Advertisement

Erkenntnis

, Volume 79, Supplement 1, pp 155–172 | Cite as

Disagreement, Relativism and Doxastic Revision

  • J. Adam CarterEmail author
Article

Abstract

I investigate the implication of the truth-relativist’s alleged ‘faultless disagreements’ for issues in the epistemology of disagreement. A conclusion I draw is that the type of disagreement the truth-relativist claims (as a key advantage over the contextualist) to preserve fails in principle to be epistemically significant in the way we should expect disagreements to be in social-epistemic practice. In particular, the fact of faultless disagreement fails to ever play the epistemically significant role of making doxastic revision (at least sometimes) rationally required for either party in a (faultless) disagreement. That the truth-relativists’ disagreements over centred content fail to play this epistemically significant role that disagreements characteristically play in social epistemology should leave us sceptical that disagreement is what the truth-relativist has actually preserved.

Keywords

Epistemic Modal Knowledge Attribution Epistemic Possibility Conversational Context Personal Taste 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

References

  1. Baghramian, M. (forthcoming). The many faces of relativism. In V. Villa (Ed.), Il relativismo, Temi e prospettive.Google Scholar
  2. Brandom, R. (1983). Asserting. In Nous (Vol. 17, pp. 637–650). No. 4 (Nov., 1983).Google Scholar
  3. Cappelen, H., & Hawthorne, J. (2009). Relativism and monadic truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Christensen, D. (2007). Epistemology of disagreement: The good news. The Philosophical Review, 116, 187–217.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Cohnitz, D. Conceptual and faultless disagreements (draft).Google Scholar
  6. Conee, E. (2009). Peerage. Episteme, 6(3), 313–323.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. DeRose, K. (2004). Single scoreboard semantics. Philosophical Studies, 119, 1–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Dreier, J. (2009) Relativism (And Expressivism) and the problem of disagreement. In Philosophical perspectives, 23, Ethics.Google Scholar
  9. Egan, A. (2007). Epistemic modals, relativism and assertion. Philosphical Studies, 133, 1–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Egan, A. (2011). Relativism about epistemic modals. In S. Hales (Ed.), A companion to relativism: Blackwell companion to philosophy. Hoboken: Wiley.Google Scholar
  11. Egan, A., Hawthorne, J., & Weatherson, B. (2005). Epistemic modals in context. In Gerhard. Preyer & G. Peter (Eds.), Contextualism in philosophy: Knowledge, meaning and truth (pp. 131–170). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Egan, A., & Weatherson, B. (Eds.). (2011). Epistemic modality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  13. Elga, A. (2007). Reflection and disagreement. Nous, 41, 478–502.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Feldman, R. (2007a). Reasonable religious disagreement. In Louise. Antony (Ed.), Philosophers without God: Meditations on atheism and the secular life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  15. Feldman, R. (2007b). Epistemological puzzles about disagreement. In S. Hetherington (Ed.), Epistemology futures (pp. 216–236). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Feldman, R., & Warfield, T. (2010). Disagreement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  17. Francén, R. (2010). No deep disagreement for new relativists. Philosophical Studies, 151, 19–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Frances, B. (2009). The reflective episternic renegade. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 81(2), 419–463.Google Scholar
  19. Frances, B. (2012). Discovering disagreeing epistemic peers and superiors. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 20(1), 1–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Hawthorne, J. (2007). Eavesdroppers and epistemic modals. In Philosophical Issues 17, the metaphysics of epistemology.Google Scholar
  21. Kaplan, D. (1989). Demonstratives: An essay on the semantics, logic, metaphysics and epistemology of demonstratives and other indexicals. In J. Almog, J. Perry, & H. Wettstein (Eds.), Themes from Kaplan (pp. 481–566). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  22. Kelly, T. (2005). The epistemic significance of disagreement. In J. Hawthorne & T. S. Gendler (Eds.), Oxford studies in epistemology (Vol. 1). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  23. Kölbel, M. (2003). Faultless disagreement. In Proceedings of the Aristotelian society, New Series 104:53–73.Google Scholar
  24. Lackey, J. (2010). A justificationist view of disagreement’s epistemic significance. Social epistemology, 298–325.Google Scholar
  25. Lasersohn, P. (2005). Context dependence, disagreement, and predicates of personal taste. Linguistics and Philosophy, 28, 643–686.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Lewis, D. (1979). Scorekeeping in a language game. Journal of Philosohpical Logic, 8, 339–359.Google Scholar
  27. Lewis, D, (1980). Index, context, and content. In S. Kanger, & S. Öhman (Eds.), Philosophy and grammar. Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
  28. MacFarlane, J. (2003). Future contingents and relative truth. The philosophical quarterly, 53(212), 321–336. Google Scholar
  29. MacFarlane, J. (2005). The assessment sensitivity of knowledge attributions. In T. S. Gendler, & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Oxford studies in epistemology 1:197–233.Google Scholar
  30. MacFarlane, J. (2007). Relativism and disagreement. Philosophical Studies, 132, 17–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. MacFarlane, J. (2010). Relativism and knowledge attributions. In S. Bernecker & D. Pritchard (Eds.), Routledge companion to epistemology. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  32. Richard, M. (2004). Contextualism and relativism. Philosophical Studies, 119(1), 215–242.Google Scholar
  33. Stephenson, T. (2007). Judge dependence, epistemic modals, and predicates of personal taste. Linguistics and Philosophy, 30, 487–525.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Stojanovic, I. (2007). Talking about taste: Disagreement, implicit arguments, and relative truth. Linguistics and Philosophy, 30(2007), 691–706.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Sundell, T. (2011). Disagreements about taste. Philosophical Studies, 155(2011), 267–288.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. van Inwagen, P. (1996). Is It Wrong, Everywhere, Always, and for Anyone to Believe Anything on Insufficient Evidence? In J. Jeff & H. S. Daniel (Eds.), Faith, Freedom, and Rationality. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
  37. Weatherson, B. (2009). Conditionals and indexical relativism. Synthese, 166(2), 333–357.Google Scholar
  38. Wright, C. (2007). New age relativism and epistemic possibility: The question of evidence. Philosophical Issues, 17(1), 262–283.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Philosophy and Ethics, School of Innovation SciencesEindhoven University of TechnologyEindhovenThe Netherlands

Personalised recommendations