Abstract
In an unpublished appendix to his Organization of Inquiry (“Flatland Revisited”) Gordon Tullock develops and extends ideas from both Ludwig von Mises and Karl Popper. We first discuss these commonalities and extensions, which center on the notions of necessary truth and reciprocity. Then we recover the manuscript history as well as comments from James Buchanan and provide an answer to the question of why the manuscript was never published.
This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution.
Notes
Feigenbaum and Levy (1993) make clear their debts to Tullock for long discussions about the problem of replication in economics.
Tullock ([1966] 2005, p. xix]. Tullock tells us that he’d never met Michael Polanyi. Polanyi gave a lecture series for the Thomas Jefferson Center in November 1961 but there is correspondence in which Tullock writes about the manuscript he gave Polanyi. Tullock’s well-known problem with memory may have started very early. We thank John Nye.
Where does Organization fit in the Tullock opus? We know from Jeremy Shearmur’s reconstruction of Karl Popper’s lecture series at Emory University (25 June–6 July 1956), which Tullock attended, that the Tullock–Popper connection is much earlier than Tullock’s association with the economists of the Thomas Jefferson Center. In a letter to Popper and Joseph Agassi of July 9, 1958, Tullock writes about his upcoming fellowship at the University of Virginia where he planned to work on a book entitled Organization of Inquiry: “I have been giving some thought to coming over to London. My program would call for writing a book essentially based on the Logic [of Scientific Discovery?] I think maybe I have discovered a third system of Positional Logic the subject matter of which may be indicated by my provisional title: The Organization of Inquiry. The problems are two, in the first place I am not certain my theory of right, and secondly, it may be too trivial to bother with. The positional logic of Inside Bureaucracy is much less elaborate than that of economics, and my latest theory is even less so. At any event, I would like to get the Logic as soon as possible, and after further thought in Virginia I might be able to decide definitely.” The predatory aspects we discuss in Levy and Peart (2012), the analysis of tariffs and the unlocated reference in Hobbes, were initially in a third appendix—”On the Backwardness of the Social Sciences.” (Tullock Papers, Box 91). The initial reader’s report to Duke University Press, suggested making it into a chapter (16 April 1963). Tullock Papers, Box 108 Correspondence Folder. Copyright Stanford University.
The traditional view is discussed in Lemmon ([1966] 1977, pp. 1–11). All of the systems Lewis proposed allow this inference. Prior ([1955], 1962, p. 311) gives the axioms for the original Lewis systems and (pp. 312–13) for Lemmon’s Gödelized reaxiomatization. In Lewis’s axiomization taking “strict implication” as primitive, the actual strictly implies the possible; the Gödelized version has the necessary implying the actual.
von Wright describes his contribution: “… the conception of modal logic as a superstructure, or ‘second story’, to be erected—like quantification theory—on the basis of the logic of propositions … (I later learnt that the idea was not entirely novel. It can be traced back to a short paper by Gödel from the early 1930s and to a paper by Feys from 1937).” Von Wright (1989, p. 29).
Lemmon ([1966] 1977, p. 50) credits the weakening from □α → α to □α → ◊α to von Wright’s deontic logic in which “necessary” is taken as “obligatory.” In this context it is implausible to suppose that the actual follows from the obligatory (von Wright 1951, p. 41). In Robert Feys’ comprehensive account, “System 1” [Lewis S1] is constructed from a modal grammar developed in “System 10 “plus the axiom that the actual strictly implies the possible (Feys 1965, p. 64). Tullock’s contribution might be seen as proposing a non-normative interpretation as an alternative to von Wright’s.
Popper ([1959] 1974, p. 78): “Duhem denies (Engl. Transl. p. 188) the possibility of crucial experiments, because he thinks of them as verifications, while I assert the possibility of crucial falsifying experiments.” In the Postscript Popper (1983, p. 178) offers an holistic approach in which theoretic systems are tested as wholes. It is unclear that there is any difference between a later Popperian approach and that of Quine (1960). In his letter to Popper and Agassiz of July 9, 1958, Tullock acknowledges receipt of reprints of Popper articles. He writes that he has seen the one on Duhem. Taking Duhem seriously, then we can explain Tullock’s giving more emphasis on replication and less on testing than is common. Replication for Tullock is testing without the desire to find one’s own model true. Congleton helped us here.
Alex Tabarrok and Peter Boettke tell us they had similar conversations. Ours (August 31, 2006) was prompted by a conversation earlier that summer between Tullock and James Buchanan about the Calculus of Consent at a session of the Summer Institute for the Preservation of the History of Economics.
Tullock 1971a, 2:375: “(It may seem odd to place an article originally designed for publication in a biological journal in a collection of articles to Ludwig von Mises. Among his other distinctions, Professor von Mises was among the first to point out that economics can be expanded to deal with many areas outside of its traditional scope. In my own case, my work in expanding economics into new areas was, in a real sense, begun by my reading of Human Action. The article below, then, represents my most extreme application of economics outside its pre-von Mises boundaries)”.
Von Mises ([1927] 1966, p. 176): “For the few who apply higher standards to the activities of political parties, who demand that even in political action the categorical imperative be followed (‘Act only on that principle which you can will at the same time to be a universal law, i.e., so that no contradiction results from the attempt to conceive of your action as a law to be universally complied with’), the ideology of the parties of special interests certainly has nothing to offer.” Emphasis added.
When Scott Scheall’s research is published we will know much more about the discussions concerning logic between von Mises and the formidable mathematician Karl Menger.
Daniel Nientiedt first asked this question.
Tullock Papers, Box 107, Folder labeled: “G. Tullock Organization of Inquiry (3/3) Draft w/comments”. Copyright Stanford University.
The original typescript is found in the Tullock Papers, Box 109, Folder “Tullock Organization of Inquiry (3/3).” Reproductions are found in the Tullock Papers, Box 91, Folder “Organization of Inquiry Appendices” and Box 389, Folder 389.8 among others. Copyright Stanford University.
Tullock Papers, Box 42. This in an orange binder in an unlabeled folder. Copyright Stanford University.
This is found in the same orange binder in the unlabeled folder in Tullock Papers, Box 42 in which we found State Three. State Four is also of interest as it is no longer labelled as Appendix 2. Copyright Stanford University.
Flatland, A Romance of Many Dimensions, A. Square, (Edwin A, Abbott). The work has gone through numerous editions. I refreshed my memory with the Basil Blackwell Oxford edition of 1926 and all page citations are to this version.
P. 79.
See “Explanation and Prediction in Evolutionary Theory” by Scriven, Science, August 28, 1959, p. 477.
Bent within the plane in which the Flatlanders imagine themselves living, of course. Many of the lines are bent, as we third dimension dwellers can see, but they are bent quite differently than the Flatlanders believe.
References
Boettke, P. J., & Leeson, P. T. (2006). Introduction: The economist as system builder: Ludwig von Mises as the architect of economic science and political economy. In P. J. Boettke & P. T. Leeson (Eds.), The legacy of Ludwig von Mises (pp. xi–xx). Cheltenham: Elgar.
Feigenbaum, S., & Levy, D. M. (1993). The market for (Ir)reproducible econometrics. Social Epistemology, 7, 215–232.
Feys, R. (1965). Modal logics. In J. Dopp (Ed.). Louvain: E. Nauwelaerts.
Friedman, M. (1991). Say no to intolerance. Inquiry, 4, 17–20.
Gasparski, W. W. (1996). Between logic and ethics: The origin of praxiology. Axiomathes, 7, 385–394.
Gödel, K. ([1933]1986). An interpretation of the intuitionistic propositional calculus. In S. Feferman, J. W. Dawson Jr., S. C. Kleene, G. H. Moore, R. M. Solovay, & J. van Heijenoort (Eds.), Volume 1 of Collected Works (pp. 301–302). Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Gordon Tullock Papers, Hoover Institution. http://www.oac.cdlib.org/findaid/ark:/13030/kt787034zq/entire_text/
Kirzner, I. M. (2001). Ludwig von Mises: The man and his economics. Wilmington: ISI Books.
Lemmon, E. J. ([1966]1977). An introduction to modal logic: The Lemmon notes. In K. Segerberg (Ed.). Oxford: Blackwell.
Levy, D. M., & Peart, S. J. (2012). Tullock on motivated inquiry: Expert-induced uncertainty disguised as risk. Public Choice, 153, 163–180.
Levy, D. M., & Peart, S. J. (2017). Escape from democracy: Experts and the public in economic policy. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Peart, S. J., & Levy, D. M. (2008). Discussion, construction and evolution: Mill, Buchanan and Hayek on the constitutional order. Constitutional Political Economy, 19, 3–18.
Peart, S. J., & Levy, D. M. (2015). On ‘strongly fortified minds’: Self-restraint and cooperation in the discussion tradition. In E. Chamlee-Wright (Ed.), Liberal learning and the art of self-governance. New York: Taylor and Francis.
Popper, K. R. (1983). Realism and the aim of science. From the postscript to logic of scientific discovery. In W. W. Bartley III (Ed.). London: Routledge.
Popper, K. R. ([1959]1974). Logic of scientific discovery. London: Hutchinson.
Prior, A. N. ([1955]1962). Formal logic. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Quine, W. V. O. (1960). Word and object. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Sir Karl Raimund Popper Papers. (1928–1995). Hoover Institution. http://pdf.oac.cdlib.org/pdf/hoover/reg_189.pdf
Tideman, N. (2015). Gordon Tullock and the demand-revealing process. George Mason University Tullock Conference. http://rdc1.net/Tullock%20Memorial%20Conference/Tideman_Gordon%20Tullock%20and%20the%20Demand.pdf
Tideman, N., & Tullock, G. (1976). A new and superior process for making social choices. Journal of Political Economy, 84, 1145–1159.
Tullock, G. (1959). The problem of majority voting. Journal of Political Economy, 67, 571–579.
Tullock, G. (1966). The organization of inquiry. Durham: Duke University Press.
Tullock, G. (1967). The welfare costs of tariffs, monopolies, and theft. Western Economic Journal, 5, 224–232.
Tullock, G. (1971). An application of economics in biology. In F. A. von Hayek, H. Hazlitt, L. E. Read, G. R. Velasco, & F. A. Harper (Eds.), Toward liberty: Essays in honour of Ludwig von Mises on the occasion of his 90th birthday, September 29, 1971 (vol. 2, pp. 375–91). Menlo Park: Institute for Humane Studies.
Tullock, G. (1971b). Charity of the uncharitable. Western Economic Journal, 9, 379–392.
Tullock, G. (1971c). The coal tit as a careful shopper. American Naturalist, 105, 77–80.
Tullock, G. (2002). People are people: The elements of public choice. In G. Tullock, A. Seldon, & G. L. Brady (Eds.), Government failure: A primer in public choice (pp. 3–16). Washington DC: CATO Institute.
Tullock, G. ([1966]2005). The organization of inquiry. In C. K. Rowley (Ed.), Volume 3 of Selected Works of Gordon Tullock. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.
Von Mises, L. (1949). Human action. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Von Mises, L. ([1927]1966). The free and prosperous commonwealth (Trans Raico, R.). Princeton: D. Van Nostrand.
Von Wright, G. H. (1951). An essay in modal logic. Amsterdam: North-Holland.
Von Wright, G. H. (1989). Intellectual autobiography of Georg Henrik von Wright. In P. A. Schlipp & L. E. Hahn (Eds.), The philosophy of Georg Henrik von Wright (pp. 1–55). La Salle, IL: Open Court.
Acknowledgements
Earlier versions were presented at the 2015 meetings of the Public Choice Society, the Summer Institute for the History of Economics at the University of Richmond’s Jepson School of Leadership Studies, the George Mason Conference to remember Gordon Tullock and at a History of Economics Society Panel at the Allied Social Sciences Association in January 2016. An informal seminar at the Public Choice Center with John Nye, Trey Dudley and David Coker in October 2016 helped clarify some issues. Ron Basich helped with the collection of the Tullock-Popper correspondence. R. August Hardy helped check the paper. Jane Perry helped with the transcription of “Flatland Revisited” as well as the paper itself. Jeremy Shearmur gave us much insight into the early Tullock–Popper connection. Daniel Nientiedt asked a very helpful question in San Francisco. We are grateful for access to the Hoover Institute archives. Alex Tabarrok has been a source of much enthusiasm, encouragement and many resources. Roger Congleton and the referees of CPE gave us a list of wonderful questions for us to think about. Our thanks to all! The surviving mistakes are our responsibility. We are grateful for permission granted to us to publish Gordon Tullock’s words by Mary Lou Gunderson and by Carol A. Leadenham of the Hoover Institution; to publish James Buchanan’s words by Jo Ann Burgess; to publish Ashbel Brice’s words by Diane Grossé of Duke University Press.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Appendices
Appendix: The manuscript and James Buchanan’s comments
Correspondence between Tullock and Duke University Press demonstrates that “Flatland Revisited” was excluded by editorial decision because it would have been too demanding on the reader. The letter from Duke University Press’s editor (Ashbel Brice) on 13 August 1965 writes about the decision: “I think the explanation of why “Flatland Revisited” loses me is to be found in your opening sentence: ‘Practically every mathematics student…’ That eliminates me. In looking for our reader’s advice that these be eliminated, I noted that our critic admonished you not to overestimate the information of your readers.” The photograph of the opening footnote (Fig. 1) has a struck out sentence predicting the fate of the appendix.
The decision not to ask Hayek for the preface that he offered, something Tullock noted in the letter submitting the manuscript to Duke (Tullock 3 January 1963) seems to have been made because of the predicted controversy (Brice to Tullock 23 March 1965). One ought to note that Tullock was enormously pleased by “extraordinarily handsome book” which the Press created (Tullock to John Langley) on 15 December 1966. All of these letters are in the Tullock Papers, Box 108, Correspondence Folder in the Tullock Papers.
We can identify four states of the manuscript of “Flatland Revised” in the Tullock papers. First, there is a hand-corrected typescript with a color pen which surely was not produced professionally.Footnote 14
This is of interest because it was the manuscript upon which James Buchanan comments. The line struck out in red suggests the problem Tullock would face with Duke’s editor.
The second state is a professional typescript. This exists in the original form, the cutting of the paper by metal strikes is decisive, and in several reproductions.Footnote 15 The third state is a hand-corrected carbon copy of the second state:Footnote 16 This is the basis for our transcription of the manuscript below. The difference between a typescript and a carbon copy is clear by observing the relative sharpness of the letters (Fig. 2).
There is also a typescript that encompasses these hand-marked corrections (State Four).Footnote 17 We find this an unreliable text. Tullock writes to Brice at Duke (15 April 1964) that “the Flatlanders parable, has also been omitted. Since I liked this appendix I have arranged the draft so that it could be easily replaced.” He goes on to describe the problem he had finding a competent typist: “After seeing the product I have decided she will never work for me again.” Indeed, we found omitted lines in the typescript that were not corrected. Even though State Four is surely made from State Three, we trust it only as a guide to Tullock’s oblique directions in his hand correction.
What we reprint next is in our judgment the final state of Tullock’s ill-fated appendix.
Appendix 2: Flatland Revisited
Practically every mathematics student at one time or another has read FLATLAND,Footnote 18 Abbott’s instructive tale of an inhabitant of a two dimensional world and of how he had the existence of a third dimension proved to him by a being who removed from his two dimensional world, “Flatland,” and showed him a three dimensional continuum. The book, as written, gives a false impression, particularly through its title. The land in which A. Square lived was not flat. If we were to view his two dimensional world from the outside, we would quickly recognize that it was as irregular in shape as the surface of any other world. The failure of Mr. Square to notice this fact during the period when he was outside the two dimensional world may be put down partially to the limitations on his opportunities for observation and partly to the hereditary constitution of the mind of an inhabitant of this universe which might better be called “Bentland.”
Mr. Square was only outside his two dimensional world for a short time, and his state of emotional and intellectual shock during that period was such as to make it unlikely that he would make any very careful observations of the environment in which he found himself. Further, he seems mostly to have been interested in observing the inhabitants and structures of his native land rather than the physical structure of the land itself. In addition, when he first left his two dimensional world, he was quite incapable of appreciating the nature of any surface other than a flat one. It was only after his guide, Mr. Sphere, had carefully explained this idea to him with the help of a cube that he began to perceive the possibility of non-flat surfaces. In the short and exciting period remaining he can be excused for not noticing the irregular nature of his native world.
The question remains of why his instructor, the sphere, did not acquaint him with this feature of his world. As a being fully conversant with the three dimensional world within which the two dimensional “Flatland” lay, he can hardly have been unaware of its irregular nature. Indeed, he refers to “the plains of Flatland”Footnote 19* and plains are not absolutely level areas, but gently rolling nearly flat areas. Further, “plains” naturally is put in opposition to other terms like mountains, canyons, and hills, and Mr. Sphere, therefore, must be taken to have known that, while the bulk of the inhabitants of Flatland lived in a relatively level area, there were numerous pronounced irregularities in their two dimensional world particularly in its less settled parts.
Shortage of time, as we have said, may have led the sphere to avoid this subject, but it may also have seemed useless to him in view of his great knowledge of the inhabitants of “Flatland.” For it is a fact that the minds of these dwellers is so constituted that they cannot conceive of their land as anything except flat. It is possible that the sphere might have succeeded in convincing Mr. Square that deviation from flatness was theoretically possible, but he could never have given him a real appreciation of what a two dimensional continuum which was irregular rather than flat when viewed from a three dimensional space was like. This peculiarity of the minds of Flatlanders has occasioned much interest among the inhabitants of “Spaceland” and the savants of the area have devoted much time to speculating on its origin. To an account of the results of this discussion, I shall shortly turn. After briefly indicating the principle points of view expressed in this debate, I shall then describe the effect of the concurrence of irregularities and minds inherently unable to think of such things on science in “Flatland.” Finally, I shall explain what may not be obvious to some of my readers, what all of this has to do with us.
Among the scholars of spaceland there are quite a number of views on how the “Flatlanders” came to have minds which are incapable of thinking of their world as anything but flat. One thread unites all of these theories, however; all the savants are agreed that the Flatlanders evolved from lower forms and that the present constitution of their minds must be the product of that evolution. The exact evolutionary process is the only matter which divides them although there are sufficient grounds for division within this sphere to permit the development of a large number of warring schools of thought.
The first and, in some ways, most influential of these schools of thought holds that evolution necessarily proceeds from the simple to the complex. One-celled species necessarily preceded multi-celled and the Amphibia preceed the lizards. It seems likely, therefore, that the first brain which could really think, in the course of evolution would be the simplest type. Clearly, it is easier and simpler to think in terms of a flat two dimensional surface than in terms of an irregular one. It is, therefore, easy to see why the Flatlanders all have such simplified brains. Whether, in time, further evolution will lead to further development is, of course, a mere matter of opinion.Footnote 20
A second school of thought, in part allied with the first, holds simply that a brain which could think in terms of a wavy two dimensional continuum would have had little evolutionary value at the time the race originally was formed. It is an undoubted historical fact that the race of Flatlanders first developed in the relatively level part of their world, and in this area an appreciation of the minor irregularities in the landscape would have been of little help to primitive tribesmen trying to catch wild animals while at the same time avoiding being caught themselves. While such a set of mental equipment would have had little or no positive evolutionary value, this school points out that it would most certainly have had a negative value. In the first place, the mind which was capable of considering that its two dimensional world varied in an almost inconceivable third dimension would necessarily be larger than one which could not, and this would be an additional weight for the organism to carry around. Further, most genes have multiple effects. The genes which gave the mind this power, then would probably have other effects on the organism, and, if these were negative, even if only mildly so, the whole effect would be to secure the elimination of individuals with such equipment from the race in its earliest stages of evolutionary development.
Once the race had developed with this type of mind, any mutation to another type with an ability to think in other terms than a completely flat universe would have been of negative evolutionary value due to the fact that the non-mutated members of the race would undoubtedly consider the mutant insane. Further, the advantage which such a mutation would give would be very slight to non-existent since only a very small part of the race would, at any given time, be doing things which required the new type of mind. The mutant, being different from his fellows in precisely such a field would probably find that, in those areas where he had a superiority, he would be distrusted by his colleagues, and, consequently, would not be permitted to work, or if he did, his results would not be accepted. Altogether, the “civilized” environment is most unfavorable to the survival of genetic mutations radically different from the prevailing type of mentality, and once a race of one basic mind type has become established, it is unlikely to be replaced by another.
The two remaining schools of thought are less influential than the two we have discussed so far. One holds that there are quite a number of mind types possible for such a race as the Flatlanders, and that it is largely a question of chance and the detailed historical development of the evolutionary process which determines which one any race will have. Once a mind of any type is achieved, however, it immediately gives the species holding it a major competitive advantage over the other, less intelligent, species. This species is then likely to establish its dominance over its environment and, for reasons similar to those given by our previous group of scholars, it forms an unfavorable environment for any mutation which might lead to a different way of thinking.
The last group of savants, in radical opposition to all of the others, holds that the limitation on the Flatlanders’ minds which makes it impossible for them to think of their world as other than flat arises essentially from chemical rather than biological factors. They point out that a brain is essentially a carefully arranged collection of chemicals, and they point out that only some chemicals can exist in Flatland, those which have molecules in which the atoms are arranged in three dimensional lattices being, ex definitione, ruled out. This means that there are natural limits on the types of mind which can be constructed, and these savants hold that these limits happen to forbid the construction of a mind which can think of its environment in other than flat terms.
Clearly, our present knowledge of the nature of biological organisms is not great enough to permit us to determine which of these schools of thought is correct. Perhaps none of them are or perhaps the truth involves some sort of compromise between them. Nevertheless, it would seem clear that the development of such a limited mind as the Flatlanders have would be evolutionarily possible. Certainly, the Flatlanders have these limits built into their minds, and never succeed in thinking of their world as anything but flat.
The effect of this limitation on the minds of the Flatlanders has been most peculiar. In the early days of their civilization, it had almost no influence. They learned to make various things and used simple geometric forms in their construction, but surveying did not develop as a science due to the fact, of course, that forms of any size would have widely varying characteristics, depending on where it happened to be located. Eventually, formal geometry was invented (although it was not called “earth measuring”) and carried to quite a high level of development. This development, however, eventually led to a crisis which destroyed the simple symmetry of the geometric view of nature. A leading geometrician decided to apply his learning on a large field and attempted to determine the distance between two points by triangulation. The irregularity of the surface at this point was such that his computed results were greatly different from directly measured distance. The experiment was repeated by a number of other scholars at other points and the uniformly disappointing results may be said to have constituted the most important revolution in scientific thought in the entire history of Flatland. The eventual outcome was the conclusion by most scientists that simple geometry was only an approximation of reality. Although normally a close approximation for small figures, even there it was not exact and for larger figures it was almost useless.
The result of this revolution in science was the development as the largest, most important, and most difficult area of scientific investigation of the field of surveying. Mr. Square does not mention this in his brief summary of the characteristics of his land for much the same reasons which would lead an average inhabitant of our country to omit the Einstein theory from a brief account of its nature. Among the scientists, however, the various problems of surveying are a continuous preoccupation. Making careful measurements of various figures on the surface which is thought to be flat, and then trying to develop theories fitting these measurements is a major scientific activity. Probably the most important and certainly the only generally applicable of these theories is the theory which “proves” the existence of inherent limitations on the accuracy of measuring instruments. Needless to say, this is a great help in fitting other theories to the measured data.
All the other theories are regional in nature. That is the theory [which] will attempt to explain the variations in some particular locality. As of today, there are such theories for only a small part of the total area of the country, but the scientists of Flatland are most optimistic about the possibilities of further development. They point out that the history of surveying has been one of steadily accelerating progress. In the last 50 years, in particular, many new areas have been “explained,” and many older, rather inaccurate, theories explaining areas have been replaced by new and better explanations, They look forward to an accelerating process of expansion of the area covered by their theories and hope eventually to find a “general surveying theory” which will provide a single equation which covers the whole country. To the outside observer, the problem appears more difficult. Since he knows that the present theories are, in fact, all wrong, he may be dubious about the possibility of extending them to the whole area. On the other hand, the scientists of Flatland have so far shown undoubted ingenuity in applying their incorrect theories to reality and the possibility that they will eventually solve their problems cannot be disregarded. If they do find their “general surveying theory,” it will be an interesting example of a theory which is completely incorrect, yet which explains all of the observed data in terms of its own, improper, assumptions.
The presently existing local theories may be divided among three basic categories. In the first place, there are a few in which the theory simply consists of an equation with no explanation of why it should work. Those theories which are explanatory, and they make up the vast bulk of the total, normally depend either on an assumption that measures of length vary from place to place or that straight lines are actually bent is various ways.Footnote 21 Some combine elements of both these explanations or, in some cases, also combine unexplained elements with one or the other of these basic explanations. As far as accuracy goes, some few of the Flatlanders’ theories use equations which are exactly those we would use ourselves, although they have derived them differently. In a few more cases, they use equations which lead to the same results as ours but which are more complex. In most cases, however, the theories developed by the Flatlander scientists are mere approximations of reality and many of them are not even close approximations.
But, what, the reader may ask, has all of this to do with us? I am coming to that and as an introduction may I ask that you consider the possibility that some Flatlander might begin to doubt the flatness of his universe. While he could doubt its flatness, he could not, given his mental constitution, think at all in non-flat terms. He could only feel that possibly the universe was non-flat, but he would have no idea what that meant in positive terms. In support of this view that the world was non-flat, he could offer only two, rather feeble arguments. Firstly, it would seem unlikely that the type of brain which would evolve under primitive conditions would be particularly suited to scientific efforts to penetrate the real nature of the universe. Secondly, he could point out that most scientific theories, efforts to explain the universe in terms of this built-in flatness axiom, were mere approximations of the data obtained by measurement and that vast areas were completely unexplained.
Weak as these arguments are, those on the other side are even weaker. There is first the argument from hope—someday our theories may fit the measurements exactly. Secondly, there is the argument of non-comprehension. A great many of the scholars of Flatland could be depended upon to simply point out that the results of reasoning based on the flatness axiom which was part of their biological brains seemed perfectly logical and that no other line of reasoning was so logical. This would, of course, he quite true, but also beside the point. The contention would be quite simply that the minds of the Flatlanders were so constructed that what seemed logical to them was nevertheless not in exact accord with the reality of nature. The fact that Flatlander logical reasoning appeared logical to Flatlanders would be irrelevant.
Obviously, with such weak arguments on either side, it would be impossible for the Flatlanders to determine who was right; the problem would have to remain an open question. Possibly after a few hundred thousands of years, some conclusion might be drawn by considering whether the whole of Flatland were covered by a coherent explanation, but surely nothing can be decided now.
Nevertheless, even a Flatlander who became convinced that the world was, in fact, non-flat would have to continue investigations using the flatness axiom. As we have pointed out, their minds are so constituted that they can think in no other terms. It would be a question of thinking in terms of this axiom or not thinking at all, and as long as any progress at all was possible with the use of the false axiom, it should be used. Our Flatlander would be in much the same situation as a modern Indian peasant. He knows that it would be much easier to break ground with a tractor and plow than with a hoe, but he doesn’t have the tractor and plow so he makes do with what he has.
The application of all of this to ourselves is, I suppose, obvious by now. We are biologically equipped with brains of a certain pattern. These brains permit us to think in certain ways, which are as much part of the biological equipment of the species as are arms and legs. Clearly, this thinking ability has positive evolutionary value and has given the human species a major competitive advantage over other species, but this does not prove that human logic and the real interrelations of things in this world are in a one-to-one relationship. Nevertheless, we have no choice but to continue thinking in our natural way. It may or may not be the best key to the universe, but it is the only one we have.
Comments from J[ames] B[uchanan]: I find this to be a very provocative and amusing essay. I was reminded of the comment of Hoyle. He made the point that the birds should have been rulers of the universe except for the fact that they are not able to support in the air brains having enough to make them superior. But the idea of surveying food potential from the air was a great one he said. Also the elephant. But for a deficiency in blood supply to brain he might have out-evolved humans. After this conversation with Hoyle, I think a lot more of evolution and animals.
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Levy, D.M., Peart, S.J. Gordon Tullock’s ill-fated appendix: “Flatland Revisited”. Const Polit Econ 28, 18–34 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10602-016-9232-8
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10602-016-9232-8