Journal of Business Ethics

, Volume 117, Issue 4, pp 695–706 | Cite as

A Constructivist Approach to Business Ethics

Article

Abstract

A recurrent challenge in applied ethics concerns the development of principles that are both suitably general to cover various cases and sufficiently exact to guide behavior in particular instances. In business ethics, two central approaches—stockholder and stakeholder—often fail by one or the other requirement. The author argues that the failure is precipitated by their reliance upon “universal” theory, which views the justification of principles as both independent of their context of application and universally appropriate to all contexts. The author develops a contextual interpretation of “constructivism” as an alternative approach, and argues that this alternative meets the above challenge.

Keywords

Constructivism Contextualism Universalism Manager responsibility Pharmaceuticals Health impact fund 

References

  1. Barry, B. (1990). Political argument: A reissue with a new introduction. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  2. Bates, B. C., Kundzewics, Z. W., Wu, S. & Palutikof, J. P. (Eds.) (2008). Climate change and water: Implications for policy and sustainable development. In Intergovernmental panel on climate change. Technical Paper VI. Retrieved December 15, 2011, from http://www.ipcc.ch/pdf/technical-papers/ccw/chapter7.pdf.
  3. Boatright, J. (2006). What’s wrong—And what’s right—With stakeholder management. Journal of Private Enterprise, 21(2), 106–130.Google Scholar
  4. Brand, V. (2009). Empirical business ethics research and paradigm analysis. Journal of Business Ethics, 86, 429–449.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Carroll, A., & Buchholtz, A. K. (2011). Business and society: Ethics, sustainability, and stakeholder management. Cincinnati: South-Western Publishing.Google Scholar
  6. Cohen, G. A. (2008). Rescuing justice & equality. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  7. Danzon, P. M., & Towse, A. (2003). Differential pricing for pharmaceuticals: Reconciling access, R&D and patents. International Journal of Health Care Finance and Economics, 3(3), 183–205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. De George, R. (2005). Intellectual property and pharmaceutical drugs: An ethical analysis. Business Ethics Quarterly, 15(4), 549–575.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. DiMasi, J. A., Hansen, R. W., & Grabowski, H. G. (2003). The price of innovation: New estimates of drug development costs. Journal of Health Economics, 22, 151–185.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Donaldson, T. (1999). Making stakeholder theory whole. Academy of Management Review, 24(2), 237–241.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Donaldson, T., & Preston, Lee. E. (1995). The stakeholder theory of the corporation: Concepts, evidence, and implications. Academy of Management Review, 20(1), 65–91.Google Scholar
  12. Drucker, P. (1981). What is business ethics? The Public Interest, 63, 18–36.Google Scholar
  13. Economist. (2005). Special report: A survey of corporate social responsibility. Retrieved January 20, 2005, from http://www.economist.com/node/3555212.
  14. Economist. (2011). Diving into the rich pool. Retrieved September 24, 2011, from http://www.economist.com/node/21530093.
  15. Freeman, R. E. (1984). Strategic management: A stakeholder approach. Boston: Pitman.Google Scholar
  16. Freeman, R. E. (2002). Stakeholder theory of the modern corporation. In T. Donaldson, P. Werhane, & M. Cording (Eds.), Ethical issues in business (7th ed., pp. 38–49). Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
  17. Friedman, M., (1970, September 13). The social responsibility of business is to increase its profits. New York Times Magazine.Google Scholar
  18. Friedman, M. (1982). Capitalism and freedom. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  19. Garriga, E., & Melé, D. (2004). Corporate social responsibility theories: Mapping the territory. Journal of Business Ethics, 53, 51–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Gibson, K. (2000). The moral basis of stakeholder theory. Journal of Business Ethics, 26, 245–257.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Gini, Al., & Marcoux, A. (2012). The ethics of business: A concise introduction. Lanham, ML: The Roman & Littlefield Publishing Group.Google Scholar
  22. Guba, E. G., & Yvonna, S. L. (1994). Competing paradigms in qualitative research. In N. Denzin & Y. Lincoln (Eds.), Handbook of qualitative research. London: Sage Publications.Google Scholar
  23. Hardin, Gt. (1968). The tragedy of the commons. Science, New Series, 162(3859), 1243–1248.Google Scholar
  24. Harris, G. (2012). Citing drug resistance, U.S. restricts more antibiotics for livestock. New York Times. Retrieved from http://www.nytimes.com/2012/01/05/health/policy/fda-restricts-use-of-antibiotics-in-livestock.html?scp=1&sq=FDA%20restricts%20use%20of%20antibiotics%20in%20livestock&st=cse.
  25. Hasnas, J. (1998). The normative theories of business ethics: A guide for the perplexed. Business Ethics Quarterly, 8(1), 19–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Heath, J. (2006). Business ethics without stakeholders. Business Ethics Quarterly, 16(4), 533–557.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Hollis, A., & Pogge, T. (2008). The health impact fund: Making new medicines accessible for all. New Haven: Incentives for Global Health.Google Scholar
  28. Kaul, I., Gurnberg, I., & Stern, M. A. (Eds.). (1999). Global public goods: International cooperation in the 21st century. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  29. Korsgaard, C. (2003). Realism and constructivism in twentieth-century moral philosophy. Journal of Philosophical Research, APA Centennial Supplement, 28, 99–122.Google Scholar
  30. Le Grand, J. (1990). Equity versus efficiency: The elusive trade-off. Ethics, 100(3), 554–568.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Le Grand, J., Robinson, R., & Propper, C. (1992). The economics of social problems (3rd ed.). Hong Kong: MacMillan Press.Google Scholar
  32. MacIntyre, A. (1984). After virtue (2nd ed.). Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
  33. Maitland, I. (2002). Priceless goods: How should life-saving drugs be priced? Business Ethics Quarterly, 12(4), 451–480.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Mankiw, N. G. (2009). Principles of microeconomics (5th ed.). Mason, OH: South-Western Cengage Learning.Google Scholar
  35. Mankiw, N. G. (2012). Principles of economics (6th ed.). Mason, OH: South-Western Cengage Learning.Google Scholar
  36. Marcoux, A. (2006). The concept of business in business ethics. Journal of Private Enterprise, 21(2), 50–67.Google Scholar
  37. McVea, J., & Freeman, R. E. (2005). A names-and-faces approach to stakeholder management. Journal of Management Inquiry, 14, 57–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Mill, J. S. [1848] (1977). On liberty. In J. M. Robson (Ed.), Collected works of John Stuart Mill. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
  39. Miller, D. (2002). Two ways to think about justice. Politics, Philosophy & Economics, 1(5), 5–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Morrell, K., & Clark, I. (2010). Private equity and the public good. Journal of Business Ethics, 96, 249–263.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Nussbaum, M. (1999). Sex and social justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  42. O’Conner, J. (2005). Dissenting. Kelo v New London, 545 U.S., 10–11.Google Scholar
  43. Okun, A. (1975). Equality and efficiency: The big trade-off. Washington, DC: Brookings Institution.Google Scholar
  44. Olson, S. (1995). Old guards, young Turks, and the $64,000 question: What is business ethics? Business Ethics Quarterly, 5(2), 371–379.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Orts, E. W., & Strudler, A. (2009). Putting a stake in stakeholder theory. Journal of Business Ethics, 88, 605–615.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Outterson, K. (2005). Pharmaceutical arbitrage: Balancing access and innovation in international prescription drug markets. Yale Journal of Health Policy, Law and Ethics, 5, 193–291.Google Scholar
  47. Phillips, R., Freeman, R. E., & Wicks, A. C. (2003). What stakeholder theory is not. Business Ethics Quarterly, 13(4), 479–502.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Pogge, T. (2009a). Global public policy: Definition and globalization. Retrieved from http://www.ony.unu.edu/events-forums/new/GPP/2009/global-public-policy-roundtabl.php.
  49. Pogge, T. (2009b). The health impact fund and its justification by appeal to human rights. Journal of Social Philosophy, 40(4), 542–569.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Rawls, J. (1993). Political liberalism (2nd ed.). New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
  51. Rawls, J. (1999a). A theory of justice (revised ed.). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  52. Rawls, J. (1999b). Kantian constructivism in moral theory. In S. Freeman (Ed.), John Rawls: Collected papers. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  53. Rawls, J. (1999c). The law of peoples. In S. Freeman (Ed.), John Rawls: Collected papers. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  54. Rawls, J. (2001). Justice as fairness: A restatement. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  55. Rossouw, D., & Christoph, S. (Eds.) (2012). Global survey of business ethics: Teaching, training and research (Globethics.net). Retrieved from www.globethics.net.
  56. Schwandt, T. (1994). Constructivist, interpretivist approaches to human inquiry. In N. Denzin & Y. Lincoln (Eds.), Handbook of qualitative research. London: Sage Publications.Google Scholar
  57. Scriven, M. (1995). The philosophical foundations of Las Vegas. Journal of Gambling Studies, 11(1), 61–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  58. Sen, A. (2009). The idea of justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  59. Solomon, R. & Clancey, M. (2003). Above the bottom line: An introduction to business ethics (3rd ed.). Belmont: Wadsworth.Google Scholar
  60. Sonderholm, J. (2009). Paying a high price for low costs: Why there should be no legal constraints on the profits that can be made on drugs for tropical diseases. Journal of Medical Ethics, 35, 309–313.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  61. Sowell, T. (2000). Basic economics: A citizen’s guide to the economy. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
  62. Stark, A. (1993). What’s the matter with business ethics? Harvard Business Review, 71, 38–48.Google Scholar
  63. Sternberg, E. (2000). Just business. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  64. Street, S. (2010). What is constructivism in ethics and metaethics. Philosophy Compass, 5(5), 363–384.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  65. UNDP Human Development Report. (2003). Millennium development goals: A compact among nations to end poverty. New York: Oxford University Press. Retrieved from http://hdr.undp.org/en/media/hdr03_complete.pdf.
  66. US v. Microsoft Corp. (1998). 97 F. Supp. 2d 59—District Court, District of Columbia. Retrieved from http://www.justice.gov/atr/cases/f1700/1763.htm.
  67. Watkins, K., et al. (2006). United Nations development report 2006: Beyond scarcity: power, poverty and the global water crisis. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
  68. Wendt, A. (1992). Anarchy is what states make of it: The social construction of power politics. International Organization, 46(2), 391–425.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  69. Werhane, P. H. (1999). Moral imagination and management decision-making. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  70. Werhane, P. H. (2008). Mental models, moral imagination and systems thinking in the age of globalization. Journal of Business Ethics, 78, 463–474.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  71. Wittgenstein, L. (1958). Philosophical investigations (3rd ed.). In G. E. M. Anscombe (trans.). New York: Macmillian Publishing Co. Inc.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Philosophy DepartmentLehman College, CUNYBronxUSA

Personalised recommendations