Abstract
The current deconstruction of paradoxes is one among several signs that a profound renewal of methods for clinical and epidemiological research is taking place; perhaps for some basic life sciences as well. The new methodological approaches have already deconstructed and explained long puzzling apparent paradoxes, including the (non-existent) benefits of obesity in diabetics, or of smoking in low birth weight. Achievements of the new methods also comprise the elucidation of the causal structure of long-disputed and highly complex questions, as Berkson’s bias and Simpson’s paradox, and clarifying reasons for deep controversies, as those on estrogens and endometrial cancer, or on adverse effects of hormone replacement therapy. These are signs that the new methods can go deeper and beyond the methods in current use. A major example of a highly relevant idea is: when we condition on a common effect of a pair of variables, then a spurious association between such pair is likely. The implications of these ideas are potentially vast. A substantial number of apparent paradoxes may simply be the result of collider biases, a source of selection bias that is common not just in epidemiologic research, but in many types of research in the health, life, and social sciences. The new approaches develop a new framework of concepts and methods, as collider, instrumental variables, d-separation, backdoor path and, notably, Directed Acyclic Graphs (DAGs). The current theoretical and methodological renewal—or, perhaps, “revolution”—may be changing deeply how clinical and epidemiological research is conceived and performed, how we assess the validity and relevance of findings, and how causal inferences are made. Clinical and basic researchers, among others, should get acquainted with DAGs and related concepts.
This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution.


References
Al-Khalili J. Paradox: the nine greatest enigmas in physics. New York: Random House; 2012.
Glymour MM, Greenland S. Causal diagrams. In: Rothman KJ, Greenland S, Lash TL, editors. Modern epidemiology. 3rd ed. Philadelphia: Lippincott-Raven; 2008. p. 183–209.
Porta M, editor. A dictionary of epidemiology. 6th ed. New York: Oxford University Press; 2014.
Dixon JB, Egger GJ. A narrow view of optimal weight for health generates the obesity paradox. Am J Clin Nutr. 2014;99:969–70.
Pearl J. Causality: models, reasoning and inference. 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 2009.
Hernán MA, Robins JM. Causal inference. New York: Chapman & Hall/CRC; 2015. http://www.hsph.harvard.edu/miguel-hernan/causal-inference-book.
Greenland S, Pearl J, Robins JM. Causal diagrams for epidemiologic research. Epidemiology. 1999;10:37–48.
Robins JM. Data, design, and background knowledge in etiologic inference. Epidemiology. 2001;12:313–20.
Hernán MA, Hernández-Díaz S, Werler MM, Mitchell AA. Causal knowledge as a prerequisite for confounding evaluation: an application to birth defects epidemiology. Am J Epidemiol. 2002;155:176–84.
Hernández-Díaz S, Schisterman EF, Hernán MA. The birth weight ‘‘paradox’’ uncovered? Am J Epidemiol. 2006;164:1115–20.
Hernández-Díaz S, Wilcox AJ, Schisterman EF, Hernán MA. From causal diagrams to birth weight-specific curves of infant mortality. Eur J Epidemiol. 2008;23:163–6.
Snoep JD, Morabia A, Hernández-Díaz S, Hernán MA, Vandenbroucke JP. A structural approach to Berkson’s fallacy and a guide to a history of opinions about it. Int J Epidemiol. 2014;43:515–21.
Greenland S. Quantifying biases in causal models: classical confounding vs. collider-stratification bias. Epidemiology. 2003;14:300–6.
Cole SR, Platt RW, Schisterman EF, et al. Illustrating bias due to conditioning on a collider. Int J Epidemiol. 2010;39:417–20.
VanderWeele TJ. Explanation in causal inference: methods for mediation and interaction. New York: Oxford University Press; 2015.
Lee DH, Porta M, Jacobs DR, Vandenberg LN. Chlorinated persistent organic pollutants, obesity, and type 2 diabetes. Endocr Rev. 2014;35:557–601.
Richiardi L, Barone-Adesi F, Merletti F, Pearce N. Using directed acyclic graphs to consider adjustment for socioeconomic status in occupational cancer studies. J Epidemiol Community Health. 2008;62:e14.
Pearce N, Richiardi L. Three worlds collide: Berkson’s bias, selection bias and collider bias. Int J Epidemiol. 2014;43:521–4.
Lajous M, Banack HR, Kaufman JS, Hernán MA. Should patients with chronic disease be told to gain weight? The obesity paradox and selection bias. Am J Med. 2015;128:334–6.
Porta M. The deconstruction of paradoxes, and a methodological revolution in clinical and epidemiological research. OUPblog (Oxford University Press Blog). 2014. http://blog.oup.com/2014/10/deconstruction-paradoxes-sociology-epidemiology/.
Pearl J. Are economists smarter than epidemiologists? Comments on Imbens’s recent paper. Causal analysis in theory and practice [Blog]. 2014. http://www.mii.ucla.edu/causality/?p=1241.
Joffe M, Gambhir M, Chadeau-Hyam M, Vineis P. Causal diagrams in systems epidemiology. Emerg Themes Epidemiol. 2012;9(1):1.
Aalen O, Røysland K, Gran J, Kouyos R, Lange T. Can we believe the DAGs? A comment on the relationship between causal DAGs and mechanisms. Stat Methods Med Res. 2014. http://smm.sagepub.com/content/early/2014/03/27/0962280213520436.full.pdf+html.
Bolúmar F, Porta M. Epidemiologic methods: beyond clinical medicine, beyond epidemiology. Eur J Epidemiol. 2004;19:733–5.
Vineis P, Stringhini S, Porta M. The environmental roots of non-communicable diseases (NCDs) and the epigenetic impacts of globalization. Environ Res. 2014;133:424–30.
Hernán MA. Agent-based models for causal inference—reweighting data and theory in epidemiology. Am J Epidemiol. 2015;181:103–5.
Geneletti SG, Gallo V, Porta M, Khoury MJ, Vineis P. Assessing causal relationships in genomics: from Bradford-Hill criteria to complex gene-environment interactions and directed acyclic graphs. Emerg Themes Epidemiol. 2011;8:5. http://www.ete-online.com/content/8/1/5.
Krieger N. Epidemiology and the people’s health. New York: Oxford University Press. Theory and Context; 2011.
Smith GD. Epidemiology, epigenetics and the ‘Gloomy Prospect’: embracing randomness in population health research and practice. Int J Epidemiol. 2011;40:537–62.
Richmond RC, Al-Amin A, Davey Smith G, Relton C. Approaches for drawing causal inferences from epidemiological birth cohorts: a review. Early Hum Dev. 2014;90:769–80.
Vineis P, Porta M. Causal thinking, biomarkers and mechanisms of carcinogenesis. J Clin Epidemiol. 1996;49:951–6.
Greenland S, Mansournia MA. Limitations of individual causal models, causal graphs, and ignorability assumptions, as illustrated by random confounding and design unfaithfulness. Eur J Epidemiol. 2015;. doi:10.1007/s10654-015-9995-7.
Glass TA, Goodman SN, Hernán MA, Samet JM. Causal inference in public health. Annu Rev Public Health. 2013;34:61–75.
VanderWeele TJ, Vansteelandt S, Robins JM. Marginal structural models for sufficient cause interactions. Am J Epidemiol. 2010;1717:506–14.
Robins JM, Hernán MA, Brumbach B. Marginal structural models and causal inference in epidemiology. Epidemiology. 2000;11:550–60.
Van der Weele TJ, Hernán MA. From counterfactuals to sufficient component causes and vice versa. Eur J Epidemiol. 2006;21:855–8.
Hernán MA, Robins JM. Instruments for causal inference: an epidemiologist’s dream? Epidemiology. 2006;17:360–72.
Tong S, Neale RE, Shen X, Olsen J. Challenges for epidemiologic research on the verge of a new era. Eur J Epidemiol. 2011;26:689–94.
Joffe M, Mindell J. Complex causal process diagrams for analyzing the health impacts of policy interventions. Am J Public Health. 2006;96:473–9.
Pearce N. Epidemiology in a changing world: variation, causation and ubiquitous risk factors. Int J Epidemiol. 2011;40:503–12.
Wilcox A. On the importance—and the unimportance—of birthweight. Int J Epidemiol. 2001;30:1233–41.
Victora CG, Huttly SR, Fuchs SC, Olinto MT. The role of conceptual frameworks in epidemiological analysis: a hierarchical approach. Int J Epidemiol. 1997;26:224–7.
Rundle A, Ahsan H, Vineis P. Better cancer biomarker discovery through better study design. Eur J Clin Invest. 2012;42(12):1350–9.
Mansournia MA, Hernán MA, Greenland S. Matched designs and causal diagrams. Int J Epidemiol. 2013;42:860–9.
Preston SH, Stokes A. Obesity paradox: conditioning on disease enhances biases in estimating the mortality risks of obesity. Epidemiology. 2014;25:454–61.
Renehan AG. The ‘obesity paradox’ and survival after colorectal cancer: true or false? Cancer Causes Control. 2014;25:1419–22.
Banack HR, Kaufman JS. The obesity paradox: understanding the effect of obesity on mortality among individuals with cardiovascular disease. Prev Med. 2014;62:96–102.
Moga DC, Abner EL, Brouwer ES. Dementia and “obesity paradox”: Is this for real or are we missing something? An epidemiologist’s perspective. J Am Med Dir Assoc. 2015;16:78–9.
Niedziela J, Hudzik B, Niedziela N, Gąsior M, Gierlotka M, Wasilewski J, et al. The obesity paradox in acute coronary syndrome: a meta-analysis. Eur J Epidemiol. 2014;29:801–12.
Röhrig N, Strobl R, Müller M, Perz S, Kääb S, Martens E, et al. Directed acyclic graphs helped to identify confounding in the association of disability and electrocardiographic findings: results from the KORA-Age study. J Clin Epidemiol. 2014;67:199–206.
Hernán MA. The hazards of hazard ratios. Epidemiology. 2010;21:13–5.
Hernán MA, Hernández-Diaz S, Robins JM. A structural approach to selection bias. Epidemiology. 2004;15:615–25.
Porta M, Vandenbroucke JP, Ioannidis JPA, Sanz S, Fernandez E, Bhopal R, et al. Trends in citations to books on epidemiological and statistical methods in the biomedical literature. PLoS ONE. 2013;8(5):e61837.
Chiolero A, Kaufman JS. Metabolic mediators of body-mass index and cardiovascular risk. Lancet. 2014;383:2042.
Dahabreh IJ, Kitsios GD, Trikalinos TA, Kent DM. The complexity of ABO in coronary heart disease. Lancet. 2011;377:1493.
Hernán MA, Clayton D, Keiding N. The Simpson’s paradox unraveled. Int J Epidemiol. 2011;40:780–5.
Hernán MA, Alonso A, Logan R, Grodstein F, Michels KB, Willett WC, et al. Observational studies analyzed like randomized experiments: an application to postmenopausal hormone therapy and coronary heart disease. Epidemiology. 2008;19:766–79.
Lipsitch M, Tchetgen E, Cohen T. Negative controls. A tool for detecting confounding and bias in observational studies. Epidemiology. 2010;21:383–8.
Pearce N, Blair A, Vineis P, Ahrens W, Andersen A, Antó JM, et al. IARC monographs: 40 years of evaluating carcinogenic hazards to humans. Environ Health Perspect. 2015;123:507–14.
Hamra GB, Guha N, Cohen A, Laden F, Raaschou-Nielsen O, Samet JM, et al. Outdoor particulate matter exposure and lung cancer: a systematic review and meta-analysis. Environ Health Perspect. 2014;122:906–11.
VanderWeele TJ. Mediation and mechanism. Eur J Epidemiol. 2009;24:217–24.
Porta M, Álvarez-Dardet C. Epidemiology: bridges over (and across) roaring levels. J Epidemiol Community Health. 1998;52:605.
Espina C, Porta P, Schüz J, Hernández-Aguado I, Percival RV, Dora C, et al. Environmental and occupational interventions for primary prevention of cancer: a cross-sectorial policy framework. Environ Health Perspect. 2013;121:420–6.
Acknowledgments
We thank Julia del Amo, Arnaud Chiolero, Cesar Victora and three anonymous reviewers for insightful comments to earlier versions of the manuscript. The work was supported in part by research Grants from Instituto de Salud Carlos III—FEDER (FIS PI13/00020 and CIBER de Epidemiología y Salud Pública—CIBERESP), Government of Spain; Fundació La Marató de TV3 (20132910); and Government of Catalonia (2014 SGR 1012).
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Porta, M., Vineis, P. & Bolúmar, F. The current deconstruction of paradoxes: one sign of the ongoing methodological “revolution”. Eur J Epidemiol 30, 1079–1087 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10654-015-0068-8
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10654-015-0068-8
Keywords
- Paradox
- Methods
- Clinical research
- Causal inference
- Collider
- Directed Acyclic Graphs (DAGs)