Abstract
This article revisits the "harmony doctrine" school of economics (1835–1860) and its distinctive understanding of how ethics and economics intersect. Harmony doctrine thinkers staked out a “natural” understanding of economic phenomena that in many ways fused the classical political economy of Adam Smith with the earlier French Physiocratic School. Their metaphysically grounded interpretation was largely eclipsed by the developments of utilitarian and marginalist schools by the end of the nineteenth century. Yet harmony doctrine thinking adhered to a distinct understanding of how ethical processes and outcomes play out within the economic sphere that has to date gone under examined by business ethicists. This paper outlines three characteristics of harmony doctrine views: the belief in curative forces empowered to "heal" the economic order, a dichotomous interpretation of the economic realm that distinguishes the “natural” from the “artificial,” and an overarching belief in a harmonious social order actualized by cooperative interdependencies within economic enterprises. Despite falling into obscurity in the economic discipline, all these ideas found new life in intellectual currents of organizational and political thought at the turn of the twentieth century. After surveying these historical developments, this article concludes by demonstrating how harmony doctrine thinking helpfully illuminates persisting metaphysical dimensions of contemporary business ethics.
This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution.
Notes
To take as an example of the challenge in synthesizing Smith’s thought, the most extensive review of the notion of the “invisible hand” (Samuels, 2011) indexes over ninety different definitions of the concept in the history of economic thought, leading the author of the review to conclude that the concept has always been “laden with ambiguity” (ibid, p. 144) and now constitutes an “embarrassment” when used in the field (ibid, p. 293, cf. Hahn, 1982).
The similarities in themes and arguments in their respective thinking did not go unnoticed: Carey accused Bastiat of plagiarism in the years prior to Bastiat’s death. While this has been the subject of debate among economic historians, Ernest Teilhac (1936) made the case that the similarities between the two are the consequence of both thinkers relying so heavily on Say’s writings.
Marx recognized Bastiat’s influence on economic thought in the latter half of the nineteenth century: an updated afterword to the second German edition of Das Capital in 1873 recognizes Bastiat as one of the two major poles in contemporary political economy thinking, the other being John Stuart Mill. Bastiat’s “bourgeois political economy” represented the “most superficial and therefore the most adequate representative of the apologetic of vulgar economy.” Marx gave slightly more credit to Mill’s thought, which Marx labeled a “shallow syncretism” that attempted to “reconcile irreconcilables'' but, to its credit, recognized the “bankrupt” status of the economy itself.
Gide (1948) fittingly labels Malthus and Ricardo the “pessimist school” to emphasize the contrast with the optimists coming after them, a contrast echoed by Heilbroner (1986). These pessimistic scholars were in many ways responding to a prior cohort of “optimists”: William Godwin and Marquis de Condorcet (Screptani & Zamagni, 2005).
Smith’s most direct engagement with French Physiocratic thought appears in his consideration of Francois Quesnay’s (1694–1774) thought in Book 4, Chapter 9, para. 27 of Wealth of Nations. Smith sees Quesnay’s move of applying the same principles of health for the human body to political economy as placing too high a demand for “perfect liberty” on societies. Smith instead sees the “political body” as containing principles of “preservation and correcting” that may operate in the absence of Quesnay’s perfect liberty (cf. Harcourt, 2011, p. 81–85).
Their naturalism should also not be confused with moral naturalism (e.g. Foot, 1978) or the naturalism associated with positivist perspectives that perceive a basic continuity between the subject matter of the natural sciences and the social sciences that warrants the application of scientific methods onto study of social behavior (e.g. Nagel, 1963), a view that gained ground in twentieth century postwar American sociology and psychology. Though writing in an earlier time period, Bastiat and Carey would likely find some common ground with this latter form of naturalism while effectively landing on the exact opposite conclusion: the continuity between the social and natural world warranted the supremacy of philosophy (and natural theology) in political economy over and against any surrendering of the field to deductive and mechanistic methods of the natural sciences.
According to Somers and Block’s (2014) account–which in turn relies on Polanyi’s (1944) history of ideas–social naturalism made its first major inroads into political economy in the work of Joseph Townsend (1739–1816) before moving to Malthus and Ricardo. Yet the harmony doctrine thinkers in many ways represent an alternative and substantively different stream of naturalism, one which centers on a different unit (or level) of analysis. Whereas Townsend drew attention to biological instincts of human beings, the harmony doctrine thinkers inherited from the French Physiocrats the notion of a biology-like nature governing over the economic systems as a whole. This divide appears to have a lasting impact: Townsend’s instinct-based naturalism appears more influential on the microeconomic axioms that would eventually flow into utilitarianism and marginalism while the French Physiocrats and the French Liberal School that came after them would stake out more macro-grounded visions of equilibrating forces governing national wealth and trade.
Carey’s only qualifier for this perfect harmony is that “producer and consumer [must] take their places by each other’s side” in making face-to-face transactions. Carey saw “hostile interests” arising only when traders and merchants became intermediaries in transactions, as these actors incited competition and left no place for “harmony, sympathy, neutrality, partnership, or even equity of distribution” (1859, p. 422). The prevalence of intermediaries in the British system earned some of Carey’s sharpest criticisms.
The migration of harmony doctrine ideas into books and essays on law and politics rather than economic disciplinary journals also reflects changes in the economic discipline itself, which began to favor the formal modeling of neoclassical economics rather than the style of writing and argumentation best served the earlier harmony doctrine writers.
Similarities to earlier harmony doctrine may not be accidental, as the authors of Conscious Capitalism profess a profound admiration for several Austrian economists mentioned above (Hayek, Von Mises, Rothbard). Mackey and Sisodia credit these thinkers for inciting a massive shift in their thinking (Mackey & Sisodia, 2013, p. 4).
“Mutations” from a well-functioning organization are not limited to labor unions and overly-demanding workers: Conscious Capitalism also identifies shareholder value maximization and senior management teams receiving such high compensation that “unhappy stakeholders” begin exiting in a manner that ultimately harms the organization (Mackey & Sisodia, 2013, p. 172).
References
Abend, G. (2014). The moral background: An inquiry into the history of business ethics. Princeton University Press.
Agarwal, R., & Holmes, R. M., Jr. (2019). Let’s not focus on income inequality. Academy of Management Review, 44(2), 450–460.
Arena, R. (2000). Jean-Baptiste Say and the French Liberal School of the nineteenth century: Outside the canon? In E. L. Forget & S. Peart (Eds.), Reflections on the canon in economics. (pp. 205–223). Routledge.
Arrow, K. J., & Hahn, F. (1971). General competitive analysis. Holden-Day.
Bannister, R. (1979). Social Darwinism: Science and myth in Anglo-American thought. Temple University Press.
Bassiry, G. R., & Jones, M. (1993). Adam Smith and the ethics of contemporary capitalism. Journal of Business Ethics, 12, 621–627.
Bastiat, F. (1870). Economic harmonies. Oliver & Boyd.
Berry, C. B. (2013). Idea of commercial society in the Scottish Enlightenment. Edinburgh University Press
Blaug, M. (1985). Economic theory in retrospect. University of Cambridge.
Block, F., & Somers, M. (2014). The power of market fundamentalism: Karl Polanyi’s critique. Harvard University Press.
Bragues, G. (2009). Adam Smith’s vision of the ethical manager. Journal of Business Ethics, 90, 447–460.
Carey, H. C. (1871). Principles of social science. J.B. Lippincott & Co.
Carroll, A. (1987). In search of the amoral manager. Business Horizons, 30(2), 7–15.
Conkin, P. K. (1980). Prophets of prosperity: America’s first political economists. Indiana University Press.
Dawson, A. (2000). Reassessing Henry Carey (1793–1879): The problems of writing political economy in nineteenth-century America. Journal of American Studies, 34(3), 465–485.
Donaldson, T. (1982). Corporations and morality. Prentice-Hall.
Dumont, L. (1977). From Mandeville to Marx: The genesis and triumph of economic ideology. University of Chicago Press.
Evensky, J. (2005). Chicago Smith” versus “Kirkaldy Smith. History of Political Economy, 37(2), 197–203.
Foot, P. (1978). Virtues and vices and other essays in moral philosophy. Oxford University Press.
Forget, E. L. (2001). Jean-Baptiste Say and spontaneous order. History of Political Economy, 33(2), 193–218.
Foxwell, H. S. (1919). Papers on current finance. Macmillan and Co.
Freeman, R. E. (1994). The politics of stakeholder theory: Some future directions. Business Ethics Quarterly, 4(4), 409–421.
Gide, C. (1948). A history of economic doctrines from the time of the Physiocrats to the present day. George G.
Godfrey, P. C. (2006). A reply to Bright: virtuousness and the virtues of the market. Academy of Management Review, 31(3), 754–756.
Gonin, M. (2015). Adam Smith’s contribution to business ethics, then and now. Journal of Business Ethics, 129, 221–236.
Greenwood, M., & Van Buren, H. J. (2017). Ideology in HRM scholarship: Interrogating the ideological performativity of ‘new unitarism.’ Journal of Business Ethics, 142, 663–678.
Hahn, F. (1982). Reflections on the invisible hand. Lloyds Bank Review, April, 1–21.
Harcourt, B. (2011). The illusion of free markets: Punishment and myth of natural order. Harvard University Press.
Hayek, F. A. (1960). The constitution of liberty. University of Chicago Press.
Heilbroner, R. L. (1986). The worldly philosophers: The lives, times, and ideas of the great economic thinkers. Simon & Schuster Inc.
Hofstadter, R. (1944). Social Darwinism in American thought. University of Pennsylvania Press.
Huebert, J. H. (2010). Libertarianism today. ABC-CLIO.
Huhn, M. P., & Dierksmeier, C. (2016). Will the real Adam Smith please stand up! Journal of Business Ethics, 136, 119–132.
Hulsmann, J. G. (2001). Bastiat’s legacy in economics. Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics, 4(4), 55–70.
Hunt, E. K., & Lautzenheiser, M. (2011). History of economic thought: A critical perspective. Routledge.
Ingra, B. & Israel, B. (1990). The invisible hand: Economic equilibrium in the history of science. Trans. By I. McGilvray, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
Jevons, W. S. (1888). The theory of political economy. (3rd ed.). Macmillan.
Keynes, J. M. (1971 [1933]), Essays in biography. In E. Johnson and D. Moggridge (Eds.), The collected works of John Maynard Keynes, 29 vols, vol. X. Macmillan
Kirzner, I. M. (1989). Economic harmony. In J. Eatwell, M. Milgate, & P. Newman (Eds.), The invisible hand. (pp. 94–98). Macmillan.
Knight, F. (1956). On the history and method of economics: Selected essays. University of Chicago Press.
Koslowski, P. (1996). The ethics of capitalism. In P. Koslowski (ed.) Ethics of capitalism and critique of sociobiology: Two essays with a comment by James M. Buchanan, (pp.3–64), Springer
Lawson, T. (2003). Reorienting economics. Routledge.
Leonard, T. C. (2016). Illiberal reformers: Race, eugenics, and American economics in the progressive era. Princeton University Press.
Lynn, A. (2020). Why ‘doing well to do good’ goes wrong: A critical review of ‘good ethics pays’ claims in managerial thinking. Academy of Management Review, In Press. https://doi.org/10.5465/amr.2018.0250.
Mackey, J., & Sisodia, R. (2013). Conscious capitalism: Liberating the heroic spirit of business. Harvard Business Review Press.
Maier, C. S. (1970). Between Taylorism and technocracy: European ideologies and the vision of industrial productivity in the 1920s. Journal of Contemporary History, 5(2), 27–61.
McMahon, C. (1981). Morality and the invisible hand. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 10(3), 247–277.
Migate, M. (1989). Equilibrium: Development of a concept. In J. Eatwell, M. Milgate, & P. Newman (Eds.), The invisible hand. (pp. 105–113). Macmillan.
Mill, J. S. (1865). The positive philosophy of Auguste Comte. Henry Holt.
Mitzman, A. (1996). Michelet and social romanticism: Religion, revolution, nature. Journal of the History of Ideas, 57(4), 659–682.
Morrison, R. (1986). Henry C. Carey and American economic development: American philosophical society, Philadelphia, PA.
Nagel, E. (1963). Problems of concept and theory formation in the social sciences. In M. Natanson (Ed.), Philosophy of the social sciences. (pp. 189–209). Random House.
Neill, T. (1948). Quesnay and physiocracy. Journal of the History of Idea, 9(2), 153–173.
Nozik, R. (1974). Anarchy, state, and utopia. Basic Books.
Parrington, V. L. (1927). Main Currents in American Thought. Harcourt.
Phillips-Fein, K. (2010). Invisible hands: The businessmen’s crusade against the new deal. WW Norton & Company.
Polanyi, K. (1944). The great transformation: The political and economic origins of our time. Farrar & Rinehart.
O’Donnell, M. G. (1993). Economics as ethics: Bastiat’s nineteenth century interpretation. Journal of Business Ethics, 12(1), 57–61.
Quinn, D. P., & Jones, T. M. (1995). An agent morality view of business policy. Academy of Management Review, 20(1), 22–42.
Reybaud, L. (1862). Les economistes modernes. Guillaumin.
Ross, D. (1991). The origins of American social science. Cambridge University Press.
Rothbard, M. (1962). Man, economy, and state: A treatise on economic principles. Van Nostrand.
Samuels, W. J. (2011). Erasing the invisible hand: Essays on an elusive and misused concept in economics. Cambridge University Press.
Say, J.-B. (1832). A treatise on political economy; or the production, distribution, and consumption of wealth. By C.R. Prinsep, Grigg & Elliott, Philadelphia, PA.
Schumpeter, J. (1991). The meaning of rationality in the social sciences. In R. Swedberg (Ed.), Joseph A. Schumpeter: The economics and sociology of capitalism (pp. 316–338). Princeton University Press.
Schwartz, M. (2018). Business ethics. In R. W. Kolb (Ed.), The SAGE encyclopedia of business ethics and society. (pp. 319–322). Sage Publications.
Screptani, E., & Zamagni, S. (2005). An outline of the history of economic thought. Oxford University Press.
Sen, A. (1993). Does business ethics make economic sense? Business Ethics Quarterly, 3(1), 45–54.
Smith, A. 1776 (1976). The theory of moral sentiments. Cambridge University Press.
Spencer, H. (1925). Principles of sociology. D. Appleton & Company.
Taylor, F. W. (1912). Testimony of Mr. Frederick Winslow Taylor. United States Congress Hearings Before Special Committee to Investigate the Taylor and Other Systems of Shop Management, 3, 1377–1426.
Taylor, C. (1989). Sources of the self: The making of the modern identity. Harvard University Press.
Teilhac, E. (1936). Pioneers of American economic thought in the nineteenth century. Macmillan.
Ulrich, P. (1996). Towards an ethically-based conception of socio-economic rationality. In W. W. Gasparski & C. S. V. Leo V. Ryan (Eds.), Human action in business: Praxiological and ethical dimensions (1st ed., pp. 21–49). Transaction Publishers
Veblen, T. (1899). The preconceptions of economic science. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 13. Reprinted in T. Veblen, The Place of Science in Modern Civilization and Other Essay, (pp. 114–147), Capricorn Books
Viner, J. (1927). Adam Smith and laissez faire. Journal of Political Economy, 35(2), 198–232.
Von Mises, L. (1962). The free and prosperous commonwealth: An exposition in the ideas of classical liberalism. Van Nostrand
Wells, T. R. (2019). What Adam Smith really thought should not matter. Business Ethics Journal Review, 7(7), 40–46.
Werhane, P. H. (1991). Adam Smith and his legacy for modern capitalism. Oxford University Press.
Werhane, P. H. (2000). Business ethics and the origins of contemporary capitalism: Economics and ethics in the work of Adam Smith and Herbert Spencer. Journal of Business Ethics, 24, 185–198.
Werhane, P. H., Freeman, R. E., & Dmytriyev, S. (2017). The use of historical figures as a research approach. In. P.H. Werhane, R.E. Freeman, & S. Dmytriyev (Eds.), Cambridge handbook of research approaches to business ethics and corporate responsibility, (pp. 12–24), Cambridge University Press
Wicks, A. C. (1996). Overcoming the separation thesis: The need for a reconsideration of business and society research. Business and Society, 35, 89–118.
Wolin, S. (1960). Politics and vision: Continuity and innovation in western political thought. University of California
Zamagni, S. (1989). Economic laws. In J. Eatwell, M. Milgate, & P. Newman (Eds.), The invisible hand. (pp. 99–104). Macmillan.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Ethics declarations
Conflict of interest
The author hereby declares no financial or non-financial conflict of interest.
Additional information
Publisher's Note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Lynn, A. Ethics, Economics, and the Specter of Naturalism: The Enduring Relevance of the Harmony Doctrine School of Economics. J Bus Ethics 178, 661–673 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-021-04819-y
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-021-04819-y