Advertisement

Erkenntnis

, Volume 79, Issue 3, pp 593–623 | Cite as

Assessing Theories: The Coherentist Approach

  • Peter BrösselEmail author
Original Article

Abstract

In this paper we show that the coherence measures of Olsson (J Philos 94:246–272, 2002), Shogenji (Log Anal 59:338–345, 1999), and Fitelson (Log Anal 63:194–199, 2003) satisfy the two most important adequacy requirements for the purpose of assessing theories. Following Hempel (Synthese 12:439–469, 1960), Levi (Gambling with truth, New York, A. A. Knopf, 1967), and recently Huber (Synthese 161:89–118, 2008) we require, as minimal or necessary conditions, that adequate assessment functions favor true theories over false theories and true and informative theories over true but uninformative theories. We then demonstrate that the coherence measures of Olsson, Shogenji, and Fitelson satisfy these minimal conditions if we confront the hypotheses with a separating sequence of observational statements. In the concluding remarks we set out the philosophical relevance, and limitations, of the formal results. Inter alia, we discuss the problematic implications of our precondition that competing hypotheses must be confronted with a separating sequence of observational statements, which also leads us to discuss theory assessment in the context of scientific antirealism.

References

  1. Atkinson, D. (2012). Confirmation and justification. A commentary on Shogenji’s measure. Synthese, 184, 49–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Bovens, L., & Hartmann, S. (2003). Bayesian epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Brössel, P. (forthcoming). Correlation and truth. In V. Karakostas & D. Dieks (Ed.), Recent progress in philosophy of science: Perspectives and foundational problems. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
  4. Christensen, D. (1999). Measuring confirmation. Journal of Philosophy, 96, 437–461.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Carnap, R., & Bar-Hillel, Y. (1952). An outline of a theory of semantic information. Technical Report no. 247 Research Laboratory of Electronics, Massachusetts Institute of Technology.Google Scholar
  6. Crupi, V., Tentori, K., & Gonzalez, M. (2007). On Bayesian measures of evidential support: Theoretical and empirical issues. Philosophy of Science, 74, 229–252.Google Scholar
  7. Douven, I., & Meijs, W. (2007). Measuring coherence. Synthese, 156, 405–425.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Earman, J. (1992). Bayes or bust? A critical examination of Bayesian confirmation theory. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  9. Fitelson, B. (2001). Studies in Bayesian confirmation theory. PhD. Dissertation, University of Wisconsin-Madison (Philosophy).Google Scholar
  10. Fitelson, B. (2003). A probabilistic theory of coherence. Logic and Analysis, 63, 194–199.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Glass, D. (2007). Coherence measures and inference to the best explanation. Synthese, 157, 275–296.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Good, I. J. (1960). Weight of evidence, corroboration, explanatory power, information and the utility of experiments. Journal of the Royal Statistical Society. Series B (Methodological), 22, 319–331.Google Scholar
  13. Gaifman, H., & Snir, M. (1982). Probabilities over rich languages, testing, and randomness. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 47, 495–548.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Hawthorne, J. (2011). Confirmation theory. In P.S. Bandyopadhyay & M.R. Forster (Eds.), Handbook of philosophy of science, Vol. 7: Philosophy of statistics. Amsterdam: Elsevier.Google Scholar
  15. Hempel, C. G. (1960). Inductive inconsistencies. Synthese, 12, 439–469.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Hempel, C. G., & Oppenheim, P. (1948). Studies in the logic of explanation. in Aspects of scientific explanation and other essays in the philosophie of science, 1965, New York: Free Press, pp. 245–291.Google Scholar
  17. Hilpinen, R. (1970). On the information provided by observations. In J. Hintikka & P. Suppes (Eds.), Information and inference (pp. 97–123). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Hintikka, J. (1999). The varieties of information and scientific explanation. in jaakko hintikka selected papers, Vol. 5: Inquiry as inquiry: A logic of scientific discovery. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Hintikka, J., & Pietarinen, J. (1966). Semantic information and inductive logic. In J. Hintikka & P. Suppes (Eds.), Aspects of inductive logic (pp. 96–112). Amsterdam: North-Holland Publ. Comp.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Huber, F. (2008). Assessing theories, Bayes style. Synthese, 161, 89–118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Huber, F. (2005). What is the point of confirmation. Philosophy of Science, 72, 1146–1159.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Joyce, J. (1999). Foundations of causal decision theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Kemeny, J., & Oppenheim, P. (1952). Degrees of factual support. Philosophy of Science, 19, 307–324.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Levi, I. (1961). Decision theory and confirmation. The Journal of Philosophy, 58, 614–625.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Levi, I. (1967). Gambling with truth. New York: A. A. Knopf.Google Scholar
  26. Miller, D. (1974). Popper’s qualitative theory of verisimilitude. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 25, 166–177.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Olsson, E. (2002). What is the problem of coherence and truth. Journal of Philosophy, 94, 246–272.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Olsson, E. (2005). Against coherence: Truth, probability, and justification. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Popper, K. (1954). Degree of confirmation.. The British Journal of the Philosophy of Science, 5, 143–149.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Popper, K. (1968). The logic of scientific discovery. London: Hutchinson.Google Scholar
  31. Salmon, W. (2001). Reflections of a bashful Bayesian: A reply to Peter Lipton. In G. Hon & S. Rakover (Eds.), Explanation: Theoretical approaches and applications (pp. 121–136). Kluwer: Dordrecht.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Shogenji, T. (2012). The degree of epistemic justification and the conjunction fallacy. Synthese, 184, 29–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Shogenji, T. (1999). Is coherence truth conducive. Logic and Analysis, 59, 338–345.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Tichý, P. (1974). On popper’s definitions of verisimilitude. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 25, 155–160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Van Fraassen, B. C. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of Philosophy II, Center for Mind, Brain, and Cognitive EvolutionRuhr-University of BochumBochumGermany

Personalised recommendations