Skip to main content
Log in

Making executive politics mutually productive and fair

Constitutional Political Economy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Cite this article

Abstract

Winner-take-all elections for executive offices create high-stakes electoral conflict that distorts policy-making and constitution-making behavior. When the stakes are high, so long as it increases the chances of victory, office-seekers seek to shift perceived benefits toward and burdens away from potentially pivotal participants. This can entail the strategic allocation of spoils, the strategic selection of public policies that mobilize one’s base or divide the opposition, the strategic shifting of benefits into the present and costs into the future, and the strategic deception of the uninformed. This paper proposes a “turn-taking institution,” an electoral system in which the whole term is only awarded to a sufficiently inclusive supermajority coalition; if no coalition qualifies, the plurality winner and the runner-up take alternating one-year turns for the length of the term. This institution lowers the stakes of electoral conflict by roughly an order of magnitude, and fosters the formation, enforcement and adaptation of mutually productive policy-making and constitution-making behaviors. Critically, these results hold up even when voters and policy-makers are impatient, and when only short-run commitments are possible.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Scapegoats make diagnosing and solving problems a relatively simple matter. In politics, the undesirable output of a complex system (e.g. a rising price) may be the “true villain” for whom or for which the scapegoat (e.g. greedy merchants and/or an ethnic minority) is made to cover. For a bias to exist, scapegoats need not be entirely innocent, just marginally more innocent than they are perceived and/or treated.

  2. Indeed, we can frame majority rule (or plurality rule) as a special case of this mechanism: the case where the threshold required to win it all is a majority (or plurality).

  3. As an example of a relevant variation omitted here: rather than an absolute threshold of 60%, we might consider a rule where the 1st place team must be at least 1.5 times the size of the 2nd place team to win it all. When there are only two parties, this is equivalent to the 60% absolute threshold; when there are three or more, this version has the virtue of awarding the whole office to any party that stands out enough from the others.

  4. Two other prominent examples are the presidency during the Frente Nacional in Colombia (1958–1974), and the Presidency of the Council of the European Union (1958–2006).

  5. Alternative measures of the “good” would be highly correlated here. The improvement could be reckoned in terms of, for example, the magnitude of supermajority consensus, of economic growth rates, of life expectancies, or of the spread of basic political freedoms.

  6. Both teams of elites may offer a similar “core” of productive public policy that lifts these absolute payoffs above a historical baseline, while still maintaining the marginal differentiation that drives policy conflict.

  7. This is a take-off of the famous description of Buchanan (1972) of “public choice” as an attempt to see “politics without romance.”

  8. This is the sense used by Hardin (1999), who draws on David Hume, David Lewis and Thomas Schelling.

  9. James Buchanan devoted the second section of the first article published in this journal, “The Domain of Constitutional Economics,” to this point (Buchanan 1990: 7–9).

  10. This definition of impatience as some level of time discounting comes from Elster (2007: 154).

  11. This is equivalent to a Markov perfect equilibrium, a useful solution concept for modeling choices by ruling coalitions insofar as it captures the difficulty that such coalitions have in making binding commitments. As Acemoglu and Robinson (2006: 153) put it: “the advantage of the concept of Markov perfect equilibrium is that it incorporates the commitment problem in a simple way: given the state of the system…each party plays the best strategy for itself, irrespective of any promises made before or how the game was played in the past. Therefore, this equilibrium concept already builds in the commitment problem: all players know that each will play whatever is in their interest in the future.”

  12. For a discussion of the how folk theorem is used (and abused), see Gintis (2009: 216–217).

  13. That said, these accounts are a step forward from the standard account, which—in the tradition of Arrow (1951) and Downs (1957)—is a static, one-period account that precludes any inter-temporal cooperation by assumption.

  14. It would be straightforward to adjust the account to allow for quasi-hyperbolic discounting, but it would not qualitatively affect the results here.

  15. The stream of payoffs within the electoral-political context would be different than the choice between a lump sum and a stream of dollar payments, a point made by Brennan and Buchanan (1985: chapter 5).

  16. Here we restrict our focus to the case where players choose 4 years at a time, and their choices are revealed as soon as they are chosen. This greatly simplifies this exposition without qualitatively changing the results. In Durant and Weintraub (2010), players choose 1 year at a time (which happens to be equivalent to the case where they choose continuously).

  17. A different paper (Durant 2010) proposes the application of the “divide and choose” algorithm to decide turn-length within the term in a way that reliably zeroes out the stakes entirely for office-seekers. The 1st place candidate chooses to be Divider or Chooser. The Divider divides the term into two pieces, and the Chooser picks which piece he prefer. In equilibrium, most candidates (and citizens) are likely to be roughly indifferent between the pieces, so that the marginal benefit of being in 1st place is roughly zero.

  18. This would further lower the stakes by limiting the “additional benefits” available to winners.

  19. The difference between veil constructs and the turn-taking phase is that veil constructs assume participants can identify what would work and come to agreement ex ante, and can enforce their agreement ex post. These are heroic assumptions (Hardin 1988, 1991; Elster 1995; Knight 1998).

  20. Even if the incumbent is eligible as a candidate, it would patently unfair to allow him to win it all when his opponent has more votes, though not enough votes to meet the threshold.

  21. See Colomer and McClean (1998) for a history of the deadlocks arising from electing the Pope by a supermajority rule. Often this meant re-running the election dozens or even hundreds of times. Rules emerged to make the process increasingly uncomfortable in order to hasten agreement: locking the cardinals in the “conclave” (meaning “under key”), restricting their access to personal staff, rationing their food, requiring them to sleep in cramped and austere quarters, etc. This is not an approach that can be used to resolve deadlocks in large electorates.

  22. The weight of the second and fourth years is d + d 3. This makes the additional weighted win-share from winning the supermajority (d + d 3)(1 − d), whereas with a winner-take-all election it would be (1 + d + d 2 + d 3)(1 − d). When d = .85 (or .75 or .95), this makes the stakes of the move into or out of the supermajority phase roughly 46% (or 40 or 50%) of a winner-take-all election.

  23. This would be true insofar as (1) elites have diminishing marginal utility for non-policy and policy benefits alike, (2) elites predominantly care about non-policy benefits of holding office that would not double in the supermajority phase, (3) the policy benefits of preventing domination in the turn-taking phase are greater than those of dominating in the supermajority phase.

  24. Notably, emigration allows individuals to choose the history of governance of the polity they choose to inhabit.

  25. A third option is to build a win–win supermajority consensus. This is likely to be similar to finding win–win opportunities through alternating mutual accommodation.

  26. For more on this point, see Olson (1993) and Skinner (1978: Ch. 8).

  27. Elsewhere, I intend to argue that the demand of mass-level citizens would shift back as well.

  28. As it happens, while the theoretical norm is to suppose that the whole term of the office-holder is evaluated, empirically it seems that the several months before the election are given dramatically more weight (Achen and Bartels 2004).

References

  • Acemoglu, D., & Johnson, S. (2006). Unbundling institutions. Journal of Political Economy, 113(5), 949–995.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Acemoglu, D., & Robinson, J. (2006). Economic origins of dictatorship and democracy. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

  • Achen, C., & Bartels, L. (2004). Musical chairs: Pocketbook voting and the limits of democratic accountability. Princeton University working paper: http://www.princeton.edu/~bartels/chairs.pdf.

  • Alesina, A. (1988). Credibility and policy convergence in a two-party system with rational voters. American Economic Review, 78(4), 796–805.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arrow, K. (1951). Social choice and individual values. New York: Wiley and Sons.

  • Babcock, L., & Loewenstein, G. (1997). Explaining bargaining impasse: The role of self-serving biases. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 11(1), 109–126.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bates, R. (2008). Things fell apart: State failure in late-century Africa. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bednar, J. (2009). The Robust federation: Principles of design. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Besley, T. (2006). Principled agents? The political economy of good government.

  • Brennan, G., & Buchanan, J. (1980). The power to tax: Analytic foundations of a fiscal constitution. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, G., & Buchanan, J. (1985). The reason of rules: Constitutional political economy. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, G., & Lomasky, L. (1997). Democracy and decision: The pure theory of electoral preference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. (1972). Politics without romance: A sketch of positive public choice theory and its normative implications. In J. Buchanan & R. Tollison (Eds.), The theory of public choice, II. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. (1990). The domain of constitutional economics. Constitutional Political Economy, 1(1), 1–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. (1993). How can constitutions be designed so that politicians who seek to serve the ‘public interest’ can survive and prosper? Constitutional Political Economy, 4(1), 1–6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. (2005). Three amendments: Responsibility, generality and natural liberty. Cato Unbound, December 5th, 2005. http://www.cato-unbound.org/2005/12/05/james-m-buchanan/three-amendments/.

  • Buchanan, J. (2008). Same players, different game: How better rules make better politics. Constitutional Political Economy, 19(3), 171–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J., & Congleton, R. (1998). Politics by Principle, not interest: Toward nondiscriminatory democracy. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J., & Tullock, G. (1962). The calculus of consent. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bueno de Mesquita, B., Smith, A., Siverson, R., & Morrow, J. (2003). The logic of political survival. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caplan, B. (2001). Rationality irrationality and the microfoundations of political failure. Public Choice, 107, 311–331.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caplan, B. (2007). The Myth of the rational voter. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cebula, R., & Kaflogis, M. (1983). In search of the optimum ‘relative unanimity.’ Public Choice, 40(2), 195–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colomer, M., & McClean, I. (1998). Electing popes: Approval balloting and qualified majority rule. Journal of Interdisciplinary History, 29(1), 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cowen, T. (2005). Self-deception as the root of political failure. Public Choice, 124, 437–451.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cox, G. (2009). Swing voters, core voters and distributive politics. In S. Shapiro, Wood, & Kirshner (Eds.), Political representation. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dixit, A. (2003). Some lessons from transaction-cost politics for less-developed countries. Economics & Politics, 15, 107–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dixit, A., Grossman, G., & Gul, F. ( 2000). The dynamics of political compromise. Journal of Political Economy, 108(3), 531–568.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dixit, A., & Londregan, J. (1998). Ideology, tactics and efficiency in redistributive politics. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 113(2), 497–529.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Downs, A. (1957). An economic theory of political action in a democracy. Journal of Political Economy, 65(2), 135–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Durant, T. C. (2010). Zeroing out the stakes of electoral conflict with divide and choose. New York University, Working Paper.

  • Durant, T. C., & Weintraub, M. (2010). How to make democracy self-enforcing after civil war. New York University, Working Paper.

  • Elster, J. (1995). Forces and mechanisms in the constitution-making process. Duke Law Journal, 45(2), 364–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. (2007). Explaining social behavior: More nuts and bolts for the social sciences. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

  • Fearon, J. (1998). Bargaining, enforcement and international cooperation. International Organization, 52, 269–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fiorina, M. (1981). Retrospective voting in American elections. NH: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frederick, S., Loewenstein, G., & O’Donoghue, T. (2002). Time discounting and time preference: A critical review. Journal of Economic Literature, 40(2), 351–401.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, J. (2005). Popper, weber, and hayek: The epistemology and politics of ignorance. Critical Review, 17(1–2), I–Iviii.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, J. (2006). Public competence in normative and positive theory: Neglected implications of ‘The nature of belief systems in mass publics.’ Critical Review, 18(1–3): i–xliii.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs, V. (1982). Time preferences and health: An exploratory study. In V. Fuchs (Ed.), Economic aspects of health (pp. 93–120 ). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Geddes, B. (1994). Politician’s dilemma: Building state capacity in Latin America. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gintis, H. (2009). The bounds of reason: Game theory and the unification of the behavioral sciences. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

  • Glaeser, E. D. (2005). The political economy of hatred. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 120(1), 45–86.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glassner, B. (2000). The culture of fear: Why Americans are afraid of the wrong things. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardin, R. (1988). Constitutional political economy: Agreement on rules. British Journal of Political Science, 18(4), 513–530.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hardin, R. (1991). Hobbesian political order. Political Theory, 19(2), 156–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hardin, R. (1999). Liberalism, constitutionalism and democracy. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Heckathorn, D., & Maser, S. (1987). Bargaining and constitutional contracts. American Journal of Political Science, 31(1), 142–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horowitz, D. (1985). Ethnic groups in conflict. Berkeley, CA: The University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howell, W. (2005). Unilateral powers: A brief overview. Presidential Studies Quarterly, 35(3), 417–439.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jervis, R. (1998). System effects: Complexity in political and social life. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

  • Kernell, S. (1992). Going public: New strategies of presidential leadership. CA: CQ Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Key, V. O. (1966). The responsible electorate: Rationality in presidential voting, 1936–1960. Cambridge: Belknap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knight, J. (1998). Justice and fairness. Annual Review of Political Science, 1, 425–449.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kotlikoff, L. (2005). The coming generational storm: What you need to know about America’s economic future.

  • Krueger, A. (1990). Government failures in development. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 4(3), 9–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lomborg, B. (2010). Smart solutions to climate change: Comparing costs and benefits. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moe, T. (1990). Political institutions: The neglected side of the story. Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 6, 213–253.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moe, T. (2005). Power and political institutions. Perspectives on Politics, 3, 213–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moe, T., & Howell, W. (1999). The presidential power of unilateral action. Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 15, 132–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, K., Shleifer, A., & Vishny, R. (1993). Why is rent-seeking so costly to growth? American Economic Review, Papers and Proceedings, 83(2), 409–414.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neale, J. E. (1959). The age of Catherine de Medici. New York, NY: Barnes & Noble.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neustadt, R. (1991). Presidential power and modern presidents. New York, NY: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • North, D., Wallis, J., & Weingast, B. (2009). Violence and the social order: A conceptual framework for interpreting recorded human history.

  • North, D., & Weingast, B. (1989). Constitutions and commitment: The evolution of institutions governing public choice in seventeenth century England. Journal of Economic History, 49(4), 803–832.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olson, M. (1983). The rise and decline of nations: Economic growth, stagflation and social rigidities.

  • Olson, M. (1993). Dictatorship, democracy and development. American Political Science Review, 87, 567–576.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olson, M., & McGuire, M. (1996). The economics of autocracy and majority rule: The invisible hand and the use of force. Journal of Economic Literature, 34(1), 72–96.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ostrom, V. (1971). The political theory of a compound republic. Blacksburg, VA: Public Choice.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, J. (1998). Theories of ‘bad policy’. Journal of Economic Policy Reform, 2, 1–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rodrik, D. (2000). Participatory politics, social cooperation and economic stability. American Economic Review, 90, 140–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schelling, T. (1960). The strategy of conflict. MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schuessler, A. (2000). A logic of expressive choice. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, Q. (1978). The foundation of modern political thought: The age of reformation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spindler, Z. A. (1990). Constitutional design for a rent-seeking society: Voting choice rule. Constitutional Political Economy, 1(3), 73–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stigler, G. (1970). Director’s law of public income redistribution. Journal of Law and Economics, 13(1), 1–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tsebelis, G. (2002). Veto players: How political institutions work. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tulis, J. (1988). The rhetorical presidency. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wagner, R. E. (1976). Revenue structure, fiscal illusion and budgetary choice. Public Choice, 25, 45–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Warner, J. T., & Pleeter, S. (2001). The personal discount rate: Evidence from military downsizing programs. American Economic Review, 91(1), 33–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weingast, B. (1997). The political foundations of democracy and the rule of law. American Political Science Review, 91, 245–263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weingast, B. (2005). Self-enforcing constitutions: With an application to democratic stability in America’s first century. Working Paper.

  • Wittman, D. (1997). The myth of democratic failure: Why political institutions are efficient. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Tyler Cowen, Pete Boettke, Rob Axtell, Mike Munger, Mario Rizzo and David Harper for their criticism of many drafts. The seminar participants at the Colloquium on Market Institutions and Economic Processes at New York University provided many helpful comments. Counsel from Virgil Storr, Michael Weintraub, Ilya Beylin and Taylor Durant has been invaluable. I gratefully acknowledge support from the Earhart Foundation, the Bradley Foundation and the Searle Foundation. This paper is dedicated to the memory of my grandfathers, Richard Durant and John C. Sparks.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to T. Clark Durant.

Appendix

Appendix

See Fig. 7.

Fig. 7
figure 7

The weighted win-shares for the 1st place party with the status quo and the turn-taking institutions

Rights and permissions

Reprints and Permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Durant, T.C. Making executive politics mutually productive and fair. Const Polit Econ 22, 141–172 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10602-010-9097-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10602-010-9097-1

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation