Skip to main content
Log in

Pay Secrecy, Discrimination, and Autonomy

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Journal of Business Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

A question facing nearly all private firms is whether they may keep employee pay secret. Many think it is obvious that firms are obligated to disclose a good deal of pay information once we properly appreciate the severity of pay discrimination in our economy and the autonomy-related interests that would be served by pay disclosure. This article puts forth a dissenting voice against the vast majority of recent commentary. It exploits a fissure between reasons we have to support certain coercive regulations and reasons firms have to act in the absence of such regulation. While acknowledging that we may need transparency regulations for firms that fail to act morally, it argues that otherwise moral firms need not disclose pay on the surveyed grounds.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Others have made some similar observations, though steeped in the application of frameworks rooted in continental philosophy or Frankfurt School critical theory (Flyverbom et al. 2015). For instance, Roberts (2009, p. 964) observes that, “[t]he problem but power of transparency lies in its use as an instrument of hierarchy, large-scale organisation, and control at a distance.” Transparency is said to lie at the intersection of power and the panoptic worldview (Foucault 1980, 1995), relying on “the twin possibilities of observation and control” (Zuboff 1989, p. 321).

  2. Secrecy is fundamentally “a property of information” (Mahon 2018, pp. 173–174; Scheppele 1988, p. 12), not a property of things. Hence, my definition of pay secrecy does not reference pay per se, but pay information.

  3. The reader may be familiar with President Obama’s 2014 Executive Order 11246, which was widely heralded to be a significant step towards ending pay secrecy (Eliperin 2014). The Executive Order resulted in rules barring federal contractors from retaliating against employees that discuss pay (Calvasina et al. 2015), substantially providing rights to individuals not already covered under the NLRA’s protections, such as managers, supervisors, and other workers in specific industries (Department of Labor n.d.). This is not the kind of pay secrecy this article focuses on, however, which is the top-down intentional concealment of pay information.

  4. I cannot speak comprehensively to the cultures surrounding pay in non-American contexts. But it would seem that social norms encouraging the discussion of pay would be the exception to the rule.

  5. I should note that, as Robert Hughes (2013a, b) points out, it does seem conceptually possible for government to enact non-coercive laws—that coercion is not necessary to law-making. But even a non-coercive law regulating lunches with friends would seem unjustified.

  6. I thank an anonymous referee for drawing this helpful distinction.

  7. I thank Amy Sepinwall for illustrating the importance of this concern to me.

  8. Here, ought implies can. While companies certainly have some discretion in setting compensation (Moriarty 2012), the market economy does impose some constraints (Maitland 1985).

  9. See, also, Waluchow (1988) for a rich smattering of candidates for a standard for fair pay, including: how the existing market would pay; what a theoretical fair market would pay; what a person deserves; how much the work contributes to the success of the firm; how much the work benefits society; the going rate in the same industry for people who do the same work; and adherence to the employer’s pre-existing explicit or implicit wage policy.

  10. There stands a question, however, of what conceptions of fairness my account may exclude. For one, it seems to exclude recently popular legitimation approaches to management ethics (Scherer and Palazzo 2007; Schrempf-Stirling et al. 2016); if compensation must be legitimated through some kind of public discourse (Joutsenvirta 2013), secrecy would seem to preclude such legitimation.

  11. Moriarty (2020, p. 124) argues that the incentive view takes on a “normative logic of effectiveness.” However, this logic only attaches by way of being associated with a demanding view of the corporate objective with a mandate to generate shareholder wealth. While I think Moriarty is right to associate the incentive view with theorists who adopt this kind of shareholder-centric paradigm, it bears repeating that there is no necessary analytical relationship between the two. We have good reason to think corporations have significant moral discretion to direct resources to different ends (Strudler 2017), whether wages are primarily incentives or not.

  12. I thank an anonymous referee for pointing this out.

  13. Since I am only considering in this particular section whether the prevention and policing of discrimination constitutes a reason to disclose pay, when I say something like “the firm does not have reason to disclose pay,” I generally mean, in this section, “the firm does not have reason to disclose pay in virtue of the imperative to prevent and police discrimination”.

  14. Hereafter, when I say “cease discrimination” or “stop discrimination,” I mean with the qualification of “to the extent possible.” I will discuss herein issues relating to the extent to which companies may be limited in preventing or policing discrimination.

  15. We might imagine circumstances in which this is the case. For example, a well-meaning CEO may lack the political power to institute new, costly discrimination prevention measures, but have the clout to enact a policy of pay disclosure. But there is no reason to think that this is the paradigm case.

  16. It should be noted that the particular case of Google might merit a different analysis, given assertions by the Department of Labor of “extreme gender pay inequity” (Shu 2017). I use it here to advance an intuitive point, not to render a final judgment in this specific case.

  17. I thank an anonymous reviewer for raising this worry.

  18. One exception is Moriarty (2009), who argues that executives with fiduciary duties to a firm may have a moral duty to accept only (a version of) their reservation price.

  19. Framing our discussion in terms of dyadic wage negotiations risks conveying an overly simplistic model of labor markets and pay negotiations. Wage determination processes are complex, involving a variety of labor market participants and institutions, most notably labor unions and occupational licensing authorities (Gittleman and Kleiner 2016). The structure and power of these institutions stand to affect trends in pay discrimination in significant ways—it has been argued, for instance, that labor unions provide disproportionate benefits to women (Porter 2013). In this article’s context, how we describe the duties in particular wage-setting environments may vary with the number of parties involved and their respective roles. My hope is that all of the conclusions I reach in discussing duties of employers to their employees here, though, are consistent with or easily transmutable to contexts in which several parties are involved in wage determination. My ultimate conclusion that pay secrecy is not obligatory in virtue of employee rights or interests can be redescribed to include overall labor union interests as well.

  20. This line of reasoning is inspired by a discussion by Taurek (1977), who reasons in one case that if even the weakest of self-serving reasons can negate a supposed obligation, then it is best said that the obligation never existed at all.

  21. Approaches rooted in the positivist organizational justice literature identify the just wage with the perceived just wage (Marasi et al. 2018; e.g., Marasi and Bennett 2016), even promoting ‘informational justice’ as a distinct psychological construct (Scheller and Harrison 2018); but normative ethics maintains a line between perception and reality (Alzola 2019; Kim and Donaldson 2016).

  22. Note that this section engages only with this conditional claim. I do not seek to justify or argue that employers are obligated to provide a living wage. I only ask what their obligations are with regard to pay transparency if this is the case.

  23. Fenster (2010, p. 626 n. 28) notes that, as of 2010, more than 550 Journals and Law Reviews in the Westlaw database used “sunlight” and “disinfectant” in the same sentence.

  24. Popular business articles, in particular, are dotted with endorsements of transparency, often invoking prudential concerns alongside a vague concept of ‘trust’ as a justification for an unconditional imperative for transparency. For selections from the Harvard Business Review, see ‘The Strategic Benefits of Transparency’ (Balter 2007); 'Want Your Employees to Trust You? Show You Trust Them' (Brower et al. 2017); 'Winning in an Age of Radical Transparency' (Goleman, 2009) 'Trust in the Age of Transparency' (Kirby 2012); 'Trust Through Transparency' (Nayar 2009); 'What's Needed Next: A Culture of Candor' (O’Toole and Bennis 2009); 'Why Radical Transparency is Good Business' (Smith and Tabibnia 2012); 'Heed the Calls for Transparency' (Wilkin 2009).

References

  • Adams, J. S. (1963). Towards an understanding of inequity. The Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 67(5), 422.

    Google Scholar 

  • Albu, O. B., & Flyverbom, M. (2016). Organizational transparency: Conceptualizations, conditions, and consequences. Business & Society. https://doi.org/10.1177/0007650316659851.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alchian, A. A., & Demsetz, H. (1972). Production, information costs, and economic organization. The American Economic Review, 62(5), 777–795.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allen, A. L. (2002). Privacy isn’t everything: accountability as a personal and social good. Alabama Law Review, 4, 1375–1392.

    Google Scholar 

  • Altman, A. (2016). Discrimination. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Stanford: Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alzola, M. (2019). Even when no one is watching: the moral psychology of corporate reputation. Business & Society., 58, 1267–1301.

    Google Scholar 

  • Amis, J. M., Mair, J., & Munir, K. A. (2019). The organizational reproduction of inequality. Academy of Management Annals, 14(1), 195–230.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anand, V., & Rosen, C. C. (2008). The ethics of organizational secrets. Journal of Management Inquiry, 17(2), 97–101. https://doi.org/10.1177/1056492607312785.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arnold, D. G., & Bowie, N. E. (2003). Sweatshops and respect for persons. Business Ethics Quarterly, 13(2), 221–242. https://doi.org/10.2307/3857660.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Balter, D. (2007). The strategic benefits of transparency. Harvard Business Review., 75, 385.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bartlett, K. T. (2009). Making good on good intentions: The critical role of motivation in reducing implicit workplace discrimination. Virginia Law Review, 95(8), 1893–1972.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bebchuk, L. A., & Fried, J. M. (2004). Executive compensation at Fannie mae: A case study of perverse incentives, nonperformance pay, and camouflage studies on executive pay. Journal of Corporation Law, 30(4), 807–822.

    Google Scholar 

  • Belogolovsky, E., & Bamberger, P. A. (2014). Signaling in secret: Pay for performance and the incentive and sorting effects of pay secrecy. Academy of Management Journal, 57(6), 1706–1733. https://doi.org/10.5465/amj.2012.0937.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bentham, J. (1908 [1802]). Theory of Legislation. (R. Hildreth, Trans.) (Translated from the French of Etienne Dumont). London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trübner & Company.

  • Bielby, W. T. (2000). Minimizing workplace gender and racial bias. Contemporary Sociology, 29(1), 120–129. https://doi.org/10.2307/2654937.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bierman, L., & Gely, R. (2004). “Love, sex and politics? Sure. Salary? No way”: Workplace social norms and the law. Berkeley Journal of Employment and Labor Law, 25(1), 167–191.

    Google Scholar 

  • Birkinshaw, P. (2006). Transparency as a human right. In C. Hood & D. Heald (Eds.), Transparency: The key to better governance (pp. 47–57). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blau, F. D., & Kahn, L. M. (2000). Gender differences in pay. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 14(4), 75–100.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloom, M. (2004). The ethics of compensation systems. Journal of Business Ethics, 52(2), 149–152.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bok, S. (1989). Secrets: On the ethics of concealment and revelation (Reissue ed.). New York: Vintage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borradori, G. (2016). Between transparency and surveillance politics of the secret. Philosophy and Social Criticism, 42(4–5), 456–464.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandeis, L. D. (1914). Other people’s money, and how the bankers use it. New York: Stokes.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, J. (2019). Should employers pay a living wage? Journal of Business Ethics, 157(1), 15–26. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-017-3724-y.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brower, H. H., Lester, S. W., & Korsgaard, M. A. (2017). Want your employees to trust you? Show you trust them. Harvard Business Review, 47, 81–89.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burkus, D. (2016). Under new management: How leading organizations are upending business as usual. Boston: Houghton Mifflin Harcourt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Calland, R. (2007). Prizing open the profit-making world. In A. Florini (Ed.), The right to know: Transparency for an open world (pp. 214–242). New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Calvasina, G. E., Calvasina, R. V., & Calvasina, E. J. (2015). Pay secrecy: Legal, policy, and practice issues for employers. Journal of Legal, Ethical and Regulatory Issues, 18(2), 1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Canales, B. (2017). Closing the federal gender pay gap through wage transparency. Houston Law Review, 55, 969–998.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carreyrou, J. (2018). Bad blood: Secrets and lies in a silicon valley startup. New York: Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carson, T. L., Wokutch, R. E., & Murrmann, K. F. (1982). Bluffing in labor negotiations: Legal and ethical issues. Journal of Business Ethics, 1(1), 13–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Castilla, E. J. (2008). Gender, race, and meritocracy in organizational careers. American Journal of Sociology, 113(6), 1479–1526.

    Google Scholar 

  • Castilla, E. J. (2015). Accounting for the gap: A firm study manipulating organizational accountability and transparency in pay decisions. Organization Science, 26(2), 311–333.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colella, A., Paetzold, R. L., Zardkoohi, A., & Wesson, M. J. (2007). Exposing pay secrecy. The Academy of Management Review, 32(1), 55–71.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corvino, J. (2006). Reframing “Morality Pays”: toward a better answer to “Why be Moral?” in business. Journal of Business Ethics, 67(1), 1–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cory, J. (2001). Activist business ethics. Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cory, J. (2004). Business ethics: The ethical revolution of minority shareholders. New York: Springer Science & Business Media.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cropanzano, R., Bowen, D. E., & Gilliland, S. W. (2007). The management of organizational justice. Academy of Management Perspectives, 21(4), 34–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cullen, Z. B., & Perez-Truglia, R. (2018). The salary taboo: Privacy norms and the diffusion of information (Working Paper No. 25145). National Bureau of Economic Research. https://doi.org/10.3386/w25145.

  • Dando, N., & Swift, T. (2003). Transparency and assurance: Minding the credibility gap. Journal of Business Ethics, 44(2/3), 195–200.

    Google Scholar 

  • Danziger, L., & Katz, E. (1997). Wage secrecy as a social convention. Economic Inquiry, 35(1), 59–69.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Maria, W. (2006). Brother secret, sister silence: Sibling conspiracies against managerial integrity. Journal of Business Ethics, 65(3), 219–234.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dean, J. (2001). Publicity’s secret. Political Theory, 29(5), 624–650.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dees, J. G., & Cramton, P. C. (1995). Deception and mutual trust: A reply to strudler. Business Ethics Quarterly, 5(4), 823–832.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C., & Roy, D. (2015). How digital transparency became a force of nature. Scientific American, 5, 82–94.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dishman, L. (2017). Activist investor demands that Google provide more data on its gender pay gap. Fast Company. Retrieved December 6, 2017 fromhttps://www.fastcompany.com/40474369/activist-investor-demands-that-google-provide-more-data-on-its-gender-pay-gap.

  • Doll, J. (2012). How keeping salaries secret makes employees complicit in wage inequality. The Atlantic. Retrieved January 29, 2018 from https://www.theatlantic.com/business/archive/2012/05/how-keeping-salaries-secrets-makes-employees-complicit-wage-inequality/327457/.

  • Donaldson, T. (1989). The ethics of international business. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreisbach, T. (2014). “Pay Secrecy” policies at work: Often illegal, and misunderstood. NPR. Org. Retrieved September 4, 2018 from https://www.npr.org/2014/04/13/301989789/pay-secrecy-policies-at-work-often-illegal-and-misunderstood.

  • Dufresne, R. L., & Offstein, E. H. (2008). On the virtues of secrecy in organizations. Journal of Management Inquiry, 17(2), 102–106. https://doi.org/10.1177/1056492607313082.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duska, R. F. (2014). Why business ethics needs rhetoric: An aristotelian perspective. Business Ethics Quarterly, 24(1), 119–134. https://doi.org/10.5840/beq20141271.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Edwards, M. A. (2005). The law and social norms of pay secrecy. Berkeley Journal of Employment and Labor Law, 26, 41–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eisenberg, D. T. (2011). Money, sex, and sunshine: A market-based approach to pay discrimination. Arizona State Law Journal, 43, 951–1020.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eisenberg, E. M., & Witten, M. G. (1987). Reconsidering openness in organizational communication. The Academy of Management Review, 12(3), 418–426.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elia, J. (2009). Transparency rights, technology, and trust. Ethics and Information Technology, 11(2), 145–153. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10676-009-9192-z.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eliperin, J. (2014). Obama takes executive action to lift the veil of “pay secrecy.” Washington Post. https://www.washingtonpost.com/news/post-politics/wp/2014/04/08/obama-takes-executive-action-to-lift-the-veil-of-pay-secrecy/. Accessed 7 February 2020.

  • England, P. (2017). Comparable worth: Theories and evidence. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Estlund, C. (2014). Extending the case for workplace transparency to information about pay. UC Irvine Law Review, 4(2), 781.

    Google Scholar 

  • Etzioni, A. (2010). Is transparency the best disinfectant? Journal of Political Philosophy, 18(4), 389–404. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9760.2010.00366.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eurofound. (2018). Pay transparency in Europe: First experiences with gender pay reports and audits in four Member States. Luxembourg: Publications Office of the European Union.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fenster, M. (2010). Seeing the state: Transparency as metaphor. Administrative Law Review, 62(3), 617–672.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fieser, J. (1996). Do businesses have moral obligations beyond what the law requires? Journal of Business Ethics, 15(4), 457–468.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisk, G. M. (2010). “I want it all and I want it now!” An examination of the etiology, expression, and escalation of excessive employee entitlement. Human Resource Management Review, 20(2), 102–114. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.hrmr.2009.11.001.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Florini, A. (2000). The End of Secrecy. In B. I. Finel & K. M. Lord (Eds.), Power and conflict in the age of transparency (pp. 13–28). New York: Palgrave Macmillan US.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flyverbom, M. (2020). The digital prism: Transparency and visibility in the age of total information. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flyverbom, M., Christensen, L. T., & Hansen, H. K. (2015). The transparency-power nexus: Observational and regularizing control. Management Communication Quarterly, 29(3), 385–410.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (1980). Power/knowledge: Selected interviews and other writings, 1972–1977. New York: Pantheon Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (1995). Discipline & punish: The birth of the prison. (A. Sheridan, Trans.). New York: Vintage Books.

  • Freeman, R. E., & Greenwood, M. (2020). Deepening methods in business ethics. Journal of Business Ethics, 161(1), 1–3. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-019-04374-7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frye, J., & Holmes, K. (2017). Wage discrimination: Behind the numbers. Center for American Progress. Retrieved August 10, 2017 from https://www.americanprogress.org/issues/women/news/2017/07/05/435190/wage-discrimination-behind-numbers/.

  • Fung, A., Graham, M., & Weil, D. (2007). Full disclosure: The perils and promise of transparency. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, D. R. (2014). Enduring illusions: The social organization of secrecy and deception. Sociological Theory, 32(4), 283–306. https://doi.org/10.1177/0735275114558631.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gittleman, M., & Kleiner, M. M. (2016). Wage effects of unionization and occupational licensing coverage in the United States. ILR Review, 69(1), 142–172.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glassman, M., & Mcafee, R. B. (2005). Pay inversion at universities: is it ethical? Journal of Business Ethics, 56(4), 325–333. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-004-5004-x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, B. M., Gutek, B. A., Stein, J. H., & Lewis, K. (2006). Employment discrimination in organizations: Antecedents and consequences. Journal of Management, 32(6), 786–830. https://doi.org/10.1177/0149206306293544.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goleman, D. (2009). Winning in an age of radical transparency. Harvard Business Review. Retrieved December 5, 2018 from https://hbr.org/2009/05/radical-transparency.

  • Grey, C., & Costas, J. (2016). Secrecy at work: The hidden architecture of organizational life. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gumpert, G., & Drucker, S. J. (2007). Through the looking glass: illusions of transparency and the cult of information. Journal of Management Development, 26(5), 493–498.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hasnas, J. (2006). Trapped: when acting ethically is against the law. Washington, D.C: Cato Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heald, D. (2006). Transparency as an INSTRUMENTAL VALue. In C. Hood & D. Heald (Eds.), Transparency: The key to better governance? (pp. 57–73). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heath, J. (2014). Morality, competition, and the firm: The market failures approach to business ethics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hood, C. (2006). Transparency in historical perspective. In C. Hood & D. Heald (Eds.), Transparency: The key to better governance? (pp. 3–33). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, R. C. (2013a). Law and Coercion. Philosophy Compass, 8(3), 231–240. https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12013.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, R. C. (2013b). Law and the entitlement to coerce. In W. Waluchow & S. Sciaraffa (Eds.), Philosophical foundations of the nature of law (pp. 183–206). Oxford: OUP Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jensen, M. C., & Meckling, W. H. (1976). Theory of the firm: Managerial behavior, agency costs and ownership structure. Journal of Financial Economics, 3(4), 305–360. https://doi.org/10.1016/0304-405X(76)90026-X.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jones, G. M. (2014). Secrecy. Annual Review of Anthropology, 43(1), 53–69. https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev-anthro-102313-030058.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Joutsenvirta, M. (2013). Executive pay and legitimacy: changing discursive battles over the morality of excessive manager compensation. Journal of Business Ethics, 116(3), 459–477.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keane, C. (2008). Don’t ask, don’t tell: secrets: Their use and abuse in organizations. Journal of Management Inquiry, 17(2), 107–110. https://doi.org/10.1177/1056492607313233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, T. W., & Donaldson, T. (2016). Rethinking right: Moral epistemology in management research. Journal of Business Ethics. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-015-3009-2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirby, J. (2012). Trust in the age of transparency. Harvard Business Review, 90(7/8), 158–159.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kolstad, I. (2007). Why firms should not always maximize profits. Journal of Business Ethics, 76(2), 137–145.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. M. (1996). The sources of normativity. In O. O’Neill (Ed.). Cambridge, New York: Cambridge University Press.

  • Kulow, M. D. (2013). Beyond the paycheck fairness act: Mandatory wage disclosure laws - a necessary tool for closing the residual gender wage gap. Harvard Journal on Legislation, 2, 385–436.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladkin, D. (2018). ‘The Aesthetic’ and its relationship to business ethics: Philosophical underpinnings and implications for future research. Journal of Business Ethics, 147(1), 35–51. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-015-2928-2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lamming, R. C., Caldwell, N. D., Harrison, D. A., & Phillips, W. (2001). Transparency in supply relationships: Concept and practice. The Journal of Supply Chain Management, 37(4), 4–10. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1745-493X.2001.tb00107.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laufer, W. S. (2007). Law, ethics, and divergent rhetoric. Business Ethics Quarterly, 17(3), 441–447.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laufer, W. S. (2010). Secrecy, silence, and corporate crime reforms. Criminology & Public Policy, 9(3), 455–465. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1745-9133.2010.00641.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laufer, W. S. (2018). A very special regulatory milestone. University of Pennsylvania Journal of Business Law, 2, 392–428.

    Google Scholar 

  • Law, S. A. (2018). Income disparity, gender equality, and free expression. Fordham Law Review, 6, 2479–2500.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawler, E. E. (1972). Secrecy and the need to know. In H. Tosi, R. J. House, & M. D. Dunnette (Eds.), Managerial motivation and compensation (pp. 455–475). East Lansing: Michigan State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawler, E. E. (2012). Pay secrecy: Why bother? Forbes. Retrieved September 2, 2019 from https://www.forbes.com/sites/edwardlawler/2012/09/12/pay-secrecy-why-bother/#7efa7ea26a60.

  • Lawler, E. E. (2014). Why pay secrecy needs to end. Forbes. https://www.forbes.com/sites/edwardlawler/2014/12/17/a-pay-secrecy-rant/#25a5d21dce24. Accessed 7 February 2020.

  • Lerner, J. S., & Tetlock, P. E. (1999). Accounting for the effects of accountability. Psychological Bulletin, 125(2), 255–275. https://doi.org/10.1037/0033-2909.125.2.255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lightfoot, G., & Wisniewski, T. P. (2014). Information asymmetry and power in a surveillance society. Information and Organization, 24(4), 214–235. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.infoandorg.2014.09.001.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lippert-Rasmussen, K. (2013). What is discrimination?. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lobel, O. (forthcoming). Knowledge pays: Reversing information flows & the future of pay equity. Columbia Law Review. Retrieved September 18, 2019 from https://papers.ssrn.com/abstract=3373160.

  • Lyons, S. (2012). Why the law should intervene to disrupt pay-secrecy norms: Analyzing the Lilly Ledbetter Fair Pay Act through the lens of social norms. Columbia Journal of Law and Social Problems, 46, 361–392.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machan, T. R. (2006). Business ethics in a new key. Journal of Private Entetprise, 21(2), 159–172.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mahon, J. E. (2018). Secrets vs lies: Is there a moral asymmetry? In E. Michaelson & A. Stokke (Eds.), Lying: Language, knowledge, ethics, and politics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maitland, I. (1985). The limits of business self-regulation. California Management Review, 27(3), 132–147.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maitland, I. (1989). Rights in the workplace: A Nozickian argument. Journal of Business Ethics, 8(12), 951–954.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marasi, S., & Bennett, R. J. (2016). Pay communication: Where do we go from here? Human Resource Management Review, 26(1), 50–58. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.hrmr.2015.07.002.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marasi, S., Wall, A., & Bennett, R. J. (2018). Pay openness movement: Is it merited? Does it influence more desirable employee outcomes than pay secrecy? Organization Management Journal, 15(2), 58–77. https://doi.org/10.1080/15416518.2018.1471978.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moriarty, J. (2009). How much compensation can CEOs permissibly accept? Business Ethics Quarterly, 19(2), 235–250. https://doi.org/10.5840/beq200919212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moriarty, J. (2012). Justice in compensation: A defense. Business Ethics, 21(1), 64–76. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-8608.2011.01641.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moriarty, J. (2016). Is “equal pay for equal work” merely a principle of nondiscrimination? Economics and Philosophy, 32(03), 435–461.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moriarty, J. (2018). Against pay secrecy. Journal of Applied Philosophy, 35(4), 689–704.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moriarty, J. (2019). On the origin, content, and relevance of the market failures approach. Journal of Business Ethics. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-019-04106-x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moriarty, J. (2020). What’s in a wage? A new approach to the justification of pay. Business Ethics Quarterly, 30(1), 119–137.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morrison, E. W., & Milliken, F. J. (2000). Organizational silence: A barrier to change and development in a pluralistic world. Academy of Management Review, 25(4), 706–725.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1989). The view from nowhere. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nayar, V. (2009). Trust through transparency. Harvard Business Review. Retrieved October 6, 2018 from https://hbr.org/2009/01/trust-through-transparency.

  • Nelson, J. S. (2018). Disclosure-driven crime. U.C. Davis Law Review, 3, 1487–1584.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norman, W. (2011). Business ethics as self-regulation: Why principles that ground regulations should be used to ground beyond-compliance norms as well. Journal of Business Ethics, 102(1), 43–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nosenzo, D. (2013). Pay secrecy and effort provision. Economic Inquiry, 51(3), 1779–1794. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1465-7295.2012.00484.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, O. (2006). Transparency and the ethics of communication. In C. Hood & D. Heald (Eds.), Transparency: The key to better governance?. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, O. (2009). Ethics for communication? European Journal of Philosophy, 17(2), 167–180.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Toole, J., & Bennis, W. (2009). What’s needed next: A culture of candor. Harvard Business Review, 87(6), 54–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oliver, R. E. (2004). What is transparency? (1st ed.). New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Orts, E. W., & Sepinwall, A. (2014). Privacy and organizational persons. Minnesota Law Review, 99, 2275.

    Google Scholar 

  • Otteson, J. R. (2006). Actual ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paine, L. S. (2000). Does ethics pay? Business Ethics Quarterly, 10(1), 319–330. https://doi.org/10.2307/3857716.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Patten, T. H. (1988). Fair pay: The managerial challenge of comparable job worth and job evaluation. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paul, E. F. (2019). Equity and gender. Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Petersen, T., & Saporta, I. (2004). The opportunity structure for discrimination. American Journal of Sociology, 109(4), 852–901. https://doi.org/10.1086/378536.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pfeffer, J. (1981). Power in organizations. Marshfield, MA: Pitman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pfeffer, J., & Cohen, Y. (1984). Determinants of internal labor markets in organizations. Administrative Science Quarterly, 29(4), 550–572. https://doi.org/10.2307/2392939.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pompa, V. (1992). Managerial secrecy: An ethical examination. Journal of Business Ethics, 11(2), 147–156.

    Google Scholar 

  • Porter, N. B. (2013). Women, unions, and negotiation symposium: Democracy and the workplace. Nevada Law Journal, 14(2), 465–495.

    Google Scholar 

  • Porter, N. B., & Vartanian, J. R. (2011). Debunking the market myth in pay discrimination cases. Georgetown Journal of Gender and the Law, 12, 159.

    Google Scholar 

  • Provis, C. (2010). The ethics of impression management. Business Ethics, 19(2), 199–212.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramachandran, G. (2011). Pay transparency. Penn State Law Review, 116, 1043–1080.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rhoads, S. E. (1994). Incomparable worth: Pay equity meets the market. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Risher, H. (2014). Pay transparency is coming. Compensation & Benefits Review, 46(1), 3–5. https://doi.org/10.1177/0886368714537445.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, J. (2009). No one is perfect: The limits of transparency and an ethic for ‘intelligent’ accountability. Accounting, Organizations and Society, 34(8), 957–970. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.aos.2009.04.005.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenfeld, J. (2017). Don’t ask or tell: Pay secrecy policies in US workplaces. Social Science Research, 65, 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sagar, R. (2015). Against moral absolutism: Surveillance and disclosure after snowden. Ethics & International Affairs, 29(2), 145–159. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0892679415000040.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sayers, R. C. (2012). The cost of being female: Critical comment on Block. Journal of Business Ethics, 106(4), 519–524. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-011-1017-4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schauer, F. (1983). Rights and the right to know. Philosophic Exchange, 14(1), 65–74.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheller, E. M., & Harrison, W. (2018). Ignorance is bliss, or is it? The effects of pay transparency, informational justice and distributive justice on pay satisfaction and affective commitment. Compensation & Benefits Review, 50(2), 65–81. https://doi.org/10.1177/0886368719833215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scheppele, K. L. (1988). Legal secrets: Equality and efficiency in the common law. Chicago: University of Chicago press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schipper, F., & Bojé, D. (2008). Transparency, integrity and openness: The nike example. In A. Scherer & G. Palazzo (Eds.), Handbook of research on global corporate citizenship. Worcester: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schnackenberg, A. K., & Tomlinson, E. C. (2016). Organizational transparency: A new perspective on managing trust in organization-stakeholder relationships. Journal of Management, 42(7), 1784–1810. https://doi.org/10.1177/0149206314525202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schrempf-Stirling, J., Palazzo, G., & Phillips, R. A. (2016). Historic corporate social responsibility. Academy of Management Review 41(4), 700–719.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scherer, A. G., & Palazzo, G. (2007). Toward a political conception of corporate responsibility: business and society seen from a habermasian perspective. The Academy of Management Review, 32(4), 1096–1120.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shellenbarger, S. (2016). Open salaries: The good, the bad and the awkward. Wall Street Journal. Retrieved December 8, 2017 from http://www.wsj.com/articles/open-salaries-the-good-the-bad-and-the-awkward-1452624480.

  • Shu, C. (2017). Judge sides with Google in its battle with the Labor Department over employee pay data. TechCrunch. https://techcrunch.com/2017/07/16/judge-sides-with-google-in-its-battle-with-the-labor-department-over-employee-pay-data/. Accessed 7 February 2020.

  • Simmel, G. (1906). The sociology of secrecy and of secret societies. American Journal of Sociology, 11(4), 441–498.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, A. (2018a). Justice failure: efficiency and equality in business ethics. Journal of Business Ethics, 149(1), 97–115.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, D. J. (2018b). How to be an epistemic consequentialist. The Philosophical Quarterly, 68(272), pp. 580–602, https://doi.org/10.1093/pq/pqx056.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smit, B. W., & Montag-Smit, T. (2018). The role of pay secrecy policies and employee secrecy preferences in shaping job attitudes. Human Resource Management Journal, 28(2), 304–324. https://doi.org/10.1111/1748-8583.12180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, D. G. (1997). The shareholder primacy norm. Journal of Corporation Law, 23, 277–324.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, J., & Dubbink, W. (2011). Understanding the role of moral principles in business ethics: A kantian perspective. Business Ethics Quarterly, 21(2), 205–231.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, R. and Tabibnia, G. (2012). Why Radical Transparency Is Good Business. Harvard Business Review. Retrieved October 15, 2018 from https://hbr.org/2012/10/why-radical-transparency-is-good-business.

  • Snedegar, J. (2014). Contrastive reasons and promotion. Ethics, 125(1), 39–63. https://doi.org/10.1086/677025.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sorensen, E. (2019). Comparable worth: Is it a worthy policy?. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stevenson, R. B. (1980). Corporations and information: Secrecy, access and disclosure. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stiglitz, J. E. (2002). Information and the change in the paradigm in economics. American Economic Review, 92(3), 460–501.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strudler, A. (1995). On the ethics of deception in negotiation. Business Ethics Quarterly, 5(4), 805–822. https://doi.org/10.2307/3857416.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strudler, A. (2005). Deception unraveled. The Journal of Philosophy, 102(9), 458–473.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strudler, A. (2017). What to do with corporate wealth. Journal of Political Philosophy, 25(1), 108–126. https://doi.org/10.1111/jopp.12106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, C. R. (1991). Why markets don’t stop discrimination. Social Philosophy and Policy, 8(2), 22–37. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0265052500001114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taurek, J. M. (1977). Should the numbers count? Philosophy & Public Affairs, 6(4), 293–316.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tetlock, P. E. (1983a). Accountability and the perseverance of first impressions. Social Psychology Quarterly, 46(4), 285–292. https://doi.org/10.2307/3033716.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tetlock, P. E. (1983b). Accountability and complexity of thought. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 45(1), 74–83. https://doi.org/10.1037/0022-3514.45.1.74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trotter, R. G., Zacur, S. R., & Stickney, L. T. (2017). The new age of pay transparency. Business Horizons, 60(4), 529–539. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.bushor.2017.03.011.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turilli, M., & Floridi, L. (2009). The ethics of information transparency. Ethics and Information Technology, 11(2), 105–112. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10676-009-9187-9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van De Bunt, H. (2010). Walls of secrecy and silence: The Madoff case and cartels in the construction industry. Criminology & Public Policy, 9(3), 435–453.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van den Hoven, J., & Rooksby, E. (2008). Distributive justice and the value of information: A (Broadly) Rawlsian approach. In J. Van den Hoven & J. Weckert (Eds.), Information technology and moral philosophy (pp. 376–395). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Veldman, T. (2017). Pay transparency in the EU. Luxembourg: Publications Office of the European Union.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wakabayashi, D. (2017, September 8). At Google, employee-led effort finds men are paid more than women. The New York Times. Retrieved January 29, 2018 from https://www.nytimes.com/2017/09/08/technology/google-salaries-gender-disparity.html.

  • Waluchow, W. (1988). Pay equity: Equal value to whom? Journal of Business Ethics, 7(3), 185–189.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wexler, M. N. (1987). Conjectures on the dynamics of secrecy and the secrets business. Journal of Business Ethics, 6(6), 469–480.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkin, S. (2009). Heed the calls for transparency. Harvard Business Review, 87(7/8), 16–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (1981). Persons, character, and morality. In J. Rachels (Ed.), Moral luck: Philosophical papers (pp. 1973–1980). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wynn, A. T., & Correll, S. J. (2018). Combating gender bias in modern workplaces. In B. J. Risman, C. M. Froyum, & W. J. Scarborough (Eds.), Handbook of the sociology of gender (pp. 509–521). Cham: Springer International Publishing. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-76333-0_37.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Department of Labor. (n.d.). Frequently asked questions pay transparency regulations. Office of Federal Contract Compliances Programs. https://www.dol.gov/ofccp/regs/compliance/faqs/PayTransparencyFAQs.html#Q2.

  • Young, I. M. (2010). Responsibility for justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, C. (2019). Putting the law in its place: Business ethics and the assumption that illegal implies unethical. Journal of Business Ethics, 160(1), 35–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zuboff, S. (1989). In the age of the smart machine: The future of work and power (Reprint ed.). New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zwolinski, M. (2007). Sweatshops, choice, and exploitation. Business Ethics Quarterly, 17(4), 689–727. https://doi.org/10.2307/27673206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The author would like to thank audiences at the Wharton-INSEAD Doctoral Consortium, Society for Business Ethics, and Academy of Management. He would also like to thank Tom Donaldson, Vikram Bhargava, Alan Strudler, Dan Singer, Tae Wan Kim, Amy Sepinwall, and Carson Young for invaluable comments and discussions. Two anonymous referees also provided comments that benefited this article greatly.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Matthew Caulfield.

Ethics declarations

Conflicts of interest

There are no conflicts of interest in publishing this article. Funding support was provided by the Institute for Humane Studies.

Ethical Approval

No human subjects were involved in this research, and my research has complied with all ethical standards.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Caulfield, M. Pay Secrecy, Discrimination, and Autonomy. J Bus Ethics 171, 399–420 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-020-04455-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-020-04455-y

Keywords

Navigation