Skip to main content
Log in

Choosing one’s own informal institutions: on Hayek’s critique of Keynes’s immoralism

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Constitutional Political Economy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In the main, Hayek favored rules that apply equally to all and located such rules in tradition, beyond conscious construction. This led Hayek to attack Keynes’s immoralism, i.e., the position that one should be free to choose how to lead one’s life irrespective of the informal institutions in place. However, it is argued here that immoralism may be compatible with Hayek’s enterprise since Hayek misinterpreted Keynes, who did not advocate the dissolving of all informal rules for everybody. By avoiding this misinterpretation, immoralism can be seen as institutional experimentation at the margin, which Hayek himself favored.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See also Hayek (1973, p. 50) and Locke (1988, p. 284): “But freedom of men under government is to have a standing rule to live by, common to every one of that society, and made by the legislative power erected in it” [italics added]. Cf. Buchanan and Congleton (1998) who, inspired by Hayek, present an extended argument in favor of a generality principle in politics.

  2. Note that generality is part of the definition of liberty. Cf. Hayek (1960, chaps. 1, 4, 9, 14; 1973, pp. 55–56; 1978, pp. 132–133). For initiated discussions of Hayek’s concept of liberty, see Gray (1984) and Klein (2004).

  3. See Hayek (1944, p. 72; 1960, p. 154 ff, 207 ff).

  4. See Hayek (1960, pp. 205–206). Cf. Oakeshott (1983).

  5. It is somewhat unfortunate that North uses the term “devised”, as it might be taken to imply conscious construction only. However, the term should be interpreted in a wider sense, as North (1990, p. 4; 1991) clarifies that institutions can indeed evolve. He can be taken to use the term to stress that rules, in his view, do not have extra-human origins—they are either constructed consciously or they emerge in evolutionary processes, but they are always the result of human action.

  6. See especially Hayek (1960, chap. 10; 1973, chaps. 4–6). Cf. Leoni (1961) and Zywicki and Sanders (2007).

  7. However, Hayek (1973, pp. 88–89) does admit that grown law may require correction by legislation, which indicates that he does not regard the outcomes of evolutionary processes as necessarily optimal. Cf. Vanberg (1994a).

  8. Cf. Hayek (1976, pp. 56–59; 1988, p. 66 ff).

  9. This dichotomy between spontaneous and made orders and an assessment of their respective characteristics is a recurring theme in Hayek’s works: see, e.g., Hayek (1948; 1952b, chaps. 8, 9; 1960, chap. 4; 1967, chaps. 5–7; 1978, chap. 1; 1988, chaps. 1–5). For surveys of theories of spontaneous order, see Barry (1982) and Sugden (1989).

  10. See Hayek (1948; 1967, p. 85; 1973, p. 5, 29; 1978, chap. 1).

  11. Hayek (1952a) outlines a cognitive theory according to which the human brain cannot explain itself or phenomena more complex than itself. This makes it impossible for man to know much about complex social matters, such as to how to successfully design institutions. Hayek began stressing man’s knowledge problem in the economic context (see, e.g., Hayek 1937, 1945). For further analysis, see Vanberg (1994b), van den Hauwe (1998), Steele (2002), Caldwell (2004), and Butos and Koppl (2006).

  12. See Hayek (1978, chap. 2).

  13. See Hayek (1978, chap. 9).

  14. The Keynes quote is from Keynes (1949, p. 97)—note that “experience and self-control” from the original text has been added to Hayek‘s rendering of the quote. A similar critique of Keynes as in the quote is also presented in, e.g., Hayek (1960, p. 159; 1973, pp. 25–26; 1978, p. 16; 1984, pp. 320–321; 1988, pp. 57–58).

  15. See, e.g., Friedman (1962, pp. 25–27), Brennan and Buchanan (1985, chap. 1), Buchanan (1990), and van den Hauwe (1998, p. 96 ff). Hayek (1976, p. 36) affirms this way of looking at things when he says that (formal) rules “protect ascertainable domains within which each individual is free to act as he chooses”.

  16. Cf. Hayek (1960, p. 70): “None of these conclusions are arguments against the use of reason, but only arguments against such uses as require any exclusive and coercive powers of government; not arguments against experimentation, but arguments against all exclusive, monopolistic power to experiment in a particular field—power which brooks no alternative and which lays a claim to the possession of superior wisdom—and against the consequent preclusion of solutions better than the ones to which those in power have committed themselves” and Hayek (1978, pp. 148–149): “As in the intellectual so in the material sphere, competition is the most effective discovery procedure which will lead to the finding of better ways for the pursuit of human aims. Only when a great many different ways of doing things can be tried will there exist such a variety of individual experience, knowledge, and skills, that a continuous selection of the most successful will lead to steady improvement.” See also Hayek (1960, pp. 365, 406–407).

  17. I thank Mark Pennington for clarifying this argument to me. See Vanberg (1994a, b).

  18. Hayek argues that synthetic systems of morals (especially act-utilitarianism) will fail to achieve their own goals, as such achievement presupposes knowledge that does not exist. But since Hayek does not agree with these goals, this should perhaps not concern him in itself. What Hayek (1948, p. 19, 25; 1960, pp. 64–65; 1973, chap. 1) does worry about is that attempts to implement systems of this kind will counteract his goal of liberty and, in fact, destroy the spontaneous order characterized by general and abstract rules.

  19. Hayek (1973, pp. 45–46) does admit that “it is at least conceivable” that constructed or designed rules can result in a spontaneous order. Cf. Buchanan (1977).

  20. In addition to the long quote above, an example of this “corner-solution” mindset can be found in Hayek (1952b, chaps. 8–9). De Vlieghere (1994) roots Hayek’s negative attitude towards piecemeal social engineering in the extreme view that a reformer has to have complete knowledge in order to be entrusted with institutional reforms.

  21. The large body of empirical research in institutional economics, constitutional economics and public choice/political economics illustrates the plausibility of this intermediate position: some consequences of alternative rules can be ascertained in at least a probabilistic or tentative manner.

  22. The epistemic positions can be related to the intuitive and critical levels of moral thinking outlined by Hare (1981). The intuitive level refers to the way we think morally in familiar and everyday situations without deeper reflection. Here, not much knowledge about effects is needed and rule-following is natural. The latter level refers to the way we think morally about non-familiar situations that are not part of our everyday life—more specifically, it refers to the selection of the best set of rules for use in intuitive thinking. At times, critical thinking can be used to evaluate and change the rules. Someone only engaged in critical thinking is called an archangel by Hare, and someone only engaged in intuitive thinking is called a prole. Hayek seems in this sense to regard every individual as a prole—but Hare (and Keynes) thinks that everyone uses both levels of thinking, in different degrees.

  23. At times, Hayek himself admits that the evolutionary process is not perfect from the point of view of his own normative views—see, e.g., Hayek (1973, pp. 88–89; 1976, pp. 25–27; 1978, pp. 19–20; 1988, p. 27)—but it is not made very clear to what extent he approves of constructivist action on such a basis and, if so, what type of action would be acceptable. Hayek does speak of “evolutionary rationalism” (1973, p. 5) and about a wish to not bring about “an abdication of reason” (Hayek 1960, p. 69). Kukathas (1989) analyzes this tension in Hayek, as do Rowland (1988), Vanberg (1994a, b), and Denis (2002).

  24. Cf. Buchanan (1959), Buchanan (1977), Barry (1982, pp. 31–33), Gissurarson (1987, pp. 169–170, note 18), Buchanan and Congleton (1998, pp. 3–5), van den Hauwe (1998), Posner (2003, pp. 287–289; 2005, p. 162), Berggren (2004, p. 81), and Schubert (2005). The specific idea of group selection as a key element of cultural evolution (Hayek 1967, pp. 66–81; 1979, p. 202; 1984, p. 318) is criticized by Vanberg (1986; 1994b, chap. 5), Sugden (1993), and Denis (2002).

  25. This relates to Schelling (2006) and his analysis of ways to commit to future courses of action.

  26. It is not required for any argument in the present paper that all social informal institutions could be consciously rejected, only that some can be.

  27. Cf. Buchanan’s (1987) discussion of moral anarchy.

  28. Even if an immoralist argued that there should never be any social sanctions, it is extremely unlikely that more than an utterly small number of people would agree with him and follow his “instruction.” Hence, the immoralist program can de facto be predicted to be circumvented by the use of social sanctions.

  29. Buchanan (1993) stresses that individuals tend to value autonomy or independence and that private property is conducive to this end. Within that private sphere, as delineated by the formal institution of property rights, people are free to make their own choices, for example in the realm of informal institutions, as they see fit—and they can more easily, by relying on what they own, endure social and economic sanctions initiated by those who dislike their choices.

  30. See, e.g., Klein (2001), Berggren and Jordahl (2006), and McCloskey (2006).

  31. Admittedly, Hayek (1978, p. 126) does not view favorably the “strong anti-clerical, anti-religious and generally anti-traditionalist attitude” of continental liberals—cf. Hayek (1973, p. 25), and Hayek (1948, p. 23) claims that “true individualism affirms the value of the family and all the common efforts of the small community and group.” See also Hayek (1988, chap. 9, p. 157).

  32. See, e.g., Skidelsky (1983, chap. 6), Bateman et al. (1988), Moggridge (1992, chap. 5), Davis (1994), Backhouse and Bateman (2006), Baldwin (2006), and Raffaelli (2006).

  33. Hawtrey (1951, p. 373) and Lawson (1989, p. 512) lend further support to the interpretation that Keynes did not reject all traditional rules.

  34. This position is more pronounced in the latter Keynes, who had a greater distrust in the power of reason and in the good will of ordinary men. But as Baldwin (2006, p. 254) points out, there is no profound change of heart in Keynes (who continued to regard himself as an immoralist over the course of his life). Cf. Skidelsky (1983, pp. 143–145) and Moggridge (1992, p. 123).

  35. Cf. Keynes (1972, p. 295), Cochran and Glane (1999, p. 291), Shearmur (2004, p. 98), and Buchanan and Wagner (2000, p. 80): “Personally, he was an elitist, and his idealized world embodied policy decisions being made by a small and enlightened group of wise people.” However, it bears noting that unlike the case of economic policy, where decisions by an elite necessarily affect everyone in an alike manner, the case of choosing informal institutions only involves making choices for oneself.

  36. Hayek (1960, p. 155) stresses that no one, including (and perhaps especially) those who rule, should be allowed to deviate from commonly shared rules, including informal ones.

  37. Skidelsky (2003, p. 74) points out the following about the Apostles, an exclusive society in Cambridge to which Keynes belonged: “One should never underestimate the effect of secrecy. Much of what made the rest of the world seem alien sprang from this simple fuel. Secrecy was a bond which greatly amplified the Society’s life relative to its members’ other interests”.

  38. See van den Hauwe (1998) and Hayek (1976, p. 147).

  39. Bateman et al. (1988, p. 1105), e.g., points out that Keynes was not a utilitarian.

  40. There were genuine conflicts between Keynes and Hayek in other areas, most notably in macroeconomics. See, e.g., Machlup (1974), Hayek (1995), Cochran and Glane (1999), and Steele (2001).

References

  • Backhouse, R. E., & Bateman, B. W. (2006). John Maynard Keynes: Artist, philosopher, economist. Atlantic Economic Journal, 34(2), 149–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baldwin, T. (2006). Keynes and ethics. In R. E. Backhouse & B. W. Bateman (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to Keynes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barry, N. (1982). The tradition of spontaneous order. Literature of Liberty, 5(2), 7–58.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bateman, B. W., Moore, G. E., & Keynes, J. M. (1988). A missing chapter in the history of the expected utility model. American Economic Review, 78(5), 1098–1106.

    Google Scholar 

  • Becker, G. S. (1968). Crime and punishment: An economic approach. Journal of Political Economy, 76(2), 169–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berggren, N. (2004). Does ethical subjectivism pose a challenge to classical liberalism? Reason Papers, 27(Fall), 69–86.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berggren, N., & Jordahl, H. (2006). Free to trust: Economic freedom and social capital. Kyklos, 59(2), 141–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, G., & Buchanan, J. M. (1985). The reason of rules: Constitutional political economy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brittan, S. (2006). Keynes’s political philosophy. In R. E. Backhouse & B. W. Bateman (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to Keynes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1959). Positive economics, welfare economic, and political economy. Journal of Law and Economics, 2(October), 124–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1977). Law and the invisible hand. In B. H. Siegan (Ed.), The interaction of economics and the law. Lexington, MA: D. C. Heath.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1987). Moral community, moral order, or moral anarchy. In Economics: Between predictive science and moral philosophy. College Station, TX: Texas A&M University Press

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1990). The domain of constitutional economics. Constitutional Political Economy, 1(1), 1–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1993). Property as a guarantor of liberty. Aldershot: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M., & Congleton, R. D. (1998). Politics by principle, not interest: Towards nondiscriminatory democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M., & Wagner, R. E. (2000). Democracy in deficit: The political legacy of lord Keynes. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butos, W. N., & Koppl, R. G. (2006). Does The sensory order have a useful economic future? In R. G. Koppl, C. Krecké, & E. Krecké (Eds.), Cognition and economics. Amsterdam: JAI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caldwell, B. (2004). Some reflections on F. A. Hayek’s the sensory order. Journal of Bionomics, 6(3), 239–254.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carabelli, A., & De Vecchi, N. (2001). Hayek and Keynes: From a common critique of economic method to different theories of expectations. Review of Political Economy, 13(3), 269–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cochran, J. P., & Glane, F. R. (1999). The Hayek–Keynes debate: Lessons for current business cycle research. Lewiston, NY: Edwin Mellan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, J. D. (1994). Keynes’s philosophical development. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Vlieghere, M. (1994). A reappraisal of Friedrich A Hayek’s cultural evolutionism. Economics and Philosophy, 10(2), 285–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Denis, A. (2002). Was Hayek a Panglossian evolutionary theorist? A reply to Whitman. Constitutional Political Economy, 13(3), 275–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitzgibbons, A. (1988). Keynes’ vision. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (1962). Capitalism and freedom. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, G. F. (2004). The diversity of comprehensive liberalisms. In G. F. Gaus & C. Kukathas (Eds.), The handbook of political theory. London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauthier, D. (1986). Morals by agreement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gissurarson, H. H. (1987). Hayek’s conservative liberalism. New York, NY: Garland Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodwin, C. D. (2006). The art of an ethical life: Keynes and Bloomsbury. In R. E. Backhouse & B. W. Bateman (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to Keynes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gray, J. (1984). Hayek on liberty. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hare, R. M. (1981). Moral thinking: Its levels, method and point. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harrod, R. (1951). The life of John Maynard Keynes. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • van den Hauwe, L. (1998). Evolution and the production of rules—Some preliminary remarks. European Journal of Law and Economics, 5(1), 81–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hawtrey, R. G. (1951). Review of the life of John Maynard Keynes. The Economic Journal, 61(242), 372–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. A. (1937). Economics and knowledge. Economica (N.S.), 4, 33–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. A. (1944). The road to Serfdom. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. A. (1945). The use of knowledge in society. American Economic Review, 35(4), 519–530.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. A. (1948). Individualism: True and false. In Individualism and economic order. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

  • Hayek, F. A. (1952a). The sensory order: An inquiry into the foundations of theoretical psychology. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. A. (1952b). The counter-revolution of science: Studies on the abuse of reason. Glencoe, IL: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. A. (1960). The constitution of liberty. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. A. (1967). Studies in philosophy, politics and economics. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. A. (1973). Law, legislation and liberty: Rules and order. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. A. (1976). Law, legislation and liberty: The mirage of social justice. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. A. (1978). New studies in philosophy, politics, economics and the history of ideas. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. A. (1979). Law, legislation and liberty: The political order of a free people. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. A. (1984). The origin and effect of our morals: A problem for science. In C. Nishiyama & K. R. Leube (Eds.), The essence of Hayek. Stanford, CA: Hoover Institution Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. A. (1988). The fatal conceit: The errors of socialism. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. A. (1995). Contra Keynes and Cambridge: Essays, correspondence. Bruce Caldwell. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Iannaccone, L. R. (1994). Why strict churches are strong. American Journal of Sociology, 99(5), 1180–1211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keynes, J. M. (1949). Two memoirs. London: Rupert Hart-Davis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keynes, J. M. (1972). Essays in persuasion: Collected writings, volume 9. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, D. B. (2001). The demand for and supply of assurance. Economic Affairs, 21(1), 4–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, D. B. (2004). Mere libertarianism: Blending Hayek and Rothbard. Reason Papers, 27(Fall), 7–43.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kukathas, C. (1989). Hayek and modern liberalism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawson, T. (1989). Review of Keynes’ vision. The Economic Journal, 99(396), 511–512.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leoni, B. (1961). Freedom and the law. Princeton, NJ: D. Van Nostrand.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. (1988/1690). Two treatises of government. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Machlup, F. (1974). Friedrich von Hayek’s contribution to economics. Swedish Journal of Economics, 76(4), 498–531.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCloskey, D. N. (2006). Bourgeois virtues: Ethics for an age of commerce. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (1982/1869). On liberty. Harmondsworth: Penguin.

  • Moggridge, D. E. (1992). Maynard Keynes: An economist’s biography. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. E. (1903). Principia ethica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • North, D. C. (1990). Institutions, institutional change and economic performance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • North, D. C. (1991). Institutions. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 5(1), 97–112.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oakeshott, M. (1983). The rule of law. In On history and other essays. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

  • Popper, K. R. (1965). On the sources of knowledge and ignorance. In Conjectures and refutations: The growth of scientific knowledge. New York, NY: Harper & Row.

  • Posner, R. A. (2003). Law, pragmatism, and democracy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Posner, R. A. (2005). Hayek, law, and cognition. NYU Journal of Law & Liberty, 1, 147–165.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raffaelli, T. (2006). Keynes and philosophers. In R. E. Backhouse & B. W. Bateman (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to Keynes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1993). Political liberalism. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowland, B. M. (1988). Beyond Hayek’s pessimism: Reason, tradition and bounded constructivist rationalism. British Journal of Political Science, 18(2), 221–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1967). Autobiography, volume I. London: George Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schelling, T. C. (2006). Strategies of commitment and other essays. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schubert, C. (2005). Hayek and the evolution of designed institutions: A critical assessment. In J. G. Backhaus (Ed.), Entrepreneurship, money and coordination: Hayek’s theory of cultural evolution. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shearmur, J. (2004). Hayek, Keynes and the state. In J. C. Wood & R. D. Wood (Eds.), F. A. Hayek: Critical assessments of leading economists. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skidelsky, R. (1983). John Maynard Keynes: Hopes betrayed 1883–1920. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skidelsky, R. (2003). John Maynard Keynes: 1883–1946: Economist, philosopher, statesman. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skidelsky, R. (2006). Hayek versus Keynes: The road to reconciliation. In E. Feser (Ed.), The Cambridge companion to Hayek. Cambridge University Press: Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steele, G. R. (2001). Keynes and Hayek: The money economy. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steele, G. R. (2002). Hayek’s Sensory order. Theory and Psychology, 12(3), 125–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (1989). Spontaneous order. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 3(4), 85–97.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (1993). Normative judgments and spontaneous order: The contractarian element in Hayek’s thought. Constitutional Political Economy, 4(3), 393–424.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vanberg, V. J. (1986). Spontaneous market order and social rules: A critique of F. A. Hayek’s theory of cultural evolution. Economics and Philosophy, 2(1), 75–100.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vanberg, V. J. (1994a). Hayek’s legacy and the future of liberal thought: Rational liberalism vs evolutionary agnosticism. Journal des Economistes et des Etudes Humaines, 5(4), 451–481.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vanberg, V. J. (1994b). Rules and choice in economics. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vanberg, V. J. (2002). Constitutional economics and ethics: On the relation between self-interest and morality. In G. Brennan, H. Kliemt, & R. D. Tollison (Eds.), Method and morals in constitutional economics: Essays in honor of James M. Buchanan. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woolf, L. (1960). Sowing. London: Hogarth Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zywicki, T. J., & Sanders, A. B. (2007). Posner, Hayek & the economic analysis of law. George Mason Law & Economics Research Paper No. 07–05. Fairfax, VA: School of Law, George Mason University.

Download references

Acknowledgments

The author wishes to thank Bryan Caplan, Robin Douhan, Henrik Jordahl, Daniel Klein, Hartmut Kliemt, Mark Pennington, and two anonymous referees, as well as participants at the 2008 Public Choice Society Meetings in San Antonio, for valuable comments and suggestions and Stiftelsen Marcus och Amalia Wallenbergs Minnesfond for financial support.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Niclas Berggren.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Berggren, N. Choosing one’s own informal institutions: on Hayek’s critique of Keynes’s immoralism. Const Polit Econ 20, 139–159 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10602-008-9055-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10602-008-9055-3

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation