Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Accountable to Whom? Rethinking the Role of Corporations in Political CSR

  • Published:
Journal of Business Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

State sovereignty is undermined to the extent that powerful corporations are involved in the exercise of political authority without being legitimated for this and without submitting to the usual responsibilities incumbent on government authorities.

—Jürgen Habermas, Between Facts and Norms, pp. 433–434.

Abstract

According to Palazzo and Scherer, the changing role of business corporations in society requires that we take new measures to integrate these organizations into society-wide processes of democratic governance. We argue that their model of integration has a fundamental problem. Instead of treating business corporations as agents that must be held accountable to the democratic reasoning of affected parties, it treats corporations as agents who can hold others accountable. In our terminology, it treats business corporations as “supervising authorities” rather than “functionaries.” The result is that Palazzo and Scherer’s model does not actually address the democratic deficit that it is meant to solve. In order to fix the problem, we advocate removing business corporations from any policymaking role in political CSR and limiting participation to political NGOs and other groups that meet the standards we set out for a politically representative organization (PRO).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Both of these claims might be challenged. With respect to the first one, it might be denied that the new role of corporations creates a democratic deficit. As long as there is a legitimate state functioning in the background, it might be thought why is it a problem for democracy if corporations provide public goods and engage in self-regulation? With respect to the second claim, it might be denied that deliberative democracy is a promising way to remedy this deficit. Deliberation presupposes a level of knowledge and rationality that many citizens may not have. These challenges are important. If they succeed, then they cast doubt on, respectively, the necessity of a democratic response to political CSR, and the value of a democratic response to political CSR that is deliberative. We do not pursue these challenges here, as doing so would take us far outside of the scope of this paper (but see Hussain and Moriarty 2014). Moreover, we think that these challenges can be rebutted. We focus on developing our own (different) challenge to Palazzo and Scherer’s model of democratic accountability for corporations.

  2. Relevant considerations include moral considerations, considerations stemming from a shared political identity, and considerations connected with a fair compromise between different views. For the sake of simplicity, we leave aside Habermas’s view that the legislature in a constitutional democracy should function as an arena in which representatives can authoritatively reach fair compromises between competing social interests.

  3. In saying that society should be governed by the free, unforced deliberation of its “members” we are assuming that, in most cases, the parties who may be affected by an authoritative legal norm will be members of the society. But to avoid confusion, we want to be explicit about participation. At the most basic level, Habermas thinks that participation in institutionally defined forms of deliberation is determined by the “all affected principle” (see our discussion of this principle in “What Role Should Corporations Play?” section). So on his account, deliberative democracy requires that society should be governed by free, unforced, rational deliberation among all those who are possibly affected by society’s authoritative legal norms.

  4. Various features of social life may need to be altered to achieve these goals (Cohen 1989; Mansbridge 1999). For example, to ensure that all citizens can participate in the deliberative process, it may be necessary to restructure ownership rights in the mass media so that everyone has adequate access to newspapers, television, the internet, and other channels of communication. It may be necessary to enact limits on work hours to ensure that citizens have the time to read newspapers, think about important public issues, and participate in public debate. It may further be necessary for citizens to have access to adequate resources, so that they can engage with each other in deliberation as equals rather than as dependents.

  5. This is a list of functions that states legitimately perform, not a list of functions they actually perform. In addition to these legitimate functions, states perform other illegitimate functions, such as suppressing the free speech of their own citizens, and invading other states without just cause.

  6. Since corporations may engage in political activity across national boundaries, we might ask: which states should play these roles? The state that is the “home” of the corporation, or the state that is its “host”? Or some other state? These are good questions, and Palazzo and Scherer do not supply answers to them. As a first approximation, we might suppose that they would give the same answer to this question as they give to the question of who should participate in deliberation about a decision. So, if all parties affected by a decision should have a right to participate in deliberating about it, then all states affected by a decision have a right, or perhaps a duty, to regulate the deliberation about it. Nothing in our paper hangs on how these questions are answered, however, so we set them aside.

  7. For a description of the FSC’s governance system, see http://www.fsc.org/governance.html.

  8. Other writers, including Edward and Willmott (2008) and Moog et al. (2015) have criticized the FSC in connection with Palazzo and Scherer’s model of democratic accountability for corporations. But our criticism is novel. Edward and Willmott claim that the FSC gives too much weight to the voices of “certification bodies and commercial clients” and not enough weight to the voices of “local communities and indigenous people” (p. 420). We are claiming that institutions like the FSC should not give any weight to corporate voices in policymaking, at least insofar as they are understood as supervising authorities. Put another way, Edward and Willmott think that the FSC does not live up to the model of democratic accountability described by Palazzo and Scherer. We believe the model itself is flawed. Moog, Spicer, and Böhm argue that the effectiveness of the FSC (and other multi-stakeholder initiatives, or MSIs) is “significantly limited by the broader political and economic context in which they operate” (p. 471), and has failed to achieve its ultimate goals “of reducing deforestation and forest degradation (p. 484). They do not challenge, as we do, the role that corporations play in the FSC and other MSIs, only the value of the outcomes achieved by these initiatives.

  9. We agree with Baur and Palazzo, who recognize that only legitimate groups in society—those who are civil, engage in argument, and make good faith efforts to reach agreement—should be permitted to participate in social deliberation (Baur 2011; Baur and Palazzo 2011; see also Baur and Arenas 2014). But we think that there are further conditions that should restrict whether an organization can participate in social deliberation.

  10. A complication is that people tend to associate with others who are like themselves. Thus, if a person were faced with a choice of joining two basketball teams, one whose members shared his political views, and another whose members did not—but which were otherwise identical—he would probably choose the former. We do not believe that this poses a serious threat to our claim, however. The main reasons that people join and leave, e.g., basketball teams are basketball related. Non-basketball-related considerations—political preferences, musical tastes, religious identities, and so on—play a role only at the margins. The same is true, we will see, of corporations. Faced with a choice of joining one firm or another, a person may give preference to a firm whose employees share her political (or musical or religious) views over one whose employees do not. But these considerations will be secondary to whether the person is willing and able to perform the tasks the job requires. The same is true from the firm’s side: job-related-reasons will dominate non-job-related reasons in its decision to extend an offer of employment or not.

  11. In saying ‘mainly’ here, we acknowledge the possibility that workers, managers, and shareholders participate in the corporation in part because of non-economic interests, e.g., because they endorse the corporations’ values or certain non-economic aspects of its mission statement (see, e.g., Meyer and Allen 1997). We thank an anonymous reviewer for stressing this point.

  12. It might be objected that we could allow for business corporations to play a role in the governance processes described by Palazzo and Scherer as supervising authorities, so long as we take adequate measures to neutralize the asymmetric power that these organizations have with respect to the other parties. Note that our criticism does not appeal to the idea of power differentials. The key point is that business corporations are embedded in market competition, so they are under constant pressure to make profits. This creates a constant pressure to make arguments in support of policies that would generate higher profits, rather arguments in support of policies that would advance the common good. So the problem is that business corporations lack the proper motivation to participate in governance process as a supervising authority.

  13. The other “side” of this problem, as it were, is that some legitimate interests may not be represented by NGOs. So even if all legitimate NGOs participate in deliberation, not all voices may be heard. More generally, we acknowledge that hard questions must be asked about who should participate in deliberative processes (Banerjee 2014; Baur and Palazzo 2011). We leave these questions for future research. Our focus in this paper is on who should not participate in them, viz., corporations, because they are not PROs.

  14. We thank an anonymous referee for this point.

  15. This paper is equally the work of both authors. For helpful comments on it, we thank two anonymous reviewers for the Journal of Business Ethics.

References

  • Anderson, E. (1993). Value in ethics and economics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Archer, R. (1996). The philosophical case for economic democracy. In U. Pagano & B. Rowthorn (Eds.), Democracy and efficiency in the economic enterprise (pp. 13–35). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Banerjee, S. B. (2014). A critical perspective on corporate social responsibility: Towards a global goverance framework. Critical Perspectives on International Business, 10(1/2), 84–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baur, D. (2011). NGOs as legitimate partners of corporations: A political conceptualization. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baur, D., & Arenas, D. (2014). The value of unregulated business–NGO interaction: A deliberative perspective. Business and Society, 53(2), 157–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baur, D., & Palazzo, G. (2011). The moral legitimacy of NGOs as partners of corporations. Business Ethics Quarterly, 21(4), 579–604.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beitz, C. R. (1989). Political equality: An essay in democratic theory. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boatright, J. R. (1994). Fiduciary duties and the shareholder–management relation: Or, what’s so special about shareholders? Business Ethics Quarterly, 4(4), 393–407.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boatright, J. R. (2004). Employee governance and the ownership of the firm. Business Ethics Quarterly, 14(1), 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brenkert, G. G. (1992a). Freedom, participation, and corporations: The issue of corporate (economic) democracy. Business Ethics Quarterly, 2(3), 251–269.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brenkert, G. G. (1992b). Private corporations and public welfare. Public Affairs Quarterly, 6(2), 155–168.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, J. (1989). Deliberation and democratic legitimacy. In A. Hamlin & P. Pettit (Eds.), The good polity: Normative analysis of the state (pp. 17–34). New York: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cragg, W. (2000). Human rights and business ethics: Fashioning a new social contract. Journal of Business Ethics, 27(1/2), 205–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crane, A., Matten, D., & Moon, J. (2008). Corporations and citizenship. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dahl, R. A. (1985). A preface to economic democracy. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dahl, R. A. (1989). Democracy and its critics. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Doh, J. P. (2005). Offshore outsourcing: Implications for international business and strategic management theory and practice. Journal of Management Studies, 42(3), 695–703.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Edward, P., & Willmott, H. (2008). Structures, identities, and politics: Bringing corporate citizenship into the corporation. In A. G. Scherer & G. Palazzo (Eds.), Handbook of research on global corporate citizenship (pp. 405–429). Northampton, MA: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellerman, D. P. (1992). Property and contract in economics: The case for economic democracy. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fort, T. L., & Schipani, C. A. (2004). The role of business in fostering peaceful societies. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Frynas, J. G., & Stephens, S. (2015). Political corporate social responsibility: Reviewing theories and setting new agendas. International Journal of Management Reviews, 17(4), 483–509.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodin, R. E. (2007). Enfranchising all affected interests and its alternatives. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 35(1), 40–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gutmann, A., & Thompson, D. F. (2004). Why deliberative democracy?. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1984). The theory of communicative action. Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1989). The structural transformation of the public sphere: An inquiry into a category of bourgeois society. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1996). Between facts and norms: Contributions to a discourse theory of law and democracy (W. Rehg, Trans.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Hansmann, H. (1996). The ownership of enterprise. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hsieh, N.-H. (2005). Rawlsian justice and workplace republicanism. Social Theory & Practice, 31(1), 115–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hussain, W. (2012). Is ethical consumerism an impermissible form of vigilantism? Philosophy & Public Affairs, 40(2), 111–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hussain, W. (2013, August 17). [Review of the book Public Capitalism: The Political Authority of Corporate Executives, by C. McMahon]. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. Retrieved from https://ndpr.nd.edu/news/41657-public-capitalism-the-political-authority-of-corporate-executives/.

  • Hussain, W., & Moriarty, J. (2014). Corporations, the democratic deficit, and voting. Georgetown Journal of Law & Public Policy, 12(special issue), 429–450.

  • Jensen, M. C. (2002). Value maximization, stakeholder theory, and the corporate objective function. Business Ethics Quarterly, 12(2), 235–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kobrin, S. J. (2009). Private political authority and public responsibility: Transnational politics, transnational firms, and human rights. Business Ethics Quarterly, 19(3), 349–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mansbridge, J. (1999). Everyday talk in the deliberative system. In S. Macedo (Ed.), Deliberative politics: Essays on democracy and disagreement (pp. 211–239). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matten, D., & Crane, A. (2005). Corporate citizenship: Toward an extended theoretical conceptualization. Academy of Management Review, 30(1), 166–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCall, J. J. (2001). Employee voice in corporate governance: A defense of strong participation rights. Business Ethics Quarterly, 11(1), 195–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McMahon, C. (1994). Authority and democracy: A general theory of government and management. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McMahon, C. (2013). Public capitalism: The political authority of corporate executives. Philadelphia, PA: University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meyer, J. P., & Allen, N. J. (1997). Commitment in the workplace: Theory, research, and application. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moog, S., Spicer, A., & Böhm, S. (2015). The politics of multi-stakeholder initiatives: The crisis of the Forest Stewardship Council. Journal of Business Ethics, 128(3), 469–493.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moriarty, J. (2014). Stakeholder theory and stakeholder democracy: An excavation and defense. Business and Society, 53(6), 820–852.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Palazzo, G., & Scherer, A. G. (2006). Corporate legitimacy as deliberation: A communicative framework. Journal of Business Ethics, 66(1), 71–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1993). Political liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubenstein, J. C. (2013). The misuse of power, not bad representation: Why it is beside the point that no one elected Oxfam. Journal of Political Philosophy, 22(2), 204–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruggie, J. G. (2004). Reconstituting the global public domain: Issues, actors, and practices. European Journal of International Relations, 10(4), 499–531.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scherer, A. G., & Palazzo, G. (2007). Toward a political conception of corporate responsibility: Business and society seen from a Habermasian perspective. Academy of Management Review, 32(4), 1096–1120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scherer, A. G., & Palazzo, G. (2011). The new political role of business in a globalized world: A review of a new perspective on CSR and its implications for the firm, governance, and democracy. Journal of Management Studies, 48(4), 899–931.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scherer, A. G., Palazzo, G., & Baumann, D. (2006). Global rules and private actors: Toward a new role of the transnational corporation in global governance. Business Ethics Quarterly, 16(4), 505–532.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (1974/2012). All animals are equal. In D. Schmidtz & E. Willott (Eds.), Environmental ethics: What really matters, what really works (pp. 49–59). New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Vogel, D. (2010). The private regulation of global corporate conduct: Achievements and limitations. Business and Society, 49(1), 68–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whelan, F. G. (1983). Prologue: Democratic theory and the boundary problem. In J. R. Pennock & J. W. Chapman (Eds.), Liberal democracy (pp. 13–47). New York: New York University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jeffrey Moriarty.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Hussain, W., Moriarty, J. Accountable to Whom? Rethinking the Role of Corporations in Political CSR. J Bus Ethics 149, 519–534 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-016-3027-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-016-3027-8

Keywords

Navigation