Skip to main content
Log in

Misleading Appearances: Searle on Assertion and Meaning

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

John Searle’s philosophy of language contains a notorious tension between a literalist view on the relationship between sentences and their meanings, and what—at the first glance—appears to be a virulent defence of contextualism. Appearances notwithstanding, Searle’s views on background and meaning are closer to literalism than to contextualism. Searle defines assertion in terms of the commitment to the truth of the propositional content. In absence of an independent criterion to delimit the asserted content, such a definition overgenerates—hence Searle’s commitment to literalism. His position is untenable—and this is the general lesson of the paper—, because sentence meaning cannot be used to determine the asserted content.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Usual qualifications must be made for a restricted set of indexicals, whose linguistic meaning requires a contextual parameter for the assignation of semantic content.

  2. I owe this example to an anonymous referee.

  3. This problem is related to the old question of Quine’s ‘eternal’ sentences; for a discussion, see, for instance, Recanati (1994).

  4. Searle is quite inconsistent on this topic. In Searle (1983, chapter 5), he distinguishes the background of implicit know-hows from the network of intentional states such as beliefs. In Searle (1992, Chap. 8) he includes the network of intentional states within the background. Yet, Searle (2001) gets back to affirming that the background is not propositional.

  5. Restricting the discussion to declarative sentences and to assertions.

  6. Searle and Vanderveken (1985) propose a slightly different description of the structure of speech acts. Every illocutionary act is defined (a) by its illocutionary point; (b) the mode of achievement of the illocutionary point; (c) the degree of strength of the illocutionary point; (d) propositional content conditions; (e) preparatory conditions; (f) sincerity conditions; (g) the degree of strength of the sincerity conditions. The illocutionary point is equivalent to Searle’s essential condition—it is “the purpose which is internal to [the utterance’s] being an act of that type” (Searle and Vanderveken 1985, p. 37). The illocutionary point of an assertion is to represent an actual state of the world. Since assertions have no specific mode of achievement, no specific conditions on propositional content conditions and that the degrees of strength of their illocutionary point and of their sincerity conditions are neuter (Searle and Vanderveken 1985, p. 183), we can safely use Searle’s (1969) more informal presentation.

  7. A reviewer pointed out that Searle does not “accept abstract propositions that are expressed by some sentences, or some utterances […]. He thinks that propositional acts are abstract components of some illocutionary acts, or, perhaps, are some illocutionary acts abstractly considered.” This is correct; actually, it reinforces the point to be made below, i.e. that the Principle of Expressibility, under its strongest interpretation, applies to speech acts.

  8. Or, in case of ellipsis, onto a constituent of the non-elliptical cognate of the uttered sentence. Note that if, as claimed by Stainton (1998, 2005), there are genuinely sub-sentential assertions—irreducible to syntactic ellipsis—Alston’s solution would face an important obstacle.

  9. While Searle (1983) maintains that representing intentional states amounts to performing illocutionary acts, he also emphasises that the intention to represent an intentional state is conceptually distinct from communicating that representation.

References

  • Alston, W. P. (2000). Illocutionary acts and sentence meaning. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen, H., & Lepore, E. (2005). Insensitive semantics. A defense of semantic minimalism and speech act pluralism. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carston, R. (1988). Implicature, explicature and truth-theoretic semantics. In R. M. Kempson (Ed.), Mental representations. The interface between language and reality (pp. 155–181). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carston, R. (2002). Thoughts and utterances. The pragmatics of explicit communication. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cruse, D. A. (1986). Lexical semantics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kissine, M. (2007). The fallacy of semantic minimalism. Facta Philosophica, 19, 23–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kissine, M. (forthcoming) From contexts to circumstances of evaluation: is the trade-off always innocous? Synthese. doi:10.1007/s11229-010-9727-1.

  • Recanati, F. (1987). Meaning and force. The pragmatics of performative utterances. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (1994). Contextualism and anti-contextualism in the philosophy of language. In S. Tsohatzidis (Ed.), Foundations of speech act theory. Philosophical and linguistic perspectives (pp. 156–166). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (2001). Déstabliser le sens. Revue internationale de philosophie, 216(2), 197–208.

    Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (2003). The limits of expressibility. In B. Smith (Ed.), John Searle (pp. 189–213). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (2004). Literal meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1969). Speech acts. An essay in the philosophy of language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1978). Literal meaning. Erkenntnis, 13, 207–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1980). The background of meaning. In J. R. Searle, F. Kiefer, & M. Bierwisch (Eds.), Speech act theory and pragmatics (pp. 221–232). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1983). Intentionality. An essay in philosophy of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1992). The rediscovery of the mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (2001). Unstable meanings, stable communication. Reply to Recanati. Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 2, 284–286.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (2007). What is language: Some preliminary remarks. In I. Kecskes & L. R. Horn (Eds.), Explorations in Pragmatics. Linguistic, cognitive and intercultural aspects (pp. 7–37). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R., & Vanderveken, D. (1985). Foundations of illocutionary logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soames, S. (2002). Beyond rigidity. The unfinished semantic agenda of ‘Naming and Necessity’. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, D., & Wilson, D. (1995). Relevance. Communication and cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stainton, R. J. (1998). Quantifier phrases, meaningfulness “in isolation”, and ellipsis. Linguistics and Philosophy, 21(3), 311–340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stainton, R. J. (2005). In defense of non-sential assertion. In Z. G. Szabó (Ed.), Semantics versus Pragmatics (pp. 383–457). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2005). “Review of “Literal Meaning”, François Recanati.” Notre-Dame Philosophical Reviews (ndpr.nd.edu).

  • Vanderveken, D. (2005). Success, satisfaction and truth in speech acts and formal semantics. In S. Davis & B. S. Gillon (Eds.), Semantics. A reader (pp. 710–734). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1989). On certainty. Oxford: Blackwell.

Download references

Acknowledgments

I’m extremely grateful to Marc Dominicy for his detailed remarks on a previous draft. Two anonymous referees for this journal provided insightful criticisms that helped me to improve this paper considerably. My research is supported by a post-doctoral researcher grant from the Fonds de la Recherche Scientifique de la Communauté Française de Belgique (F.R.S.-FNRS). The results presented here are also part of the research carried out within the scope of the ARC project 06/11-342 Culturally modified organisms: “What it means to be human” in the age of culture, funded by the Ministère de la Communauté française—Direction générale de l’Enseignement non obligatoire et de la Recherche scientifique.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mikhail Kissine.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Kissine, M. Misleading Appearances: Searle on Assertion and Meaning. Erkenn 74, 115–129 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-010-9229-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-010-9229-z

Keywords

Navigation