimination, and Closure. Erkenn (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-018-0081-x

Download citation