INTRODUCTION

It is indeed an ‘unfortunate truism’ that the environment is jeopardised and harmed during armed hostilities and conflict situations,Footnote 1 and reduced to ‘a silent casualty of war’.Footnote 2 This exclusive perception still has a firm and rigid grounding in the ubiquitous understanding of ‘harm’. The international reaction to Russia’s invasion of Ukraine exemplifies the secondary treatment of the environment, still deeply entrenched in the utilitarian vision of nature. Alongside the direct toll on civilian life, the aggression has led to many far-reaching environmental abuses: for instance, the seizure of the Chernobyl nuclear disaster site has mobilised ‘radioactive dust’ and increased ‘detectable radiation [that] may spread radioactive material into new areas’.Footnote 3 As the conflict is of an international nature (‘IAC’), termed the ‘first-ever occasion’ for Article 8(2)(b)(iv) of the Rome Statute (‘Statute’),Footnote 4 there is a chance, although slight, that environmental wrongs will finally reach the attention of the International Criminal Court (‘ICC’ or ‘Court’).Footnote 5 Yet, the value of that precedent remains contentious. The first obstacle is set by the excessively high threshold of Article 8(2)(b)(iv) of the Statute, limiting its application to incidental and chimerical instances of mass environmental damage whilst excluding the majority of recent and current conflicts that are non-international (‘NIACs’) or diffusive in nature.Footnote 6 The stark absence of an equivalent peacetime and NIAC provision and the dubious prospects of creating a special international court for the environment (‘ICE’)Footnote 7 has caused many,Footnote 8 including the Independent Expert Panel for the Legal Definition of Ecocide (‘IEPLDE’)Footnote 9 and the Promise Institute for Human Rights (‘UCLA’) Group of Experts,Footnote 10 to advocate the expansion of the ICC’s jurisdiction over the gravest instances of environmental degradation. This discussion challenges the current ambitions. Although the case for the development of an autonomous international crime prohibiting mass environmental damage is meritorious and warrants attention, it seems to neglect the second and more fundamental obstacle precluding the prompt and smooth translation of environmental harm into the language of the ICC: the sui generis nature of the Court. The enduring theme of modern international criminal law (‘ICL’) remains the protection of humanity; one should not be ‘pushing too far too fast in trying to turn the ICC into more than its language clearly states’.Footnote 11 International environmental law (‘IEL’) is an unparalleled field of international law driven by its own peculiar technicalities, objectives, and narratives, which deserve individual and separate treatment. Although its normative development ‘has come a long way from ‘limited/utilitarian’ concerns to ‘common concerns of humankind’,Footnote 12 still, as shown above, environmental concerns do not attract much attention causing IEL to develop at the intersection of other sub-divisions of international law. Whilst recognising IEL’s intrinsic fragility, international courts and tribunals (‘ICTs’) have gradually taken a more ‘welcoming’ approach towards environmental matters, analysing their institutional frameworks from a plurality of perspectives and evaluating them in the context of a variety of cross-sectoral norms of international law.Footnote 13 In this spirit and without risking a too hasty adaptation of the law to a new set of rules, the fundamental premise advanced here is that the ICC should align itself to the ‘reinforcing technique’, reading environmental norms into its substantive statutory provisions. The lack of a specific environmental provision applicable in peacetime and NIAC ‘could actually be an advantage when exploring ways in which existing provisions could be more purposively interpreted’.Footnote 14 The ultimate challenge on the side of the ICC would be to ‘strike the right balance between environmental protection and the integrity’ of ICL,Footnote 15 being cautious of the fact that its practice can go both ways: ‘it could be inhibiting or facilitating legal development’.Footnote 16 With jurisdiction over the most serious crimes of international law, the ICC, being ‘a constitutional development’,Footnote 17 can influence and mould the behaviour of individual States and draw policy attention. On that approach, and within the understanding of complementarity,Footnote 18 the ICC would not substituteFootnote 19 but enhance the capacity of domestic authorities themselves to take action.

The discussion begins by analysing several possibilities for intersection and principal conflict points between ICL and IEL. The goal is not to provide definitive answers to every issue but to highlight major practical and conceptual impediments precluding the ICC from effectively accommodating instances of mass environmental harm without unbalancing its institutional framework. Whilst directly recognising all these challenges, the second section presents two options via which the ICC could optimise its current ‘environmental’ potential. Through the prism of environmental justice, the Court’s organs could purposely: (i) translate environmental realities into the substantive provisions of the ICC, and (ii) take advantage of the breadth of Articles 21(3) and 7(1)(h) of the Statute and manoeuvre their further development in a more environmentally sensitive direction. Such an approach, however, is not free of limitations. Apart from objectifying the environment, this indirect strategy towards broader environmental protection can result in a ‘bifurcated’ or ‘selective’ safety net with some natural components considered more worthwhile than others. A further argument against this expansionist rhetoric towards reducing the ‘impunity gap’ refers to the fact that it carries the danger of unbridledly enlarging the ambit of the ICC, which might result in trivializing the ICC and ultimately swamping its operations. It would ultimately depend on the Court itself to weigh the arguments in favour and against ‘greening’ its current framework and to adjudge the types of environmental damage deserving international attention and condemnation. Although the proposed solutions might be considered conservative, it is a sincere attempt to bring forward the insuperable truth: the current substantive disconnect between ICL and IEL precludes the ICC from taking a more radical stance on environmental protection. Until one attains a closer reconciliation between them and instead of detracting from the present attention by elaborate designs for amendment, one should not underestimate the power of simply relying on the existing statutory framework.

THE TERM ‘ECOCIDE’

For the purposes of this essay, the terms ‘ecocide’ and ‘mass environmental degradation’ are used interchangeably.

The idea of creating an international crime of ‘ecocide’ is not a novel concept as it dates back to the 1970s. The idea initially arose during the Vietnam War when the US military infamously used ‘Agent Orange’, a toxic herbicide, as a tool of chemical warfare in Vietnam. The term was first used publicly by the plant biologist Arthur Galston to encapsulate what he described as ‘wilful, permanent destruction of environments in which people can live in a manner of their choosing’.Footnote 21 Due to the lack of substantive and enforcement jurisdiction of the post-WW2 criminal tribunals over crimes against the environment, the first 1954 Draft Code of Offences against the Peace and Security of Mankind (‘Draft Code’)Footnote 22 did not include any new crimes not mentioned in the Nuremberg Principles.Footnote 23 Only in 1995, throughout the revision process of its Draft Code, did the International Law Commission (‘ILC’) take the initiative in criminalising offences against the environment on the international level. Despite environmental crimes finding their place in Article 26 of the Draft Code,Footnote 24 during the second reading ILC’s Chairman unilaterally decided to remove mass environmental degradation entirely as a separate provision, without any recorded justification and most likely because of pressure from the nuclear lobby and a few States.Footnote 25 As ‘an offshoot’ of the ILC’s Draft Code,Footnote 26 the final and current position of environmental protection remains ‘a far cry’ from the other provisions included in the Statute remains.Footnote 27 In its current form, Article 8(2)(b)(iv) of the Statute prohibits ‘[i]ntentionally launching an attack in the knowledge that such attack will cause (…) widespread, long-term and severe damage to the natural environment which would be clearly excessive in relation to the concrete and direct overall military advantage anticipated’. Thus, the provision limits the level of lawful destruction by the ‘ceiling’ of environmental degradation established by the absolute prohibition of ‘widespread, long-term, and severe damage to the natural environment’.Footnote 28 At first glance, the advance seems to have the potency to punish wartime environmental damage, but the cumulative threshold for operation—‘widespread’, ‘long-term’, and ‘severe’—is widely considered too high and ultimately provides little or no protection to the environment.Footnote 29 Despite being termed the ‘first genuinely ecocentric war crime’,Footnote 30 by requiring the damage to be ‘clearly excessive’, the provision is tied to instances of incidental environmental harm balanced against ‘the concrete and direct overall military advantage anticipated’.Footnote 31 As further discussed below, such a balanced approach to environmental protection is indifferent to the logic of IEL, the exercise of striking a careful balance between environmental and developmental considerations. Article 8(2)(b)(iv) of the Statute translates this reconciliation technique into the realities of armed hostilities, where the inherently anthropocentric biasesFootnote 32 are counterbalanced by the prohibition of a high level of environmental damage. But the ‘vague and malleable meaning’ of the concept of military advantage places a significant conceptual burdenFootnote 33 yet to be interpreted in an environmentally sensitive manner. Any such assessment would be heavily reliant ‘on value judgments’Footnote 34 and would be unpredictable in ‘requiring a prediction of consequences based on available information under circumstances of urgency’.Footnote 35 Article 8(2)(b)(iv) of the Statute illustrates how the objective of preventing environmental damage and the international humanitarian law (‘IHL’) philosophy of accepting all aspects of armed conflict necessary for the conduct of hostilities play off against each other. Reconciling these underlying tensions with environmentalists placing greater weight on environmental protection, the law of armed conflict lawyers lessening the strains of commitment, and IHL advocates prioritising civilian mattersFootnote 36 would require judges to mediate between different value systems to strike a balance. Could it be one of the reasons why pursuing individual criminal responsibility for environmental atrocities has been largely ignored at the international level?

This unsatisfactory status quo has led to numerous policy proposalsFootnote 37 and resulted in a vast amount of research on the possible expansion of the current prohibition of environmental damage beyond the laws of an IAC.Footnote 38 From the substantive perspective, as eloquently put by Robinson, there is ‘no elegant “magic bullet” solution’Footnote 39 to the conceptual challenges in defining international environmental crimes or ‘ecocide’. Clothing the gravest instances of environmental destruction into the fashion of ICL demands careful balancing of the interests of environmental protection with the realities of international criminal justice.

Despite the ongoing campaign to make ‘ecocide’ an international crime, very little has been done towards the interlacing of IEL and ICL. The question of ‘ecocide’ attempts to bring closer together these two disciplines, but, in reality, their ‘interaction remains strikingly limited’.Footnote 40 The following digression on the focal points for their convergence and divergence shows that, although tempting and morally appealing, any current attempts to translate mass environmental degradation into the language of the Statute may prove to be conceptually unfeasible. Instead of strengthening its effectiveness, a too-hasty innovation would raise significant normative predicaments, which, if not meticulously counterbalanced, might lead to the weakening of the existing IEL and ICL frameworks. To build this narrative, the following section begins by explaining the distinctive nature of IEL vis-à-vis other fields of international law.

IEL and ICL vs IEL or ICL

A Worthwhile Initiative?

IEL is still a very modern sub-division that has rapidly evolved over the last 40 years, challenging the foundations of traditional international law. As its raison d’être—the avoidance of the occurrence of environmental harm - dictates an anticipatory approach, at the heart of IEL lies the principle of prevention which imposes an obligation to exercise due care in the face of risks of environmental damage.Footnote 41 The current formulation of the concept of prevention in the environmental context was introduced in 1972 in Principle 21 of the Stockholm Declaration: ‘States have (…) the sovereign right to exploit their own resources (…) and the responsibility to ensure that activities within their jurisdiction or control do not cause damage to the environment of other States or of areas beyond the limits of national jurisdiction’.Footnote 42 Prevention finds its conceptual roots not in the protection of the environment per se, but in the mutual limitation of sovereign rights to the use and enjoyment of territory. Thus, the modern IEL framework has developed on the basis of the sovereign prerogative to exploit natural resources that should be exercised within mutually-acceptable bounds: exploration must not harm the environment of other States.Footnote 43 The StockholmFootnote 44 and RioFootnote 45 Declarations and other constitutional developments of international environmental justice have pushed the IEL’s progression beyond interstate interests, allowing the ‘transboundary’ set of risks to progress into a broader ‘global’ array of threats to the concern of the international community. The modern progression of IEL, with the conception of sustainable development at the heart of its governance,Footnote 46 results from the constant tension between environmental protection and human development. International environmental protection, as a relatively new specialised field of international law, has evolved in a unique manner, throughout the negotiatory processes undertaken within the international institutional framework and ‘on an ever-increasing body of soft law instruments’.Footnote 47 A significant chunk of substantive IEL, based on sectoral multilateral environmental agreements (‘MEAs’),Footnote 48 is developed by conferences of the parties responsible for facilitating the development of a specific regime.Footnote 49 The Basel Convention,Footnote 50 the Convention on Biological Diversity (‘CBD’),Footnote 51 and the Convention on DesertificationFootnote 52 have followed that approach, to name but a few. This sectoral approach to tackling international environmental law issues has resulted in a scattered and decentralised legal landscape of global environmental governance.Footnote 53 Contrary to other more-mature fields of international legal governance, IEL lacks a system of courts with compulsory jurisdiction of the kinds found, for example, in ICL.Footnote 54 With the absence of a foundational MEA giving international environmental protection character, weight, or force and with one international organisation supervising its application, IEL remains fragmented and uncoordinated.Footnote 55

As the evolution of IEL is yet to reach a more general stage in the imposition of criminal liability,Footnote 56 the possible deterrent or even pre-deterrent effect of an international criminal regime on gross environmental wrongs might produce the necessary stimuli to encourage those involved to abide by rules preserving the environment. As noted by Kersting, employing ICL as ‘a vehicle to combat environmental destruction already carries significant symbolic weight’—whether or not the agreed definition of ‘ecocide’ is ecocentric or anthropocentric.Footnote 57 The combined Rechtsgut-harm (eng ‘risk of harming’) approach, broadened to include the ‘risk to harm’ and ‘harm to oneself’,Footnote 58 can be regarded as reflective of the prevention principle, the cornerstone of modern IEL. Numerous jurisdictions use criminal responsibility as a key part of their ‘regulatory armoury’ to enhance deterrence and remediation and to increase public safety.Footnote 59 Amongst these is the European Union (‘EU’), explicitly underscoring that criminal sanctions yield ‘a social disapproval of a qualitatively different nature compared to administrative penalties or a compensation mechanism under civil law’.Footnote 60 It is plausible to assume that an overarching law on mass damage to ecosystems, applicable both in times of peace and armed conflict, is bound to produce some deterrent effects of a stigma on a much broader, international level.

Leaving aside the deterrent potential, the international judicial practice carries an important normative function: ICTs ‘stabilize normative expectations’ whilst reasserting the validity and enforcement of international law.Footnote 61 Environmental litigation has already transgressed into domestic, regional, as well as global judicial practice: in the last 2 years alone the International Court of Justice (‘ICJ’) had made several ground-breaking environmental decisions,Footnote 62 and the Inter-American Commission on Human Rights (‘IACtHR’) has released a series of high-profile international judicial rulings.Footnote 63 Although excessive reliance on the judiciary is precluded by Article 38(1)(d) of the ICJ Statute,Footnote 64 ICTs ‘do exercise influence on the development of the law’ as their potential for innovation lies predominantly in their identification of the relevant law and the application of law to facts.Footnote 65 The unique character of international environmental concerns, which have ‘larger ramifications comprising humans, other species and natural resources’,Footnote 66 provides a motivation for the ‘internationalisation’ of IEL through existing legal frameworks. Environmental considerations have, for instance, contributed to the expansion of the ramifications of ‘security’ traditionally understood in terms of political and military threats to national sovereignty that are now broadened to encompass resource, environmental, and demographic issues.Footnote 67 Although having a secondary role in peace and prevention, political and security concerns ‘form part of the contextual backdrop’ in which the ICC operates.Footnote 68 With its jurisdiction over the gravest crimes that threaten ‘the peace, security and well-being of the world’,Footnote 69 the ICC promotes the goals of its regime whilst enhancing ‘international cooperation’ for ‘the sake of present and future generations’.Footnote 70 Viewing the Statute as a ‘living instrument’, driven by the underlying intention of progressive justice and able to accommodate the needs of current and future generations, correlates with the inter-generational principle of IEL. Although it might be an argument too far that intergenerational equity lies ‘at the heart of the international criminal justice system’,Footnote 71 ICL has manifold objectives,Footnote 72 spreading over those traditionally recognised in domestic criminal law systems. Through the mechanism of purposive judicial interpretation, the ICC can captivate the attention of policy-makers and citizens alike, reinforcing the spirit of international cooperation.

A Standalone ‘Ecocide’ Provision is Still a Radical Development

The major added value of incorporating the fifth crime of ‘ecocide’ would be the expansion of international accountability for environmental harm. Yet, this assumption is only partially true. Although such an innovation would provide the ICC with the necessary tools to investigate and prosecute the gravest instances of environmental degradation, countries that signed and ratified the Statute would be under no obligation to criminalise ‘ecocide’ in their domestic law.Footnote 73 The Statute only requires that national law facilitates cooperation with the CourtFootnote 74 and penalise offences against the ICC’s administration of justice.Footnote 75 However, an ‘ecocide’ amendment is likely to have a catalysing effect on normative grounds: State Parties could feel encouraged to follow the ICC’s example and expand their jurisdictional purview. Diehl et al. mention three criteria necessary for a successful international legal innovation: the existence of a sufficiently clear legal concept, the availability of a structure or framework that can support the operation of the law, and the political will to use the law.Footnote 76 The satisfaction of these requirements does not guarantee a change to occur, but their presence would increase the likelihood of successful innovation in the international system. Whilst focusing on the first and third of these requirements, the following discussion will show that the ongoing campaign on international law on ‘ecocide’ is yet to result in (i) achieving conceptual unity on its definition and (ii) gaining political acceptance and will between the international community of States.

Precaution and Legality

As explained above, environmental cases have several peculiar features not present in other sub-divisions of international law.Footnote 77 Reaching an effective amendment would require mediating between the vagueness, flexibility, and imprecision of IEL and the specificity and rigidity required of ICL provisions.Footnote 78 Finding its primary formulation in Principle 15 of the Rio Declaration, the precautionary approach mandates those confronted with a lack of full scientific certainty to take actions ‘that err on the side of precaution rather than increasing risk’.Footnote 79 The underlying idea is that the lack of scientific certainty about the actual or potential effects of an activity must not prevent States from taking appropriate measures when such effects may be serious or irreversible.Footnote 80 This precautionary logic, dependent on decision-making in the face of uncertainty,Footnote 81 seems to clash with a cornerstone of modern ICL: the principle of legality.Footnote 82 As crafted for interstate relations, rather than the exacting demands of international criminal justice, many leading principles of IELFootnote 83 are formulated in environmental law treaties in vague and broad terms. These may raise legitimate concerns about respect for the legality principle which mandates that certain conduct can only be punished if it ‘has been criminalized in a clear and unambiguous manner (lex certa) at the time of commission (lex praevia)’.Footnote 84 The first two paragraphs of Article 22 of the Statute spell out the principle of non-retroactivity (lex preavia) and of specificity or legal certainty (lex certa).Footnote 85 The IEPLDE’s definition of ‘ecocide’, which proposes an open-ended list of possible ‘acts’ including single acts or omissions,Footnote 86 encapsulates the difficulty in reconciling precaution with nullum crimen sine lege. The rationale behind the adoption of an open list of acts can be regarded as an attempt to broadly align with the rapid evolution of IEL, and the fact that human knowledge and science have not yet managed to address all aspects of the environment. There are many areas of science where there are significant unknowns—‘we don’t know what we don’t know’.Footnote 87 The constant need for enhancing understanding of the ambit of scientific uncertainty militates against any enumeration of the underlying forms of ‘ecocide’ leading to ambiguity as to the specific conduct that may violate the prohibition. Disputes involving scientific uncertainty and potential future harm predetermine an absence of certainty from the start, running counter to the rationalist tradition.Footnote 88 Thus, it is difficult to define a crime with sufficient specificity to satisfy the requirements of ICL, but still, leave enough room for the ICC Prosecutor to apply it to a broad range of substantive activity. A solution could be to narrow the prohibited scope to a range of specific environmentally harmful acts, focusing on particular types of destruction. This approach has been undertaken, inter alia, by the European Court of Human Rights (‘ECtHR’) and the International Tribunal for the Law of the Sea (‘ITLOS’), with the former limiting its environmental purview to environmental wrongs that directly affect natural personsFootnote 89 and the latter to ‘serious harm to the marine environment’.Footnote 90 In order to rectify the imprecision of a general formula, the most recent definition of ‘ecocide’ enumerates the most established environmental hazards that could amount to crimes under international law: land, sea, and air pollution; destruction of habits, ecosystems, or natural heritage; protected species; hazardous waste; and ozone-depleting substances, persistent organic pollutants, and greenhouse gases.Footnote 91 This list concludes with a ‘residual’ provision similar to that of the CAH of other inhumane acts which defines material criminal conduct by reference to the preceding list of acts in Article 7(1) of the Statute.Footnote 92 As stated by the Pre-Trial Chamber II in Muthaura et al., ‘“other inhumane acts” is a residual category within Article 7(1)’,Footnote 93 because ‘one would never be able to catch up with the imagination of future torturers’.Footnote 94 In the same fashion, a separate provision criminalising ‘sexual violence’ found in the Statute functions as a catchall provision allowing the Court to exercise jurisdiction over any other, un-enumerated form(s) of sexual violence of comparable gravity to the listed sex-based crimes.Footnote 95 Thus, in contrast to the IEPLDE, the UCLA’s definition attempts to align the proposed definition with the requirements of Article 22 of the Statute. On the one hand, the ‘list’ technique seems to be more practical and desirable from the perspective of certainty and predictability, and thus might be relatively easier to gain States’ acceptance.Footnote 96 On the other hand, as IEL does not expressly penalise a particular conduct, it is difficult to put forward a concrete and exhaustive list of acts. Although it might have reached its infancy stage, IEL is still a very new and undeveloped field characterised by an unprecedented speed of normative growth racing to meet the emerging needs of the global society. With its fallback on ‘softer’ forms of accountability, the language of the IELs’ treaties is generally not prohibitive.Footnote 97 One example is the CBD that requires States to ‘duly take into account’ significant adverse impacts on biodiversity, and to assess projects ‘with a view’ to avoiding or minimizing harms.Footnote 98 But there is a vast number of multilateral environmental treaties that prescribe the conduct using the mandatory ‘shall’; for instance, Article 2 of the London Convention stipulates that States parties ‘shall (…) take effective measures (…) to prevent, reduce and where practicable eliminate pollution caused by dumping (…)’.Footnote 99 There have been even attempts, although scarce, to include prohibitive language such as Article 4 of the Montreal Protocol which prohibits ‘importing and exporting by States parties of substances from or to third States’.Footnote 100 These developments show the IEL’s potential to progress into a more ‘prohibitive’ direction. But the field is still at an early stage of its formation, yet to move beyond its state-centric nature. This state-centric focus constitutes the major obstacle to curving out a concise list of actions that could impose concrete prohibitions vis-à-vis States and individuals. To recall the words of the ICJ in Nuclear Weapons: ‘these treaties [on the deployment and testing of nuclear weapons] could therefore be seen as foreshadowing a future general prohibition of the use of such weapons’.Footnote 101 Yet, it immediately added that ‘they do not constitute such a prohibition by themselves’.Footnote 102 The UCLA’s proposal of a general list of acts that might be regarded as prohibitive under IEL should be regarded as a positive development, but it has to be taken with a pinch of salt.

Culpability

Beyond the questions surrounding precaution and legality, other principles inherent to the ICL doctrine—mens rea and individual criminal responsibility—further complicate the successful reconciliation of IEL and ICL under the mantle of the Statute. Article 30 of the Statute sets the general subjective element standard of crimes under the Statute that is applicable in all cases where the substantive provision in question does not rules specifically regulate the mens rea. As referred to above,Footnote 103 the only explicit reference to environmental damage found in the Statute, Article 8(2)(b)(iv), requires a standard of ‘knowledge of causation’.Footnote 104 Thus, to discharge the burden of proof, the ICC Prosecutor must prove that the accused had, with the knowledge to the contextual element and with regard to the general intent regarding the actus reus of the crime knowledge that the attacks would cause ‘clearly excessive’ environmental damage.Footnote 105 Heller and Lawrence accused the fault standard included under Article 8(2)(b)(iv) of the Statute as being futile by making it close to impossible to prove that the accused ‘knew’ that their attack would be disproportionate.Footnote 106 To rectify this conceptual limitation, the IEPLDE proposed a ‘knowledge’ element that requires only ‘a substantial likelihood’ of environmental damage,Footnote 107 whilst the UCLA put forward the standard of ‘knowledge of likelihood’.Footnote 108 Both proposed mens rea elements are much lower than the threshold, for instance, for dolus specialis for genocideFootnote 109 and the ‘knowledge of causation’ requirement under Article 8(2)(b)(iv) of the Statute. More fundamentally, both also fall short of Article 30 of the Statute which establishes the general level of mens rea for all the crimes defined in Articles 6 to 8 of the Statute.Footnote 110 The term ‘knowledge’ found in Article 30 of the Statute requires perpetrators to be aware that their actions are ‘virtually certain’ to bring about a prohibited outcomeFootnote 111 and that a circumstance exists or a consequence will occur in the ordinary course of events.Footnote 112 The ‘substantial likelihood’, instead, sets a lower cognitive threshold of subjective awareness. Because of setting the standard below the ‘general’ intent requirement within the ICC framework, the IEPLDE’s mens rea notion has been termed as ‘confusing’Footnote 113 and ‘troubling’Footnote 114 as it directly challenges the purposive exclusion of ‘dolus eventualis, recklessness or any lower form of culpability’ from the scope of the Statute.Footnote 115 Similarly, the UCLA’s ‘knowledge of likelihood’ appears to fall below the ‘genera’ subjective element requiring both intent and knowledge, and comes closer to the principles of dolus eventualis or recklessness.

However, this critique seems to disregard the phrase ‘[u]nless otherwise provided’ found in Article 30(1) of the Statute, which allows departures from the general standard prescribing both knowledge and intent.Footnote 116 A number of provisions in the Elements of Crimes relate to the phase ‘otherwise provided’ in Article 30 of the Statute, including ‘knew or should have known’,Footnote 117 ‘was aware of’,Footnote 118 ‘intended’,Footnote 119 and ‘in order to’Footnote 120 as confirmed in the literature.Footnote 121 Thus, both the UCLA and the IEPLDE definitions are consistent with the ICC legal regime which contemplates ‘knowledge’ of risk and possibilities.Footnote 122

Looking more closely at the language used by the IEPLDE, the concept of ‘substantial likelihood’ has been used on at least two occasions in the jurisprudence of the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia (‘ICTY’). First, the reference to ‘substantial likelihood’ was made by the ICTY in the context of the ‘had reason to know’ criterion under Article 7(1) ICTY Statute. In Strugar, the Appeals Chamber found that the ‘had reason to know’ standard demands ‘sufficiently alarming information putting a superior on notice of the risk that crimes might subsequently be carried out by his subordinates and justifying further inquiry’.Footnote 123 In the words of the ICTY, in order to surpass this threshold of awareness, it is not necessary to either show proof of a ‘clear and strong risk’ or a ‘substantial likelihood’ that a crime will be committed.Footnote 124 Instead, the possibility of the occurrence of unlawful acts suffices.Footnote 125 The ICTY jurisprudence on the ‘had reason to know’ standard seems to align with the interpretation of the IEPLDE: ‘substantial likelihood’ denotes ‘a clear and strong risk’ that the perpetrator accepted the peril whilst foreseeing the possibility of crime in the bargain. Second, the phrase ‘substantial likeliheood’ was referred to by the ICTY in the context of liability for ordering. The Blaškić Appeals Chamber determined that a ‘person who orders an act or omission with the awareness of the substantial likelihood that a crime will be committed in the execution of that order, has the requisite mens rea for establishing liability’.Footnote 126 The judgement concludes that ‘[o]rdering with such awareness has to be regarded as accepting that crime’.Footnote 127 It seems that the degree of such risk must be considerable—‘higher likelihood’—and that chances that are empirically not likely to occur are irrelevant. Within the ICC’s jurisprudence, the concepts of ‘substantial risk or likelihood’ formed part of the analysis on the principle of ‘dolus eventualis’ in the first decision of the ICC rendered by the Pre-Trial Chamber I (‘PTC I’) in Lubanga. It opinioned that if ‘the risk (…) is substantial (that is, there is a likelihood that it “will occur in the ordinary course of events”)’ the fact that the suspect accepted the idea to bring about the actus reus of the crime can be inferred from their awareness of substantial likelihood of its commission and the fact that they carried out their actions or omissions despite such awareness.Footnote 128 From this sentence it can be deduced that the PTC I treats the concepts of ‘risk’ and ‘likelihood’ interchangeably.Footnote 129 In the same vein, the adjective ‘substantial’ denotes the phase ‘will occur in the ordinary course of events’.Footnote 130 Thus, in line with the language of the PCT I, the IEPLDE’s concept of ‘substantial likelihood’ can be translated into risk or likelihood that the consequence will occur in the ordinary course of events. And, by reference to Article 30(3) of the Statute, the UCLA’s ‘knowledge of likelihood’ can be interpreted to mean risk or likelihood that ‘that a circumstance exists or a consequence will occur in the ordinary course of events’.Footnote 131 It boils down to the conclusion that in the wording of the Lubanga Confirmation of Charges Decision, both proposed mens rea standards for the crime of ‘ecocide’ convey a similar subjective threshold.

To summarise, whilst the concept of ‘substantial likelihood’ has an established pedigree both at the ad hoc tribunals and the ICC, the phrase ‘knowledge of likelihood’ can be implicitly inferred from the early ICC’s case law. As neither of the constitutive documents of the Court directly specifies the meaning behind either of the proposed subjective elements, the ICC judges might be willing to cite the precedent of the other international tribunals or revert to its first Confirmation of Charges Decision. If States Parties decide to introduce the lowered mens rea criterion, the above-reviewed jurisprudence can provide a reference starting point for any determination made on its scope. But, so far, the ICC has been reluctant to ‘mechanically’ transfer the ad hoc tribunals’ case law to the system of the Court.Footnote 132 Whilst the Court tends to take an account of the jurisprudence of its predecessors, the ICC judges do not feel bound or even guided by it.Footnote 133 For example, despite the introduction of joint criminal enterprise as a principal form of liability in Tadić,Footnote 134 ‘credited for being the most appropriate mode of liability to tackle the collective dimension of international crimes’,Footnote 135 the drafters of the Statute, including the ICC judges themselves, have expressly rejected its inclusion.Footnote 136

Nevertheless, if a less exacting mens rea were to be successfully inserted into the Statute, it would provide a sort of middle ground between intent and negligence. On the one hand, such a lowered mens rea requirement could make a difference in the ICC’s reach concerning environmental harm. On the other hand, a successful charge of ‘ecocide’ would require the ICC Prosecutor to prove that the perpetrator had, to a certain degree, reconciled themselves to the prohibited result by accepting a risk that, in their circumstances, was unreasonable to take. As already noted above, the IEPLDE’s definition of ‘ecocide’ omits spelling out the objective elements of the crime. The absence of a clear actus reus would be problematic from the mens rea perspective as the ICC Prosecutor would have the burden of proving that the perpetrator had knowledge—albeit general—which alerted them to the relevant risk of the prohibited conduct being committed. Without an express definition of the objective elements of the crime, it is far from certain on which basis would the ICC Prosecutor propose a charge of ‘ecocide’ and how later to discharge the requisite burden of proof. From this perspective, the UCLA’s list of prohibited conduct would limit the discretion vested in the ICC Prosecutor in terms of drawing up the list of possible charges. The inclusion of a residual clause, however, would still afford the ICC Prosecutor and, in turn, the ICC judges to expand on the range of prohibitive acts to the detriment of the principle of equality of arms.

In addition, both the IEPLDE’s and UCLA’s proposed definitions formulate ‘ecocide’ as ‘a crime of endangerment rather than of material result’.Footnote 137 By portraying risk itself as mischief,Footnote 138 such a provision would allow the ICC Prosecutor to charge alleged perpetrators, not on the basis of causing substantive harm to the environment but merely endangering it. Thus, taking advance of the open-ended scope of the IEPLDE’s prohibition, the ICC Prosecutor would be able to virtually charge any conduct that endangers severe and either widespread or long-term damage to the environment.Footnote 139

In the context of liability for international environmental damage, one could reasonably query what would happen if the risk of environmental harm is simply miscalculated or undervalued. Within the framework of the Statute, an erroneous appreciation or awareness of the relevant facts by an accused can amount to a defence of mistake of fact, negating the mens rea if the perpetrator erred about ‘a factual (descriptive) element of the relevant offence’.Footnote 140 Mistakes of facts including, for instance, a human error arising from the misidentification of factual information, can lead to the exclusion of criminal liability. What would happen if, despite carrying out a laborious and thorough analysis of available information, a superior has nevertheless erroneously predicated and mischaracterised the environmental hazards? Would the principle of precaution be relevant in the interpretation and application of that statutory provision? How far should governments and militaries align with the precautionary approach whilst working to find ways to meet the needs of both a burgeoning military and a finite life-sustaining environment?Footnote 141 Should there be a certain threshold of potential damage in the absence of which the concept of precaution could be ignored? All of these questions illustrate that even if the States Parties accept the inclusion of a more expansive mens rea to the crime of ‘ecocide’, in practice a less demanding subjective element might prove exacting to apply and establish in practice. Many have also raised reasonable concerns that any addition of a substantially dissimilar and statutorily ‘odd’ mens rea element, would become ‘an anomaly’ further uncoupling ‘ecocide’ from the remaining substantive provisions.Footnote 142

The Responsibility Paradigm

In contrast to ICL, the current framework of IEL is based on the traditional and predominant role of States and their responsibility for environmental harm.Footnote 143 But that regime has not played a significant or at least practical role in addressing environmental challenges: most cross-national environmental concerns find their resolution via negotiation or adoption of an agreement that regulates the issue at hand, and only a few cases result in formal dispute settlement.Footnote 144 This ineffectiveness of State responsibility fuels the efforts to extend the doctrine of individual criminal responsibility to the environmental damage line with the internal logic of domestic and international humanitarian and criminal law.Footnote 145 The major deficiency of individual criminal responsibility is its upfront restriction of the range of possible perpetrators to natural persons, excluding the concept of criminal liability of corporations for international crimes.Footnote 146 In line with the ICC’s model of attribution, investigations and prosecutions target individuals at the leadership level of given organisations: those who are ‘able control and dominate the collective action with full responsibility’.Footnote 147 But the ICC Prosecutor is unable to charge corporations themselves, despite the fact that many of the defendants in such cases ‘will be corporations rather than individuals’.Footnote 148 Widespread environmental threats are increasingly linked to large corporate entities, which possessed early knowledge of the risks posed by their activities and had opportunities to mitigate those risks. Instead, they failed to do so or even tried ‘to mislead the public by spreading misinformation campaigns and lobbying regulators against taking action’.Footnote 149 The added value of including corporate liability for mass environmental damage would be to bypass ‘the most complex liability theories in international law’Footnote 150—superior responsibility—and render transnational companies directly liable to provide compensation for the damage incurred throughout their activities. Instead of targeting the narrowed band of responsible CEOs, international criminal proceedings for corporate environmental crimes, putting the company’s reputation at risk, might have a ‘dissuasive and preventive effect rather than just punitive’.Footnote 151 Although discussion on the possible inclusion of corporate responsibility in the framework of the ICC falls beyond this analysis, it is relevant to mention the recent ILC Draft Principles on the Protection of the environment in relation to armed conflicts (‘ILC Draft Principles’).Footnote 152 By putting the centre of gravity of the international environmental liability regime on state responsibility,Footnote 153 ILC Draft Principle 9 has explicitly reaffirmed the supremacy of States in international environmental governance. Subsequent ILC Draft Principles impose on States a duty of ‘corporate due diligence’,Footnote 154 obliging them to ‘regulate their corporations and hold them liable for their wrongdoings’.Footnote 155 This explicit recognition of the complicity of corporations in the current environmental crisisFootnote 156 is highly relevant to the current practice as corporate involvement in environmentally harmful practices (e.g., illicit exploitation of natural resources) continues to magnify. Despite certain limitations,Footnote 157 the work of the ILC can be perceived as ‘momentous’Footnote 158 in establishing a clear hierarchy within the system of individual and corporate responsibility: States and individuals can be held responsible at the international level whilst corporations remain criminally liable under domestic law. From the dogmatic perspective, the approach undertaken by the ILC aligns with the current framework of ICL with its ‘Nuremberg’ conception of international criminal justice: ‘crimes against international law are committed by men, not abstract entities’.Footnote 159 The doctrine of individual criminal liability still remains the cornerstone of modern ICL as reflected in Article 25 of the Statute,Footnote 160 despite the increased interest in international and domestic attitudes to establish some level of corporate liability for complicity in atrocity crimes.Footnote 161 In the absence of an international criminal tribunal that can adjudge crimes committed by legal actors,Footnote 162 the link between economic power and international criminal conduct of non-State actors unalterably remains a matter of academic deliberations. Apart from reaching a consensus on extending the reach of the ICC to cover corporate international criminal misconduct, another challenge for the States Parties would be to single out one approach that would be suitable for holding corporations criminally responsible before the ICC.Footnote 163 Many domestic legal systems recognise a certain level of corporate responsibility,Footnote 164 but these systems show wide variations in approach to liability. Thus, another challenge for the States Parties would be to reconcile and balance those varied interests.Footnote 165

Lack of Sufficient Political Will

Even in the presence of a sufficiently clear definition of ‘ecocide’, its future will depend on the political consensus and the will to bear the ‘cost’ of enforcing ICL for environmental ends. The current status quo is an important reference point for any concrete discussions on potential legal innovations. At the moment, the crime is implemented in the penal codes of nine former Soviet Union countries,Footnote 166 Vietnam,Footnote 167 also the FrenchFootnote 168 and Belgium Parliaments have voted in favour of recognition of the crime of ‘ecocide’.Footnote 169 Certainly, there is an amplified interest in ‘ecocide’ that has transgressed academic circles into policy deliberations reaching, to a certain extent, the implementation stage. However, that interest still seems to be limited, as, despite the calls of the European ParliamentFootnote 170 and the United Nations Environment Programme,Footnote 171 there is no recorded State practice concerning the investigation and prosecution of the perpetrators of ‘ecocide’. During the 26th UN Climate Change Conference in Glasgow, the progress on international legislation against ‘ecocide’ was also largely under the radar.Footnote 172 Although a number of countries have implemented crime within their legal systems, to the knowledge of this author, only one put its provision into operation. In 2012, the Kyrgyz Prosecutor General reportedly charged the head of the Kyrgyz company, which illegally shipped radioactive coal, with ecocide.Footnote 173 This stark lack of state practice can be contrasted with the rapid ‘greening’ of domestic human rights law. Already in 1993, the Philippines Supreme Court described rights to a healthy environment as ‘basic rights’ which ‘predate all governments and constitutions’ and ‘need not be written in the Constitution for they are assumed to exist from the inception of humankind’.Footnote 174 In total, more than 80% of States Members of the United Nations legally recognise the right to a safe, clean, healthy and sustainable environment.Footnote 175 What is striking about the trajectory of that development is the fact that the right to an environment of a certain quality has evolved domestically vis-à-vis the supra-national legal order. The objective of providing for such a right in international law has been mostly achieved through national means, in the absence of a single universally binding source of international law entrenching such a right.Footnote 176 The domestic codification had a catalysing effect on international legal actors, not the reverse. Should the development of the prohibition of ‘ecocide’ or mass environmental damage follow the same bottom-up approach to international lawmaking? At the present moment, the lack of political willingness, its scarce existence only in a handful of countries, and the lack of environmentally-driven investigations and prosecutions suggest that the time is simply not yet ripe to seriously take into account any discussions on the subject. Ultimately, the realisation of any substantive amendment procedure will depend on the political will of States which is difficult to surmise.

ICC as a Complementary Vehicle for Redress

This detour to investigate the possibilities for synergies and major conflict points between ICL and IEL endeavoured to showcase how the dominant logics of these two sub-divisions of international law play out against each other. Beyond the highlighted challenges to the effective inclusion of an ‘ecocide’ provision to the framework of the Statute, other difficulties to the effective reconciliation of IEL and ICL include, inter alia, the repair of environmental damage,Footnote 177 quantification of environmental harm,Footnote 178 the geographically-diffuse character of environmental harms such as climate change,Footnote 179 or the issue of causation.Footnote 180 Environmental issues do not only transgress geopolitical borders but also traditional epistemic approaches to international law litigation, requiring horizontal coordination across several institutions and sectors.Footnote 181 By far, the most difficult issue that challenges the international ‘ecocide’ movement is how to best align the crime with the primary narratives driving the development of IEL: precaution and prevention. The proposed definition should be in accord with the rapid changes and innovations driving international environmental governance and, simultaneously, must specify the actus reus and the mens rea in the corpus criminalizing the conduct.Footnote 182 On the one hand, incorporating a prohibition rooted in the logic of precaution and prevention might result in a major substantive disconnect, setting up a ‘sub-system’ within the framework of the Statute. On the other, a definition too conformable with the demands of the ICL could manifest itself in regressive or rigid language, weakening its stand against the remaining ‘core’ crimes. Future deliberations on the types of factual scenarios that should or should not fall within the prohibition might aid further attempts to reduce the conceptual gap between international environmental protection and international criminal justice.

THE ‘ENVIRONMENTAL’ POTENTIAL OF THE CURRENT FRAMEWORK

The questions on the future of ‘ecocide’ in the framework of, the Statute do not put a hold on the ICC from harnessing the potential of the current statutory framework to address environmentally related concerns. Translating environmental protection into and bolstering it by reference to the substantive framework of the Statute can act as a powerful stimulus, drawing international attention to matters related to the environment. The 2016 OTP policy paper on case selection and prioritisation (‘2016 OTP Policy Paper’) provides evidence of an increased interest within the ICC itself in prioritising ‘core’ crimes ‘that are committed by means of (…) the destruction of the environment, the illegal exploitation of natural resources or the illegal dispossession of land’.Footnote 183 Although not binding in itself, the 2016 OTP Policy Paper shows an inclination on the part of the ICC Prosecutor to investigate and prosecute crimes involving illegal natural resource exploitation, land grabbing, and environmental damage.Footnote 184 Instead of adopting an overly inclusive understanding of the primary legal object of IEL—the ‘environment’Footnote 185—too demanding for the limited capabilities of the Court, the ICC should take advantage of the flexible character of that concept and model it in the light of the contextual elements of its core crimes. The following discussion proposes two possible directions for the ICC to move in that direction: (i) more resourceful translation of environmental realities into the substantive prohibitions of war crimes or (ii) more active reliance on and application of Article 21(3) of the Statute in conjunction with Article 7(1)(h). The indirect reliance on the prohibition of genocide as a means to perpetrate environmental harms has received much scholarly attention,Footnote 186 thus, it is not addressed below.

War Crimes and the Environment

As discussed above,Footnote 187 the excessively high threshold for the operation of Article 8(2)(b)(iv) of the Statute severely undermines its viability prospects in the enhancement of environmental protection through the ICL framework. Other statutory provisions applicable to IACs and NIACs might provide another layer of indirect protection and, in practice, a more feasible means for targeting instances of environmental destruction. Illegal exploitation of the environment can ‘intensify conflict during active hostilities and reignite hostilities in the aftermath of conflict’Footnote 188 or even be the main reason fueling the violence. The paradox of the ‘resource curse’ underscores the fact that extraction of natural resources can often bolster corruption,Footnote 189 forced displacement,Footnote 190 and land grabbing,Footnote 191 ultimately boiling down to political manoeuvring, instability, or even armed conflict. For example, natural resource exploitation is at the heart of many present-day armed conflicts, such as the ongoing hostilities in the Democratic Republic of the Congo (‘DRC’), Côte d'Ivoire,Footnote 192 or Ukraine.Footnote 193 The three roles of the environment in times of armed insurgencies—a lootable target, a mere tool or an incidental victim—have often been melded indistinctly into one another, making it even more challenging to craft the appropriate strategy paving the way for environmental justice.

Pillage

The prohibition of pillage enshrined in Articles 8(2)(b)(xvi) and 8(2)(e)(v) of the Statute is relevant from the environmental perspective, especially within the context of natural resource exploitation. Although its general prohibition has attained the level of a customary principle applicable in IACs and NIACs,Footnote 194 there is no official definition of ‘pillage’.Footnote 195 Within the ICC’s framework, the crime penalises appropriation of property without the consent of its owner with the intent to deprive them of the property and appropriate it for private or personal use.Footnote 196 The Court’s regime further does not require proof of force or violence as an element of such appropriation.Footnote 197 Its rationae personae is broad as the crime addresses any individual, without restriction,Footnote 198 extending both to acts of looting committed for private gain and ‘to the organized seizure of property undertaken within the framework of a systemic economic exploitation of occupied territory’.Footnote 199 Although Footnote 67 might implicitly suggest otherwise,Footnote 200 pillage and military necessity are ‘mutually exclusive concepts’,Footnote 201 as confirmed by the Trial Chamber in Bemba.Footnote 202 Thus, appropriation of private property belonging to combatants but not justified by military necessity constitutes the crime of pillaging.Footnote 203 The major novelty of the ICC’s definition is the addition of the ‘private or personal use’ element, which has been accused of being without foundation in jurisprudenceFootnote 204 and criticised for narrowing its prohibited scope and heightening the evidentiary threshold.Footnote 205 Although certain components of the environment can be subject to ownership such that they are ‘property’—be they livestock or plots of land—the property requirement limits the possibility of that provision addressing the full extent of the environmental destruction.Footnote 206 In Ongwen, the Trial Chamber emphasised that the concept of private property and the right to property are understood broadly as ‘encompassing not only the property of individuals, but also the communal property of the communities’, taking ‘into consideration the customary law of the community’.Footnote 207 The creative extension of property rights to environmental components has already taken root in the jurisprudence of, inter alia, the ECtHRFootnote 208 and the IACtHR.Footnote 209 Nevertheless, all human rights adjudicators condition the scope for environmental protection upon establishing a more or less demanding ‘link’ requirement between the impairment of a specific protected right, such as the right to property, and environmental degradation. For instance, the ECtHR rejected the claim for breach of Articles 6 and 8 of the European Convention of Human Rights (‘ECHR’) as the applicants failed to establish a clear connection between the impact of the project on the ecosystem of the Munzur Valley and their life or property.Footnote 210 In a similar fashion, only if environmental components were appropriated for private or personal use, as in Katanga, where pillaging was perpetrated for the sake of individual gain,Footnote 211 would the requirement for private or personal use be fulfilled. The question of whether natural resources could constitute civilian property was answered affirmatively by the ICJ in DRC v Uganda,Footnote 212 finding the government of Uganda internationally responsible for looting, plundering, and exploiting the DRC’s natural resources by failing to prevent members of its army from the commission of these acts. Despite the broad reading of ‘property’ and the express recognition of systematic looting of gold and diamonds as pillage by international and domestic courts,Footnote 213 the ICC’s ‘personal or private use’ requirement excludes the range of appropriations committed for other purposes, for example, to fund armed hostilities.Footnote 214 The primary focus on property further factors out a vast portion of environmental damage that is conducted without a view to exercising ownership rights.Footnote 215 It appears very likely that a potential accused could claim that any act of environmental exploitation was carried out for public ends and to fund the military campaign. The second element—proof of ‘specific intent’—further amplifies the evidentiary standard, placing an ‘unduly restrictive’Footnote 216 burden of proof on the ICC Prosecutor. So far, the ICC Prosecutor has not brought charges concerning pillaged property of a strictly environmental nature. In Ongwen, the pillaged objects were limited to foodstuffs, clothing,Footnote 217 and households;Footnote 218 in Katanga, the attackers seized mattresses, tables, chairs and kitchen equipment and took possession of livestockFootnote 219; similarly, in Bemba, the pillaged goods included bicycles, motorcycles, money,Footnote 220 and household items such as beds and electrical generators.Footnote 221 Despite its conceptual limitations, the crime of pillage has the potency to deliver another layer of environmental protection if contextualised intelligently. A more ‘preventative’ interpretation of the principle of permanent sovereignty over natural resourcesFootnote 222 would provide a viable opportunity to deepen the intersection between IEL and the context of armed conflict: viewing it as a sovereign entitlement to exploitation but also as a permanent duty to exercise those inherent economic privileges in the interest of achieving national sustainable development. The powerful statement of the Rio Declaration—of warfare being ‘inherently destructive of sustainable development’Footnote 223—cautions us that any situation involving armed conflict entails regression or, at best, stagnation of the process towards sustainability. By embracing the IEL’s focus on sustainable management of natural resources, the ICC could take a more ‘precautionary’ stance towards anticipatory resource management. Although the Court is yet to break the ‘resource curse’ and contextualise the war crime of ‘pillage’ as environmental abuse, it may be concluded that the prohibition applies to the exploitation of natural resources committed by members of rebel or foreign forces for personal enrichment. The major weakness of translating the statutory provisions on pillage to the context of natural resource exploitation is the risk of them indiscriminately targeting non-state actors without enlarging it to include the States themselves, the primary owners of natural resources.Footnote 224

Destruction and Appropriation of Property

The second environmentally relevant IAC wartime prohibition laid in Article 8(2)(a)(iv) of the Statute criminalises conduct against property in the power of the enemy. It prohibits the perpetrator from extensively and wantonly destroying or appropriating property protected under one or more of the Geneva Conventions 1949 and not justified by military necessity.Footnote 225 The term ‘destruction’ encompasses, for instance, ‘setting objects on fire, attacking or otherwise seriously damaging them; for appropriation taking, obtaining or withholding property, theft, requisition, plunder, spoliation or pillage’.Footnote 226 On the one hand, this prohibition can be regarded as broader than the crime of pillage, as it encompasses the appropriation of civilian property, including its destruction,Footnote 227 and without specifying the applicable mental element, it incorporates the default standard of Article 30 of the Statute. The absence of the ‘private or personal use’ criterion allows the prohibition to extend over the systematic exploitation of environmental components, including natural resources, for the purpose of financing military operations. On the other hand, the expressive exception of ‘military necessity’,Footnote 228 missing in the definition of pillage, would serve as a significant limitation filtering out all but the most egregious examples of environmental harm.Footnote 229

Destruction of Objects Indispensable to the Survival of the Civilian Population

The above-mentioned war crime provisions are complemented by the broader prohibition of starvation, criminalising intentional taking or destruction of objects indispensable to the survival of the civilian population.Footnote 230 Its range of prohibited conducts includes, for instance, the destruction of crops and the poisoning of water resources; however, the impeding of relief supplies, covering the transport of food and water, can also satisfy the actus reus requirement.Footnote 231 As the provision resembles an obligation of conduct—‘no result of starvation is required’Footnote 232—the notion of ‘indispensable objects’ extends over the most essential set of resources and includes deprivation of other necessities such as medicine, clothing, or food harvesting products.Footnote 233 The prohibition thereby creates room for a certain level of indirect environmental protection by banning the destruction of objects, albeit not forming part of the natural environment, whose damage can result in adverse environmental impacts. In Al Bashir, despite the ultimate lack of charges against the war crime of starvation, the prohibited methods included the destruction of the means of survival and usurpation of the land.Footnote 234 This inclusion implies the existence of a consequent link between acts of deprivation of that kind and civilian survival. Although the prohibition does not contain the exception of military necessity, it remains a selective tool, shielding environmental components strictly necessary to civilian survival whilst overlooking a substantial portion of the environment falling beyond the realm of ‘indispensable objects’.

Civilian Objects and Cultural Property

Article 8(2)(b)(ii) of the Statute encapsulates the customary rule of distinction applicable both in IACs and NIACs,Footnote 235 which requires ‘belligerents to conduct operations in a manner that respects the difference between civilians and civilian objects on the one hand, and combatants and military objectives on the other’.Footnote 236 Although components of the environment are most often civilian objects, their protection is ‘shaky’ as environmental elements can quickly become military objectsFootnote 237 depending on their use. Beyond the ‘civilian object’ shield, parts of the environment qualifying as cultural propertyFootnote 238 benefit from the additional level of protection provided under Article 8(2)(b)(ix) of the Statute, mirrored in Article 8(2)(e)(iv) applicable to NIACs. Both provisions are built on the approach introduced by the 1954 Convention for the Protection of Cultural Property in the Event of Armed ConflictFootnote 239 and its Protocol II,Footnote 240 without, however, differentiating in gravity for offences against cultural property.Footnote 241 In contrast to the Statute, the regime protecting cultural property during armed conflict offers different degrees of protection depending on the importance of the cultural property:Footnote 242 a specific object may be reinforced by so-called special or enhanced protection.Footnote 243 Whilst the protection of ‘civilian’ objects is granted to all cultural property not used for military purposes,Footnote 244 the regime of special protection shields those cultural heritage refuges identified as being ‘of very great importance’.Footnote 245 In addition, through the mechanism of listing, the enhanced protection covers properties ‘of the greatest importance for humanity’.Footnote 246 The statutory absence of such differentiation in gravity between acts perpetrated against the different elements of cultural property prevents the Court from clearly expressing the fact of wrongdoing but also articulating its degree.Footnote 247 In the only case that directly addressed the destruction of cultural heritage—Al MahdiFootnote 248the Court missed the opportunity to clarify the details of the notion of cultural property or the degree of protection recognised by the Statute. The Trial Chamber’s reasoning implies that only the UN Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organisation (‘UNESCO’) World Heritage site designation of those specifically targeted mausoleums and mosquesFootnote 249 was one of the factors reflective of their special importance to international cultural heritage and the need for international protection.Footnote 250 Though not even indirectly entertaining any environmentally related issue, the judgement remains significant primarily because it found the prohibited conduct to encompass ‘any acts of violence against protected objects’ whilst stressing that IHL ‘protects cultural objects as such from crimes committed both in battle and out of it’.Footnote 251 As the sole precedent for the prosecution of crimes against cultural heritage—the first ‘victimless crime’Footnote 252Al Mahdi’s anthropocentric reading of the crime might set limits on the future internal functioning of the ICC when dealing with crimes against other types of cultural heritage, such as its natural counterpart.Footnote 253 The current regime fails ‘to capture cultural heritage in a holistic way’,Footnote 254 providing a somewhat rigid characterisation with a prevalent focus on the spatial dimension. Thus, within the regime of cultural property, the ICC might adopt a strategy involving a regulatory approach, focusing on space rather than on the protection of movable natural elements.

Designation of Protected Zones?

Next to substantive issues peculiar to each provision, the asymmetric level of protection and the vague divide between IACs and NIACs augments the challenges involved in ascertaining the set of rules to conflicts of a hybrid or erratic nature.Footnote 255 The major weakness of the war crimes regime is the necessity to balance the already weak level of environmental protection against the subjective and convenient loophole of military necessity.Footnote 256 More general provisions regarding the preservation of property or objects indispensable to the civilian population could fill some of the gaps, however, without serving primarily environmental purposes.Footnote 257 In this regard, the ILC in its Draft Principles put forward the possibility of designating areas of major ecological and cultural importance as protected zones in the case of both IACs and NIACs.Footnote 258 ILC Draft Principle 4 encourages States to enter into agreements designating areas of environmental importance as protected zones in the event of armed conflict.Footnote 259 Examples of successful designation of such zones include the ‘peace parks’ (i.e. cross-border ecological preserves) jointly managed by Ecuador and Peru as part of peacebuilding efforts to end a long-lasting border disputeFootnote 260 or cooperation on water resources between Israel and Jordan following the 1994 peace agreement.Footnote 261 The positive feature of the proposed regime is the broad interpretation of the requisite express agreement on the designation that includes ‘verbal agreements, unilateral or reciprocal and concordant declarations, agreements with non-State actors or designation through an international organization’.Footnote 262 Under IEL, the designation of protected areas is a commonly used technique to safeguard, for instance, endangered species (CBD),Footnote 263 cultural landscapes (World Heritage Convention),Footnote 264 or ecosystems (Ramsar Convention).Footnote 265 Furthermore, to rectify its previous omission,Footnote 266 ILC Draft Principle 13(1) enshrines the presumption of the continued operation of relevant MEAs despite the outburst of armed hostilities, mandating the continuing applicability of IEL and international human rights law (‘IHRL’) obligations in situations of armed conflict. Thus, the ILC’s Draft Principles prevent IHL standards from completely relaxing environmental safeguards during armed hostilities: for example, they shield protected zones that do contain a military objectiveFootnote 267 and encourage parties to agree on an additional layer of protection even though the area concerned comprises a military target.Footnote 268 However, such an ad hoc ‘designation’ technique is not free from other potential constraints. The outcome that might result in the model of ‘militarised conservation’Footnote 269 is argued to be ‘fundamentally unjust’ because it covers specifically chosen areas and species and is not concerned with addressing the broader root causes of environmental issues such as poaching and trafficking.Footnote 270 All in all, the ILC’s proposal of ‘protected zones’, which shares similarities with the concept of ‘demilitarized zones’ in IHL,Footnote 271 can be regarded as a way forward for biodiversity protection in relation to armed conflict.Footnote 272

Crimes Against Humanity

Beyond the umbrella of armed hostilities, the regime of CAH can provide a certain level of protection, although, as implied by its title, inherently constrained by the anthropocentric ends of its prohibitions. Its narrow application to cases dealing exclusively with human suffering leaves no prospects of directly weaponizing CAH in the fight against broader environmental degradation. This proposition is not surprising as neither of the existing core crimes was designed with the environment in mind. One could even argue that adopting a more or less homo-centric or eco-centric approach to environmental protection is irrelevant since the failure to adequately protect the environment will almost always result in some level of human suffering. Although this premise is correct, reliance on ‘core’ prohibitions sanctioning human-centric harm would signify that environmental degradation is only reprehensible as a side-effect of harm to humans. Thus, the major shortcoming of criminalising mass environmental degradation under the mantle of international human rights violations is the outset limitation of the expressivist and utilitarian functions of ICL in increasing awareness of the condemnation of environmentally-harmful conduct.Footnote 273

Viewing mass environmental degradation as a means to commit another atrocity may also buttress the accusation of selectivity in ICL, ‘ “the Achilles” heel of the system of international criminal justice’.Footnote 274 As emphasised above,Footnote 275 it should not be seen as discouragement in itself, as the vast majority of international environmental conventions are of a ‘sectorial’ nature, with the transversal instruments being less numerous and less developed.Footnote 276 Cumberlege underlines the issue-specific approach to regulation in MEAsFootnote 277 based on the common understanding that there is no ‘one-size-fits-all approach’ to international environmental challenges.Footnote 278 The creation of formal ‘interlinkages’Footnote 279 between different MEAs and the synergistic cooperation between various international actors of environmental governance attempts to minimise the side effects of that approach. Instead of asymmetrically overburdening the ICC with jurisdiction over any act causing mass environmental damage, which at this stage might not produce the desired results, the Court should employ its framework strategically as a means of enforcing certain environmental norms. This approach would also align with that pursued by other environmentally non-specialised ICTs including ITLOS, limiting its environmental purview to maritime degradation,Footnote 280 and ECtHR, proactively addressing human rights abuses in the context of environmental distress.Footnote 281 Although inherently constraining in its effects, the focus on environmental harms from the perspective of humanity will allow the Court to gradually develop its jurisprudence in a more environmentally-welcoming direction.

‘Environmental’ Potential of Article 21(3) of the Statute

These deficiencies in enforcing environmental protections through anthropocentric ends have to be acknowledged from the outset. Still, its statutory framework offers a certain degree of latitude to the ICC to develop its jurisprudence in a more environmentally-enlightened manner. The eco-centrically most problematic limitation of CAH—its narrow application to cases dealing exclusively with human suffering—builds an important bridge between ICL and IHRL. The victim-centrism of IHRL is compatible with the notion of ‘humanity’, which resides at the ontological heart of ICL,Footnote 282 notably reflected in the figure of CAH.Footnote 283 The protection of the same underlying legal interests establishes a conceptual unity between ICL and IHRL, with both seeking to uphold the ‘oneness and wholeness of humanity’.Footnote 284 The ICC is not a human rights court in the strict sense, but it has great significance for the global protection of the most fundamental human rights and values.Footnote 285 In line with Article 21(3) of the Statute, IHRL lays a ‘normative foundation’ for all crimes within the framework of the ICC,Footnote 286 guiding the Court in its further development. By requiring that the interpretation and application of the law are consistent with internationally recognised human rights standards, Article 21(3) of the Statute subordinates other sources of law described in Article 21Footnote 287 whilst providing ‘a standard against which all rules applied by the Court should be tested’.Footnote 288 As the Statute is silent on its scope,Footnote 289 Article 21(3) can consequently be interpreted as encompassing a rather broad array of rights. The phrase ‘internationally recognized human rights’ appears to embody something less than universal acceptance—‘understandable for an institution that is, after all, not yet universal itself’.Footnote 290 Although it is rather unlikely that the threshold of ‘international recognition’ encompasses norms limited to one region,Footnote 291 if the scope of acceptance is wider, permeating over more than one regional legal order, the right in question might attain the requisite level of acceptance. The open-ended terminology of Article 21(3) of the Statute appears to be in common with the evolutive character of most human rights instruments. Its ‘malleable’Footnote 292 but simultaneously dynamic ambit allows judges to draw on norms of IHRL as they develop over time and consider emerging trends within the domestic, regional, and international human rights discourses.

Towards a Universal Right to a Healthy Environment

As mentioned above,Footnote 293 national, regional, and international human rights bodies have already used affirmative human rights to achieve environmental protection.Footnote 294 From a substantive perspective, the primary factor driving the development of this synergistic relationship has been the increasing recognition of a right to an environment of a certain quality.Footnote 295 Though not yet recognised in a legally binding global instrument, the right to a healthy environment is explicitly included in, inter alia, the African Charter on Human and People’s Rights,Footnote 296 the 1988 Additional Protocol to the American Convention of Human Rights,Footnote 297 or the Arab Charter on Human Rights.Footnote 298 Relevant to the European context is the Additional Protocol to the ECHRFootnote 299 which directly builds upon the inherent interrelationship between environmental protection and human rightsFootnote 300 by highlighting principles such as environmental non-discrimination,Footnote 301 prevention, and non-regression.Footnote 302 The ’greened’ understanding of human rights has also reached the UN level, with the UN Human Rights Council (‘HRC’) unequivocally recognising the human right to a clean, healthy and sustainable environment for all peopleFootnote 303 and later the United Nations General Assembly (‘UNGA’) upholding its universal character.Footnote 304

Right to a Healthy Environment under the Statute

This mounting evidence explicitly reflects the demand for the universal recognition of an autonomous human right to a healthy environment. Its widespread usage underlines that environmental protection aspires to reach a comparable level of importance as other human interests that are fundamental to human dignity, equality, and freedom. As the current extent of its recognition reaches the status of an ‘internationally recognised human right’, it might be caught by the breadth of Article 21(3) of the Statute. This provision has the potential to broaden the ICC’s powers significantly as it applies to all sources of law in Article 21 of the Statute.Footnote 305 The effect of that provision has been the subject of vigorous discussion, with some narrowing it to a ‘mandatory principle of consistency’Footnote 306 and others contemplating that it establishes an additional source of law for the CourtFootnote 307 or even creates ‘a sort of international super-legality’.Footnote 308 All in all, Article 21(3) of the Statute establishes a positive roadmap that guides the interpretation and application of other statutory provisions. However, it would be a gross oversimplification to assume a symmetrical development between ICL and IHRL. Whilst mutually reinforcing, both fields do not develop symmetrically to one another. Their exchange prompts ‘greater depth of reasoning’ and enhances ‘the quality of judicial decisions’,Footnote 309 but the Court should avoid their deeper cross-fertilisation as it would misconstrue the ICC’s engagement with the regional human rights courts.Footnote 310 The fundamental point of divergence between both is the addressee of the prohibition: ICL focuses on the responsibility of individuals, whilst human rights institutions scrutinise state responsibility.Footnote 311 Both fields are not identical, but are not utterly separate, and international criminal courts and tribunals have relied upon human rights jurisprudence quite heavily.Footnote 312 As the Court applies instruments primarily limited to the specific cases before it,Footnote 313 its case law on the relationship between IHRL and ICL is yet to attain a high level of comprehension. International criminal justice fora have usually examined the regime of serious human rights violations within which a legal qualification of some events corresponds to one of their substantive provisions.Footnote 314 This approach aligns with the introduction to the Elements of Crimes which confirms that ‘the provisions of the Statute, including Article 21 (…) are applicable to the Elements of Crimes’.Footnote 315

On this note, it is relevant to highlight the close and complementary relationship between CAH and serious human rights violations. Although having autonomous roots, the CAH framework has progressed into an important manifestation of gross human rights violationsFootnote 316 and is regarded as ‘an implementation of human rights norms within international criminal law’.Footnote 317 Out of 11 CAH provisions included in the Statute, the crime of persecution as a CAH is one of the statutory exceptions that is defined in non-exhaustive terms, allowing for the possible extension of its scope in light of the dynamic evolution of IHRL. The Statute defines persecution as ‘intentional and severe deprivation of fundamental rights contrary to international law by reason of the identity of the group or collectivity’Footnote 318 that is ‘based on political, racial, national, ethnic, cultural, religious, gender (…) or other grounds that are universally recognized as impermissible under international law’.Footnote 319 The persecution must be committed ‘in connection with any act referred to in this paragraph [article 7] or any crime within the jurisdiction of the Court’.Footnote 320 The broad and vague formulation of ‘international and severe deprivation of fundamental rights’ and the open-ended list of other internationally impermissible grounds creates room for interpreting the CAH of persecution in various contexts. As held by the Pre-Trial Chamber I in Katanga, when drawing the contours of the crime of persecution,Footnote 321 judges can resort to IHRL to delimit the specific acts that fall within its prohibited ambit. For instance, there have been academic proposals to extend the CAH of persecution to incitement to hatredFootnote 322 or adopt a more ‘intersectional approach to interpret the complexity’ of the discriminatory effects of persecution.Footnote 323 Whilst not militating in favour of the symmetrical development between ICL and IHRL, this section calls for a more holistic and ‘greener’ analysis of two foundational requirements of the prohibition of persecution: (i) the intentional deprivation of one’s fundamental rights, and (ii) the occurrence of a discriminatory act or omission based on any of the listed grounds such as race, religion or politics.Footnote 324 With regards to the former, it seems possible to extend the open-ended list of ‘rights’ recognised as ‘fundamental’ under international law to cover the right to a healthy environment. In terms of the latter, an environmentally-minded read of ‘other grounds universally recognized as impermissible under international law’ would allow judges to highlight multiple forms of discrimination that occur at the intersection of one another, thus, bringing about a more comprehensive understanding of the discrimination in question. Operating from that perspective, one can more readily accept the prospects of expanding the crime of persecution to prohibit discriminatory human rights violations arising from environmental degradation.

First, the concept of ‘severe and intentional deprivation of fundamental rights’, according to Stakić, may subsume rights other than non-derogable rights,Footnote 325 that embrace acts or omissions of varying severity. Infringements on freedom, such as restrictions on family lifeFootnote 326 and other infringements upon individual freedom,Footnote 327 can also constitute a CAH of persecution. This relatively broad understanding of ‘fundamental’ human rights gives judges a sufficient level of discretion to take advantage of the ‘guiding effect’ of IHRL over the ICC.Footnote 328 As the ambit of ‘fundamental rights’ appears to represent a much broader category of human rights that does not have to reach the level of ‘universal jurisdiction’, it subsumes all ‘internationally recognized human rights’. Thus, by virtue of Article 21(3) of the Statute, the ICC judges could possibly weaponise the CAH of persecution against widespread or systematic violations of the right to a healthy environment. A detractor could question whether human rights law could, in fact, provide a basis for individual criminal responsibility. As rightly underlined by Cryer, it would be contrary to the principle of nullum crimen sine lege to convict someone of persecution based on a definition found in IHRL that was created for different purposes.Footnote 329 In Krajišnik, the Trial Chamber I confirmed that ‘not every denial of a fundamental human right will be serious enough to constitute a crime against humanity’.Footnote 330 This, however, has not prevented the ICTY Chambers from expanding the scope of the prohibition of persecution to cover socio-economic rights, including the rights of employment, freedom of movement, proper medical care, and proper judicial process.Footnote 331 Along these lines, and keeping in mind that a violation that forms the basis of persecutive acts needs not necessarily be criminalised under international law,Footnote 332 mass violations of the right to a healthy environment reaching the threshold of statutory severity could form part of the actus reus of persecution. In such a case, the ICC Prosecutor would have to prove that such abuse was of equal gravity to the crimes listed in Article 7(1) of the Statute.Footnote 333

Second, the expanding scope of ‘other grounds that are universally recognized as impermissible under international law’ allows for the inclusion of other persecutory grounds, including environmental discrimination. Article 7(1)(h) of the Statute encompasses all ‘widely recognized’ grounds without requiring all States to acknowledge a particular ground as impermissible.Footnote 334 In terms of other, not-explicitly mentioned discriminatory grounds, Nakhjavani, for example, proposed including ‘the ground of wrongful discrimination on the basis of disability’,Footnote 335 with the Convention on the Protection and Promotion of the Rights and Dignity of Persons with DisabilitiesFootnote 336 reflective of its ‘universal’ recognition as impermissible under international law.Footnote 337 Whilst drawing attention to the widespread issue of maltreatment of environmental human rights defenders, the HRC has already highlighted that environmentally-related persecution often arises from the interplay of multiple and intersecting forms of violence, including discrimination based on sex, gender, race, or religion.Footnote 338 Therefore, discrimination on environmentally-related grounds would seldom ensue from one persecutory ground; instead, it is likely to occur because of the simultaneous concurrence of two or more prohibited factors. For a successful charge of persecution, one discriminatory ground will suffice, ‘although a combination of more than one may equally form the basis for the discrimination’.Footnote 339 The additional consideration of persecution on environmentally-related grounds could thus improve the overall understanding of the kind of discrimination a particular group or minority has faced. Such an intersectional approach to discrimination is self-evident in the label ‘environmental racism’. The term dates back to the 1987 ‘Toxic Wastes and Race’ Case Study,Footnote 340 covering acts of ‘intentional or unintentional racial discrimination’ in, for example, environmental policy or law-making.Footnote 341 It brings attention to the heightened environmental threats faced by minority groups: higher levels of lead exposure, higher risks of facing catastrophic flooding, or poorer air quality.Footnote 342 The 2001 Durban Declaration already underlined the need to view environmental issues through the lens of racial discrimination,Footnote 343 and the Chair of the UN Working Group of Experts on People of African Descent called for recognition of the racial dimension of the climate crisis.Footnote 344

Persecution on account of systematic environmental degradation or sustained failure of state protection in relation to the right to a healthy environment—which might, but does not have to, intersect with other discriminatory grounds—could result, for example, in forced displacements driven by environmental injustice.Footnote 345 By way of illustration, in Iran, water scarcity is a significant environmental stressor driving Rojhelati Kurds from their ancestral lands. The 2014 environmental report revealed that 26 of 30 dams constructed in the provinces of West Azerbaijan, East Azerbaijan, and Kurdistan benefit Azeri Turks, a predominantly Shi’a ethnic group, while Kurdish-majority areas are frequently denied infrastructure projects.Footnote 346 Such deliberate discriminatory policies clearly deprive the targeted community members of their right to a healthy environment. As highlighted above,Footnote 347 apart from environmentally driven relocation, persecution on environmentally-related grounds could be utilised as a tool to combat repression towards environmental activists and land campaigners.Footnote 348 Mexico, the Philippines, and Colombia recorded widespread targeting, including lethal attacks on defenders of environmental human rights and communities across the countries.Footnote 349 Numerous activists have been persecuted for protests against nuclear power plant constructions in Belarus and Russia.Footnote 350 All these examples of persecutory acts could be potentially caught by the breadth of Article 7(1)(h) of the Statute. This conclusion aligns with the latest report of the Special Rapporteur on human rights obligations relating to the enjoyment of a healthy environment in which he calls on States to protect environmental human rights defenders from ‘intimidation, criminalization and violence’ and ‘diligently investigate, prosecute and punish the perpetrators of those crimes’.Footnote 351

An Enriching Possibility?

Reading the open-ended scope of CAH of persecution alongside a ‘greener’ interpretation and application of Article 21(3) of the Statute would allow judges to build an important grounding for a re-orientation of ICL towards a broader, multidimensional environmental protection. The evolutive scope of Article 21(3) of the Statute invites creative engagement with IHRL but cautions against crossing the dichotomy between IHRL and ICL as it would ultimately strip one or the other of carrying a particular function. As the ICC is ‘bound to adhere to the letter of the provisions aimed at only reprimanding conduct the drafters expressly intended to criminalise’,Footnote 352 the primary difficulty facing judges would be to strike a proper balance between the effects of IHRL over ICL. Gebhard calls for ‘precaution when invoking human rights law in substantive ICL’ and argues that Article 21(3) of the Statute cannot be relied upon for applying extra-statutory substantive law.Footnote 353 This premise is convincing, but it seems to disregard the fact that few provisions, including the prohibition of persecution, are listed non-exhaustively in the Statute, thus creating room for judges to expand their substantive ambit by reference to IHRL.

Such an extension, however, can be regarded as a stark contravention of nullum crimen sine lege. On the one hand, one could argue that the ‘accessorial design’ of the crime—conditioning a finding of a charge of persecution on the presence of any act referred to in paragraph of Article 7 or any crime within the jurisdiction of the Court—already limits the breadth of the prohibition.Footnote 354 Additionally, the qualifier of a ‘fundamental’ human rights violation and the threshold clause of ‘severe deprivation’ are further attempts towards reconciling the dynamic development of IHRL with nullum crimen sine lege.Footnote 355 On the other hand, from a strictly legalistic viewpoint, directly transplanting IHRL corpus to the field of international criminal justice to (re)define international crimes remains highly dubious. The application of the IHRL on the right to a healthy environment to the interpretation of the CAH of persecution would lead to the creation of a new fundamental violation under the Statute, criminalizing what was initially perceived to be a human rights violation. That technique of directly incorporating IHRL norms to ICL is not alien to the practice of the ICC and other international criminal courts and tribunals alike. The Akayesu Trial Judgement was one of the first ICL decisions in which the ICTR judges relied directly on IHRL instruments to define and broader the remits of the CAH of rape.Footnote 356 Most recently, whilst interpreting the scope of Article 7(1)(k) of the Statute, the Myanmar PTC I directly transposed the right to return from IHRL to find that its violation caused ‘great suffering, or serious injury […] to mental […] health’, deepening the anguish of the victims and compelling them to live in deplorable conditions.Footnote 357 In a similar vein, the Appeal Chamber in Ongwen, after restating that the scope of the CAH of other inhumane acts can be delineated by reference to any relevant IHRL instrument,Footnote 358 reaffirmed that forcing one to freely enter into a marriage violates the fundamental right to marry and amounts to an inhumane act.Footnote 359 Thus, the regime of IHRL already serves a gap-filling function in the practice of international criminal courts and tribunals, and it has provided significant guidance in (re)interpreting the definitions of certain international crimes. Yet, as underlined above, if this cross-fertilisation develops in an unbridled manner, it risks crossing the dichotomy between both sub-divisions of international law and might lead to arbitrary expansion of ICL’s reach. Legal borrowings from different regimes are not per se objectionable if re-contextualised to the recipient system.Footnote 360 Accordingly, without adjusting the remits of the borrowed IHRL’s definition, such as on the right to a healthy environment, the ICC judges would be granted unparalleled power to adjudge what should be unjust and hence criminalised. That being said, this section detracts from advocating in favour of literally importing the IHRL’s rationale on the right to a healthy environment to the field of ICL. Instead, from the perspective of legality, any such proposition demands utmost caution and will have to be abandoned if its inclusion costs diluting the integrity of ICL. Another cogent argument against the practice of gleaning from IHRL different human rights violations that arise to ‘crimes of an international concern’ is that it endangers the inflation of ICL and undermines one of the primary justifications fueling its developments: the focus on ‘the most serious crimes’. This counter-argument will have to be revisited in case any material debates on the future place of the right to a healthy environment in the framework of international criminal justice unfold.

Although a purely theoretical avenue, this argument highlights a possible line of progressing with regard to the right to a healthy environment and persecution on environmentally-related grounds within the framework of the ICC. Such a human-centric recourse strategy would allow the ICC to enrich its legal system by reference to a more ‘experienced’ and environmentally welcoming sub-system—IHRL—that has directly relied upon the principles of environmental to specify human rights obligations.Footnote 361 Again, it has to be re-emphasised that any such legal transplantation would require appropriate re-contextualisation to the needs and demands of ICL.

Contextual Elements

Even though CAH framework creates a certain degree of latitude for the ICC Prosecutor to propose creative avenues for delivering environmental justice, the possible level of environmental protection is curtailed by the specific context necessary to support a conviction. In line with Article 7(1) of the Statute, the contemporary definition of CAH requires the commission of a listed prohibited act in the context of ‘a widespread or systematic attack directed against any civilian population, with knowledge of the attack’.Footnote 362 According to their ordinary meaning, CAH are contingent upon showing harm to humans and their property.Footnote 363 Most prominently, the requisite element of ‘an ‘attack’ against any civilian population’ effectively precludes any extension of the objects of criminal protection. Thus, the only feasible strategy is to consider environmental degradation as a means to target civilian populations. The requirement of ‘a State or organizational policy to commit such attack’ provides another limitation to the effective reliance on CAH provisions. The Elements of Crimes explain that a ‘“policy to commit such attack” requires that the State or organization actively promotes or encourages such an attack against a civilian population’.Footnote 364 According to the ad hoc tribunals, ‘[t]here is no requirement that this policy must be adopted formally as the policy of a state’,Footnote 365 nor must the policy or plan ‘necessarily be declared expressly or even stated clearly and precisely’.Footnote 366 Iran’s policy of torturing and executing environmental activists who campaigned against development policies destroying Iran’s biggest lake,Footnote 367 would potentially meet the formal requirements of organisational structure and control. In the context of attacks on environmental human rights defenders, the data reflects that, in most instances, it is the State and its actors which initiate acts of persecution, punishment, and harassment of environmentalists.Footnote 368 The implementation of deliberately tough legislative and regulatory measures against NGOs and their members, including those defending the environment, is part of a growing trend.Footnote 369 In addition, such a policy ‘may, in exceptional circumstances, be implemented by a deliberate failure to take action, which is consciously aimed at encouraging such attack’.Footnote 370 In the context of economically beneficial developmental activities, one could consider holding governments to account for their systematic omission to provide effective protection and remedies. Finally, the ICC Prosecutor would have to demonstrate the existence of the remaining contextual elements which demand that such ‘an attack’ be ‘widespread’ or ‘systematic’ and consistent with a ‘course of conduct involving the multiple commission of acts’.Footnote 371 In the context of acts of persecution on the grounds of environmentally-related persecution, the possible extension and systematic nature of such conduct ‘may in itself amount to a widespread or systematic attack’.Footnote 372

CONCLUDING REMARKS

The entangled character of environmental hazards—occurring at the intersection of different branches of international law with distinct approaches, values, and expertise—precludes any environmentally unspecialised body from fusing those different perspectives into a cohesive whole. This narrative aligns with the current mainstream understanding of the role of ICTs, yielding an essential yet secondary function in addressing environmental concerns. The figure of ‘humanity’ at the heart of ICL, IHRL and IHL likewise, encapsulated in different elements depending on the context of the offence (eg CAH and the ‘civilian population’ element or war crimes and ‘the principle of humanity’), compounded by the legal rigidity and specificity of ICL provisions, undermines effective reconciliation between ICL and IEL.

This discussion proposed a middle-ground solution: instead of surrendering the pursuit of environmental justice before the ICC or risking the implementation of too hasty innovations, the focus should be re-oriented on maximising the ‘environmental’ potential of the current substantive framework. The mechanisms of prosecutorial and judicial discretion ought to be employed in a more progressive and environmentally-enlightened manner to underscore the codependency between global peace and environmental health. As the ICC is not a ‘closed system’ but an organ having a broader expressive functionFootnote 373 with the ability to catalyse normative developments, its symbolic and deterrent functions should not be underestimated in the fight for environmental justice. Integrating an environmentally-friendly perspective into the interpretation and application of its statutory prohibitions, reinforced by a ‘greened’ analysis of other sub-divisions of international law richer in environmentally-minded case law, would push ICL’s further developments in a more holistic direction. Such an explicit recognition of significant adverse impacts of environmental insecurity and fragility of the ecosystem would further reinforce IEL’s principle of prevention through the prism of ‘humanity’. The Al Bashir case provides an important precedent in this regard, which should initiate further investigations and prosecutions in that environmentally-inclusive direction. The dynamic proliferation of domestic, regional, and international instruments on the right to a healthy environment also merits the closer attention of the Court. Although a violation of the right to a healthy environment remains not a criminal but human rights issue, its rapid and widespread development seems to merit the prediction that there might come a time when it will become enforceable through national, regional, or international criminal sanctions. The approach of enforcing environmental protection via anthropocentrically-minded prohibitions is not free of limitations. It might neglect the expressive value of ICL by reducing the environment to an indirect victim of harm veering towards selective environmental protection without looking beyond its substantive surface. These constraints have to be accepted from the outset as the ‘Statute is not an environmental document’.Footnote 374

It must be noted that the inclusion of an ‘ecocide’ provision would not necessarily provide a viable solution to the selectivity dilemma. If adopted, it would only be applicable against the gravest instances of environmental degradation, reaching the threshold of severe and either widespread or long-term damage to the environment, whilst bypassing a vast number of cases falling outside the requisite scope of gravity. Furthermore, the successful addition of an amendment might not automatically result in the ICC’s being readily able and willing to address mass international environmental degradation. In a similar manner to Article 8(2)(b)(iv) of the Statute, the Prosecutor might be reluctant to propose the first ‘ecocide’ charge, reducing the amendment to a purely symbolic success. So far, apart from Al Bashir,Footnote 375 the ICC Prosecutor has not focused on environmental attacks as a means ‘to achieve a destructive humanitarian impact’.Footnote 376 Once this status quo is broken, the evidence of the ICC becoming attentive to mass environmental hazards might have instrumental effects on the future of ‘ecocide’ within the domestic and international legal frameworks.

This article does not attempt to undermine the ‘ecocide’ debate acknowledging that there might come a moment when the time would be right to harness the power of ICL to protect the environment, whether before the ICC or any other mechanism. Before any serious steps are taken in this direction, the relationship between precaution and legality and the questions of mens rea and individual or (possibly) corporate liability in the context of mass environmental damage ought to be clarified. States must also take a more active stance on the issue by introducing domestic provisions penalizing mass environmental damage and initiating investigations and prosecutions on their possible violations. In the meantime, with the general ICE remaining an insurmountable normative ambition, the orientations should be altered to optimise the potential of existing legal frameworks, buttressing each other in that collective environmentally-minded effort. Any such cross-sectoral interactions ought to be steered by the principle of legality in order to maintain the integrity of ICL. This boils down to one conclusion: at present, simple reliance on the current statutory framework might be better and more effective than an elaborate embellishment.