Advertisement

Erkenntnis

, Volume 79, Supplement 6, pp 1129–1150 | Cite as

Knowledge and Approximate Knowledge

  • Lieven Decock
  • Igor Douven
  • Christoph Kelp
  • Sylvia Wenmackers
Original Article
  • 313 Downloads

Abstract

Traditionally, epistemologists have held that only truth-related factors matter in the question of whether a subject can be said to know a proposition. Various philosophers have recently departed from this doctrine by claiming that the answer to this question also depends on practical concerns. They take this move to be warranted by the fact that people’s knowledge attributions appear sensitive to contextual variation, in particular variation due to differing stakes. This paper proposes an alternative explanation of the aforementioned fact, one that allows us to stick to the orthodoxy. The alternative applies the conceptual spaces approach to the concept of knowledge. With knowledge conceived of spatially, the variability in knowledge attributions follows from recent work on identity, according to which our standards for judging things (including concepts) to be identical are context-dependent. On the proposal to be made, it depends on what is at stake in a context whether it is worth distinguishing between knowing and being at least close to knowing.

Keywords

Conceptual Space Knowledge Attribution Doxastic State Relevant Respect Justify True Belief 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

References

  1. Bach, K. (2005). The emperor’s new ‘knows’. In G. Preyer, & G. Peter (Eds.) Contextualism in philosophy (pp. 51–89). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Clark, A. (1993). Sensory qualities. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  3. Cobreros, P., Égré, P., Ripley, D., & van Rooij, R. (2012). Tolerant, classical, strict. Journal of Philosophical Logic 41, 347–385.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Cohen, S. (1987). Knowledge, context, and social standards. Synthese 73, 3–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Cohen, S. (1988). How to be a fallibilist. Philosophical Perspectives 2, 91–123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Cohen, S. (1999). Contextualism, skepticism, and the structure of reasons. Philosophical Perspectives 13, 57–89.Google Scholar
  7. Davis, W. (2007). Knowledge claims and context: Loose use. Philosophical Studies 132, 395–438.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Decock, L., & Douven, I. (2013). What is graded membership?. Noûs, in press.Google Scholar
  9. DeRose, K. (1992). Contextualism and knowledge attributions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52, 913–929.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. DeRose, K. (1995). Solving the sceptical puzzle. Philosophical Review 104, 1–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. DeRose, K. (1996), Knowledge, assertion, and lotteries. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74, 568–580.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Douven, I. (2004). The context-insensitivity of ‘Knowing More’ and ‘Knowing Better’. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 34, 313–326.Google Scholar
  13. Douven, I. (2008a). Underdetermination. In S. Psillos, M. Curd (Eds.) The routledge companion to the philosophy of science (pp. 292–301). London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  14. Douven, I. (2008b). Knowledge and practical reasoning. Dialectica 62, 101–118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Douven, I., Decock, L. (2010). Identity and similarity. Philosophical Studies 151, 59–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Edgington, D. (1997). Vagueness by degrees. In R. Keefe, P. Smith (Eds.) Vagueness: A Reader (pp. 294–316). Cambridge MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  17. Fantl, J., & McGrath, M. (2009). Knowledge in an uncertain world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Feldman, R. (2001). Skeptical problems, contextualist solutions. Philosophical Studies 103, 61–85.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Fitelson, B. (2003). A probabilistic theory of coherence. Analysis 63, 194–199.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Gärdenfors, P. (2000). Conceptual spaces. Cambridge MA: Bradford.Google Scholar
  21. Gärdenfors, P. (2007). Representing actions and functional properties in conceptual spaces. In T. Ziemke, J. Zlatev, R. M. Frank (Eds.) Body, language and mind (Vol. 1, pp. 167–195). Berlin: De Gruyter.Google Scholar
  22. Gärdenfors, P, & Warglien, M. (2011). Using concept spaces to model actions and events. Journal of Semantics (In press).Google Scholar
  23. Gärdenfors, P, & Zenker, F. (2011). Using conceptual spaces to model the dynamics of empirical theories. In: E. J., Olsson, S. Enqvist (Eds.), Belief revision meets philosophy of science (pp. 137–153). Berlin: Springer.Google Scholar
  24. Gärdenfors, P., Zenker, F. (2012). Theory change as dimensional change: Conceptual spaces applied to the dynamics of empirical theories. Synthese (In press).Google Scholar
  25. Goldman, A., Olsson, E. J. (2009). Reliabilism and the value of knowledge. In A. Haddock, A. Millar, & D. Pritchard (Eds.) Epistemic Value (pp. 19–41). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Grimm, S. R. (2011). On intellectualism in epistemology. Mind 120, 705–733.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Hawthorne, J. (2004). Knowledge and lotteries. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  28. Hazlett, A. (2010). The myth of factive verbs. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 80, 497–522.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Hetherington, S. (2001). Good knowledge, bad knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Hetherington, S. (2012) There can be lucky knowledge. In: M. Steup, J. Turri, E. Sosa (Eds.) Contemporary debates in epistemology. Oxford: Wiley–Blackwell (In press).Google Scholar
  31. Kennedy, C. (2007). Vagueness and grammar: The semantics of relative and absolute gradable adjectives. Linguistics and Philosophy 30, 1–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Klein, P. (2000). Contextualism and the real nature of academic skepticism. Philosophical Issues 10, 108–116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Kornblith, H. (2000). The contextualist evasion of epistemology. Philosophical Issues 10, 24–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Krecz, C. (1986). Parts and pieces. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 46, 381–400.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Krifka, M. (2002). Be brief and be vague. In: D. Restle, D. Zaefferer (Eds.), Sounds and systems: Studies in structure and change (pp. 439–458). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.Google Scholar
  36. Lewis, D. (1979). Scorekeeping in a language game. Journal of Philosophical Logic 8, 339–359.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Lewis, D. (1981). Causal decision theory. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 59, 5–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Lewis, D. (1996). Elusive knowledge. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74, 549–567.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Moore, G. E. (1962). Certainty. In: his Philosophical Papers (pp. 226–251). New York: Collier Books.Google Scholar
  40. Nagel, J., San Juan, V., Mar, R. (2013). Lay denial of knowledge for justified true beliefs. Cognition (In press).Google Scholar
  41. Oakley, I. T. (2001) A skeptic’s reply to Lewisian contextualism. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 31, 309–332.Google Scholar
  42. Oddie, G. (2007). “Truthlikeness,” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2008 Edition), available at http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/truthlikeness/.
  43. Olsson, E. J. (2002). What is the problem of coherence and truth?. Journal of Philosophy 94, 246–272.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Parfit, D. (1984) Reasons and persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  45. Radford, C. (1966). Knowledge—by examples. Analysis 27, 1–11.Google Scholar
  46. Rysiew, P. (2001). The context-sensitivity of knowledge attributions. Noûs 35, 477–514.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Sartwell, C. (1992). Why knowledge is merely true belief. Journal of Philosophy 89, 167–180.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Schiffer, S. (1996). Contextualist solutions to skepticism. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 96, 317–333.Google Scholar
  49. Smith, N. J. J. (2008). Vagueness and degrees of truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Sosa, E. (2000). Skepticism and contextualism. Philosophical Issues 10, 1–18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Stanley, J. (2005). Knowledge and practical interests. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. Starmans, C., Friedman, O. (2012). The folk conception of knowledge. Cognition 124, 272–283.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Starmans, C., Friedman, O. (2013). Taking ‘know’ for an answer: A reply to Nagel, San Juan, and Mar. Cognition (In press).Google Scholar
  54. Turri, J. (2012). Is knowledge justified true belief?. Synthese 184, 247–259.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  55. Unger, P. (1975). Ignorance: A case for scepticism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  56. van Deemter, K. (2010). Not exactly. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  57. Weirich, P. (2004). Realistic decision theory: Rules for nonideal agents in nonideal circumstances. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  58. Wiggins, D. (1980). Sameness and substance. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  59. Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  • Lieven Decock
    • 1
  • Igor Douven
    • 2
  • Christoph Kelp
    • 3
  • Sylvia Wenmackers
    • 2
  1. 1.Faculty of PhilosophyVU UniversityAmsterdamThe Netherlands
  2. 2.Faculty of PhilosophyUniversity of GroningenGroningenThe Netherlands
  3. 3.Institute of PhilosophyUniversity of LeuvenLeuvenBelgium

Personalised recommendations