Journal of Business Ethics

, Volume 142, Issue 1, pp 59–70 | Cite as

Beyond Coercion: Moral Assessment in the Labour Market

Article

Abstract

Some libertarians argue that informed consent alone makes transactions in the labour market morally justified. In contrast, some of their critics claim that such an act of consent is no guarantee against coercion. To know whether agreements are voluntary, we need to assess the quality of the offers or the prevailing background conditions. ISCT theorists argue that it is imperative to take social norms into account when evaluating the labour market. We present a novel framework for moral assessment in the labour market, which takes consent, background conditions and norms into account, but which mainly focuses on the offers and demands made. Consent renders a transaction legitimate in the same way we regard a fair election legitimate even if we object to its outcome. For offers to be substantially justified, exploitation must be avoided and offers must give expression to the value of community. Only then they are morally justified.

Keywords

Coercion Consent Exploitation Labour market Legitimacy Moral community 

References

  1. Basu, K. (2007). Coercion, contract and the limits of the market. Social Choice and Welfare, 29(4), 559–579.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Bowie, N. E. (1991). The firm as a moral community. In R. M. Coughlin (Ed.), Morality, rationality, and efficiency: New perspectives on socio-economics (pp. 169–183). Armonk, NY: M. E. Sharp.Google Scholar
  3. Bruni, L., & Sugden, R. (2008). Fraternity: Why the market need not be a morally free zone. Economics and Philosophy, 24, 35–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Calder, T. (2005). Kant and degrees of wrongness. Journal of Value Inquiry, 39, 229–242.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Cohen, G. A. (1983). The Structure of proletarian unfreedom. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 12, 3–33.Google Scholar
  6. Cohen, G. A. (1985). Are workers forced to sell their labor power? Philosophy & Public Affairs, 14, 99–105.Google Scholar
  7. Cohen, G. A. (1992). Incentives, inequality and community. The Tanner Lectures on Human Values, 13, 263–329.Google Scholar
  8. Dahl, R. (1989). Democracy and its critics. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Des Jardins, J. R., & McCall, J. J. (1985). A defense of employee rights. Journal of Business Ethics, 4, 367–376.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Donaldson, T., & Dunfee, T. W. (1994). Toward a unified conception of business ethics: Integrative social contracts theory. The Academy of Management Review, 19, 252–284.Google Scholar
  11. Donaldson, T., & Dunfee, T. W. (1995). Integrative social contracts theory. Economics and Philosophy, 11, 85–112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Freeman, R. E. (2001). Stakeholder theory of the modern corporation. In W. M. Hoffman, R. E. Frederick, & M. S. Schwartz (Eds.), Business ethics: Readings and cases in corporate morality (4th ed., pp. 38–48). Boston: McGraw Hill.Google Scholar
  13. Friedman, M. (1982). Capitalism and freedom. London: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  14. Gauthier, D. (1986). Morals by agreement. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  15. Gilbert, M. (1993). Agreements, coercion and obligation. Ethics, 103, 679–706.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Goodin, R. (2006). Volenti goes to market. The Journal of Ethics, 10, 53–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Hausman, D. (1989). Are markets morally free zones? Philosophy & Public Affairs, 18, 317–333.Google Scholar
  18. Hershowitz, S. (2003). Legitimacy, democracy and Razian authority. Legal Theory, 9, 201–220.Google Scholar
  19. International Labor Organization (ILO). (1998). Declaration on fundamental principles and rights at work. Retrieved March 10, 2015 from http://www.ilo.org/declaration/thedeclaration/textdeclaration/lang–en/index.htm
  20. Kant, I. [1787] (1969). Foundation of the metaphysics of morals (L. W. Beck, Trans.). Indianapolis: Bobbs-MerrillGoogle Scholar
  21. Lindblom, L. (2011). The structure of a Rawlsian theory of just work. Journal of Business Ethics, 101, 577–599.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Macpherson, C. (1968). Elegant tombstones: A note on Friedman’s freedom. Canadian Journal of Political Science, 1, 95–106.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Maitland, I. (1997). The great non-debate over international sweatshops. British Academy of Management Annual Proceedings (pp. 240–265).Google Scholar
  24. Mayer, R. (2007a). What’s wrong with exploitation? Journal of Applied Philosophy, 24, 137–150.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Mayer, R. (2007b). Sweatshops, exploitation and moral responsibility. Journal of Social Philosophy, 38, 605–619.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Murphy, J. (1981). Consent, coercion and hard choices. Virginia Law Review, 67, 79–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Nozick, R. (1974). Anarchy, state and utopia. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  28. O’Neill, O. (1985). Between consenting adults. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 14, 252–277.Google Scholar
  29. Olsaretti, S. (1998). Freedom, force and choice: Against the right-based definition of voluntariness. The Journal of Political Philosophy, 6, 53–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Peter, F. (2004). Choice, consent and the legitimacy of market transactions. Economics and Philosophy, 20, 1–18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Radin, T. J., & Werhane, P. H. (2003). Employment-at-will, employee rights, and future directions for employment. Business Ethics Quarterly, 13, 113–130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  33. Rowan, J. R. (2000). The moral foundation of employee rights. Journal of Business Ethics, 24, 355–361.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Ruggie, J. (2011). Guiding principles on business and human rights: Implementing the UN ‘protect, respect and remedy’ framework. Report of the Special Representative of the Secretary General on the Issue of Human Rights and Transnational Corporations and Other Business Enterprises. UN Doc. A/HRC/17/31.Google Scholar
  35. Sandel, M. (1998). What money can’t buy: The moral limits of markets. The Tanner Lectures on Human Values, 21, 87–122.Google Scholar
  36. Scanlon, T. M. (1998). What we owe to each other. London: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  37. Shiffrin, S. (2007). The divergence of contract and promise. Harvard Law Review, 120, 709–752.Google Scholar
  38. Stern, R. (2004). Does ‘ought’ imply ‘can’? And did Kant think it does? Utilitas, 16, 42–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Strawson, P. F. (2008). Freedom and resentment and other essays. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  40. UN General Assembly. (1948). The universal declaration of human rights. Resolution adopted by the general assembly 10/12. United Nations, New York.Google Scholar
  41. Van Buren, H. J, I. I. I. (2001). If fairness is the problem, is consent the solution? Integrating ISCT and stakeholder theory. Business Ethics Quarterly, 11, 481–499.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Walker, M. U. (2006). Moral repair: Reconstructing moral relations after wrongdoing. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Zimmerman, D. (1981). Coercive wage offers. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 10, 121–145.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of Philosophy and HistoryRoyal Institute of Technology (KTH)StockholmSweden
  2. 2.Department of Historical, Philosophical and Religious StudiesUmeå UniversityUmeåSweden

Personalised recommendations