Advertisement

Erkenntnis

, Volume 82, Issue 4, pp 819–836 | Cite as

An Argument for Shape Internalism

  • Jan Almäng
Original Research

Abstract

This paper is a defense of an internalist view of the perception of shapes. A basic assumption of the paper is that perceptual experiences have certain parts which account both for the phenomenal character associated with perceiving shapes—phenomenal shapes—and for the intentional content presenting shapes—intentional shapes. Internalism about perceptions of shapes is defined as the claim that phenomenal shapes determine the intentional shapes. Externalism is defined as the claim that perceptual experiences represent whatever shape the phenomenal shape reliably tracks. The argument against externalism proceeds in three steps. First, it is argued that phenomenal shapes are modality specific, such that a phenomenal shape that features in a visual perceptual experience cannot feature in a haptic perceptual experience, and vice versa. Second, it is argued that intentional shapes are amodal. Third, it is argued that externalism is incompatible with the fact that phenomenal shapes are modality specific and intentional shapes amodal.

Keywords

Perceptual Experience Visual Experience Phenomenal Character Intentional Content Haptic Perceptual Experience 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

References

  1. Bayne, T. (2010). The unity of consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Block, N. (1990). Inverted earth. Philosophical Perspectives, 4, 53–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Burge, T. (1986). Individualism and psychology. The Philosophical Review, 1986, 3–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Burge, T. (2010). Origins of objectivity. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Campbell, J. (1987). Is sense transparent? Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 88, 273–292.Google Scholar
  6. Chalmers, D. (2006). Perception and the fall from Eden. In T. S. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Perceptual experience (pp. 49–125). Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Crane, T. (2003). The intentional structure of consciousness. In Q. Smith & A. Jokic (Eds.), Consciousness. New philosophical perspectives. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  8. Evans, G. (1985). Collected papers. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  9. Farkas, K. (2003). What is externalism? Philosophical Studies, 112, 187–208.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Farkas, K. (2008). The subject’s point of view. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Fodor, J. (1983). The modularity of the mind. Cambridge: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  12. Gibson, J. J. (1933). Adaptation, after-effect and contrast in the perception of curved lines. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 16, 1–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Harman, G. (1990). The intrinsic quality of experience. Philosophical Perspectives, 4, 31–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Heller, M. (1983). A haptic dominance in form perception with blurred vision. Perception, 12, 607–613.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Hurley, S. (1998). Consciousness in action. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Husserl, E. (1901). Logische Untersuchungen. Zweiter Band. In U. Panzer (ed.), As repr. in Husserliana, vol. XIX/1 and XIX/2. The Hague: Nijhoff, 1975/1984.Google Scholar
  17. Martin, M. (2004). The limits of self-awareness. Philosophical Studies, 120, 37–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Meltzoff, A. N., & Borton, R. W. (1979). Intermodal matching by human neonates. Nature, 282, 403–404.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Meltzoff, A. N., & Moore, K. (1983). Newborn infants imitate adult facial gestures. Child Development, 54, 702–709.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Noë, A. (2004). Action in perception. Cambridge: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  21. Putnam, H. (1973). Meaning and reference. The Journal of Philosophy, 70, 699–711.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Rock, I., & Victor, J. (1964). Vision and touch. An experimentally created conflict between the two senses. Science, 143, 594–596.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Smith, A. D. (2000). Space and sight. Mind, 109, 481–518.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Smith, A. D. (2002). The problem of perception. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  25. Snowdon, P. (2005). The formulation of disjunctivism. A response to fish. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 105, 129–141.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Streri, A., & Gentaz, E. (2003). Cross-modal recognition of shape from hand to eyes in human newborns. Somatosensory and Motor Research, 20, 13–18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Thompson, B. (2010). The spatial content of experience. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 81, 146–184.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Tye, M. (2002). Representationalism and the transparency of experience. Noûs, 36, 137–151.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Welch, R. B., & Warren, D. H. (1980). Immediate perceptual response to intersensory discrepancy. Psychological Bulletin, 88, 638–667.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2016

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.ArvikaSweden

Personalised recommendations