Skip to main content
Log in

Epistemic Modals and Alternative Possibilities

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Indicative judgments pertain to what is true. Epistemic modal judgments pertain to what must or might be true relative to a body of information. A standard view is that epistemic modals implicitly quantify over alternative possibilities, or ways things could turn out. On this view, a proposition must be true just in case it is true in all the possibilities consistent with the available information, and a proposition might be true just in case it is true in at least one possibility consistent with the available information. I report three experiments testing this view of epistemic modals. The results show that although modal judgments are sensitive to information about alternative possibilities, the standard quantification theory mischaracterizes the ordinary meaning of modals. I then report two more experiments testing the hypothesis that epistemic modals express willingness to attribute knowledge based on the available information. The results support this hypothesis. The results also show that the difference between “inside” and “outside” probabilistic information, familiar from the judgment and decision-making literature, affects epistemic modal judgments.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Austin, J. L. (1962). How to do things with words. J. O. Urmson (Ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Bell, V. A., & Johnson-Laird, P. N. (1998). A model theory of modal reasoning. Cognitive Science, 22(1), 25–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chickering, D. M. (2002). Optimal structure identification with greedy search. The Journal of Machine Learning Research, 3(1), 507–554.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colaço, D., Buckwalter, W., Stich, S., & Machery, E. (2014). Epistemic intuitions in fake-barn thought experiments. Episteme, 11(02), 199–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, K. (1991). Epistemic possibilities. Philosophical Review, 100(4), 581–605.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diamond, H. A. (1990). Reasonable doubt: To define, or not to define. Columbia Law Review, 90(6), 1716.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dowell, J. L. (2011). A flexible contextualist account of epistemic modals. Philosophers’ Imprint, 11(14), 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Egan, A. (2007). Epistemic modals, relativism and assertion. Philosophical Studies, 133(1), 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, O., & Turri, J. (2014). Is probabilistic evidence a source of knowledge? Cognitive Science, 39(5), 1062–1080. doi:10.1111/cogs.12182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Furrow, D., & Moore, C. (1990). Gender differences in differentiating terms expressing certainty. Journal of Psycholinguistic Research, 19(6), 375–385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1967). Possibility. The Philosophical Review, 76(2), 143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, J. (2004). Knowledge and lotteries. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayes, A. F. (2013). Introduction to mediation, moderation, and conditional process analysis: A regression-based approach. New York: Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Iacobucci, D., Saldanha, N., & Deng, X. (2007). A meditation on mediation: Evidence that structural equations models perform better than regressions. Journal of Consumer Psychology, 17(2), 139–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1982). Variants of uncertainty. Cognition, 11(2), 143–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Khoo, J. (2014). Modal disagreements. Unpublished Manuscript. Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Retrieved August 29, 2014 from http://web.mit.edu/jkhoo/www/MD4.pdf.

  • Knobe, J., & Szabó, Z. G. (2013). Modals with a taste of the deontic. Semantics and Pragmatics, 6(1), 1–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J., & Yalcin, S. (2014). Epistemic modals and context: Experimental data. Semantics and Pragmatics, 7(11), 1–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, A. (1977). What must and can must and can mean. Linguistics and Philosophy, 1(3), 337–355.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1972). Naming and necessity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lagnado, D., & Sloman, S. A. (2004). Inside and outside probability judgments. In D. J. Koehler & N. Harvey (Eds.), Blackwell handbook of judgment & decision making (pp. 157–176). Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lassiter, D. (2011). Measurement and modality: The scalar basis of modal semantics. Ph.D. Thesis. New York University.

  • Lassiter, D. (2014). The weakness of must: In defense of a mantra. Proceedings of SALT, 24, 597–618.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1979). Scorekeeping in a language game. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 8(1), 339–359.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1996). Elusive knowledge. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74(4), 549–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacFarlane, J. (2011). Epistemic modals are assessment-sensitive. In A. Egan & B. Weatherson (Eds.), Epistemic modality (pp. 144–178). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E., & Stich, S. (2012). The role of experiment in the philosophy of language. In G. Russell & D. G. Fara (Eds.), The Routledge companion to the philosophy of language (pp. 495–512). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meek, C. (1997). Graphical models: Selecting causal and statistical models. Carnegie Mellon University.

  • Moore, C., Pure, K., & Furrow, D. (1990). Children’s understanding of the modal expression of speaker certainty and uncertainty and its relation to the development of a representational theory of mind. Child Development, 61(3), 722–730.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Papafragou, A. (2006). Epistemic modality and truth conditions. Lingua, 116(10), 1688–1702.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2011). Perspective in taste predicates and epistemic modals. In A. Egan & B. Weatherson (Eds.), Epistemic modality (pp. 179–226). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Stephenson, T. (2007). Judge dependence, epistemic modals, and predicates of personal taste. Linguistics and Philosophy, 30, 487–525.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J. (2016). A new paradigm for epistemology: From reliabilism to abilism. Ergo, 3(8), 189–231.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J. (ms). Knowledge attributions and lottery cases: A review and new evidence. University of Waterloo.

  • Turri, J., & Friedman, O. (2014). Winners and losers in the folk epistemology of lotteries. In J. R. Beebe (Ed.), Advances in experimental epistemology (pp. 45–69). London: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J., Friedman, O., & Keefner, A. (2017). Knowledge central: A central role for knowledge attributions in social evaluations. Quarterly journal of experimental psychology, 70(3), 504–515.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Unger, P. (1984). Philosophical relativity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Fintel, K., & Gillies, A. S. (2007). An opinionated guide to epistemic modality. In T. S. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Oxford studies in epistemology (Vol. 2, pp. 32–62). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Fintel, K., & Gillies, A. S. (2008). CIA Leaks. Philosophical Review, 117(1), 77–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Fintel, K., & Gillies, A. S. (2010). Must… stay… strong! Natural Language Semantics, 18(4), 351–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wells, G. L. (1992). Naked statistical evidence of liability: Is subjective probability enough? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 62(5), 739.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whitman, J. Q. (2008). The origins of reasonable doubt: Theological roots of the criminal trial. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yalcin, S. (2007). Epistemic modals. Mind, 116(464), 983–1026.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yalcin, S. (2011). Nonfactualism about epistemic modality. In A. Egan & B. Weatherson (Eds.), Epistemic modality (pp. 295–332). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

For helpful feedback and discussion, I thank James Beebe, Wesley Buckwalter, Ori Friedman, Joshua Knobe, Daniel Lassiter, Lisa Matthewson, Jonathan Phillips, David Rose, and Angelo Turri. Thanks also to anonymous reviewers for this journal. This research was supported by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada, the Ontario Ministry of Economic Development and Innovation, and the Canada Research Chairs program.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John Turri.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Turri, J. Epistemic Modals and Alternative Possibilities. Erkenn 83, 1063–1084 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-017-9929-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-017-9929-8

Navigation