Erkenntnis

, Volume 76, Issue 3, pp 373–394 | Cite as

Univocal Reasoning and Inferential Presuppositions

Original Article

Abstract

I pursue an answer to the psychological question “what is it for S to presuppose that p?” I will not attempt a general answer. Rather, I will explore a particular kind of presuppositions that are constituted by the mental act of reasoning: Inferential presuppositions. Indeed, I will consider a specific kind of inferential presuppositions—one that is constituted by a specific reasoning competence: The univocality competence. Roughly, this is the competence that reliably governs the univocal thought-components’ operation as univocal in a line of reasoning. I will argue that the exercise of this reasoning competence constitutes certain inferential presuppositions. More specifically, I outline a conception of an inferential presupposition as a non-attitudinal but genuinely psychological and rationally committing relation that holds between a reasoner and a proposition. Thus, inferential presuppositions may be distinguished from tacit or standing attitudes that function as premise-beliefs in reasoning. Likewise inferential presuppositions may be distinguished from other kinds of presuppositions. In conclusion, I note some features of inferential presuppositions that bear on the epistemology of inference.

References

  1. Boghossian, P. (1992). Externalism and inference. Philosophical issues, 2, Rationality in Epistemology, pp. 11–28.Google Scholar
  2. Boghossian, P. (1994). The transparency of mental content. Philosophical perspectives, 8, Logic and Language, pp. 33–50.Google Scholar
  3. Boghossian, P. (Forthcoming). The transparency of mental content revisited. Philosophical studies. Google Scholar
  4. Brown, J. (2004). Anti-individualism and knowledge. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  5. Burge, T. (1988). Individualism and self-knowledge. Journal of Philosophy, 85(11), 649–663.Google Scholar
  6. Burge, T. (1996). Our entitlement to self-knowledge. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 96, 91–116.Google Scholar
  7. Burge, T. (2003). Perceptual entitlement. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 67, 503–548.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Burge, T. (2005). Disjunctionism and perceptual psychology. Philosophical Topics, 33(1), 1–78.Google Scholar
  9. Burge, T. (2009) Five theses on de re states and attitudes. In J. Almog & P. Leonardi (Eds.), The Philosophy of David Kaplan. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Camp, J. L. (2002). Confusion: A study in the theory of knowledge. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  11. Campbell, J. (1987). Is sense transparent? Aristotelian society supplementary volume LXI, pp. 273–292.Google Scholar
  12. Campbell, J. (2002). Reference and consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  13. Evans, J. S. B. T. (1998). Matching bias in conditional reasoning: Do we understand it after 25 years? Thinking and Reasoning, 4(1), 45–110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Evans, J. S. B. T. (2003). In two minds: dual-process accounts of reasoning. TRENDS in Cognitive Sciences, 7(10), 454–459.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Gerken, M. (2007a). Epistemic reasoning and the mental. UCLA Dissertation.Google Scholar
  16. Gerken, M. (2007b). A false dilemma for anti-individualism. American Philosophical Quarterly, 44(4), 329–342.Google Scholar
  17. Gerken, M. (2009). Conceptual equivocation and epistemic relevance. Dialectica, 63(2), 117–132.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Gerken, M. (2011): Conceptual equivocation and warrant by reasoning. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, Published online, June 4th 2010.Google Scholar
  19. Gerken, M. (Forthcoming). Internalism and externalism in the epistemology of testimony. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.Google Scholar
  20. Kaplan, D. (1989). Demonstratives. In J. Almog, et al. (Eds.), Themes from Kaplan. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  21. Kaplan, D. (1991). Words. Proceedings of Aristotelian Society Supplementary, 69, 93–119.Google Scholar
  22. Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and necessity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  23. Lawlor, K. (2001). New thoughts about old things: Cognitive policies as the ground of singular concepts. New York: Garland Publishing.Google Scholar
  24. Lawlor, K. (2005). Confused thought and modes of presentation. The Philosophical Quarterly, 55(218), 21–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Lawlor, K. (2007). A notational worlds approach to confusion. Mind and Language, 22(2), 150–172.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Millikan, R. (1993). On mentalese orthography. In White queen psychology and other essays for Alice. A Bradford Book. Cambridge: The MIT Press, pp. 103–122.Google Scholar
  27. Millikan, R. (1997). Images of identity. Mind, 106, 499–519.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Millikan, R. (2000). On clear and confused concepts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Oaksford, M., & Chater, N. (2009). Precis of Bayesian rationality: The probabilistic approach to human reasoning. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 32, 69–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Over, D. E. (2009). New paradigm psychology of reasoning. Thinking and Reasoning, 15(4), 431–438.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Stalnaker, R. (1973). Presuppositions. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 2, 447–457.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Stalnaker, R. (2008). Our knowledge of the internal world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Stalnaker, R. (Forthcoming). Responses to Stoljar, Weatherson and Boghossian. Philosophical Studies.Google Scholar
  34. Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of CopenhagenCopenhagenDenmark

Personalised recommendations