Abstract
Social norms are commonly understood as rules that dictate which behaviors are appropriate, permissible, or obligatory in different situations for members of a given community. Many researchers have sought to explain the ubiquity of social norms in human life in terms of the psychological mechanisms underlying their acquisition, conformity, and enforcement. Existing theories of the psychology of social norms appeal to a variety of constructs, from prediction-error minimization, to reinforcement learning, to shared intentionality, to domain-specific adaptations for norm acquisition. In this paper, we propose a novel methodological and conceptual framework for the cognitive science of social norms that we call normative pluralism. We begin with an analysis of the (sometimes mixed) explanatory aims of the cognitive science of social norms. From this analysis, we derive a recommendation for a reformed conception of its explanandum: a minimally psychological construct that we call normative regularities. Our central empirical proposal is that the psychological underpinnings of social norms are most likely realized by a heterogeneous set of cognitive, motivational, and ecological mechanisms that vary between norms and between individuals, rather than by a single type of process or distinctive norm system. This pluralistic approach, we suggest, offers a methodologically sound point of departure for a fruitful and rigorous science of social norms.
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
Understood this way, moral psychology might be best understood as a form of applied psychology like the psychology of sport, or consumer behavior, which do not presume that their objects of study carve nature at its joints.
All references to “norms,” “normativity,” or “normative cognition” in this paper should be understood as referring to social norms, unless we specify otherwise.
There are some signs that certain norm theorists could be open to this kind of cognitive-level pluralism. For example, Theriault and colleagues distinguish between four different potential motivations for social conformity: informational influence, when a person copies others because they are perceived to be knowledgeable; reputation-seeking, when a person conforms in order to seek praise or avoid blame; social obligation, when a person feels obligated to conform to others’ expectations; and moral obligation, when a person conforms because they are motivated by independently held values or convictions (Theriault et al. 2021). Daniel Kelly has also distinguished between at least two different cognitive pathways for adopting a norm, which he calls internalization and avowal. Norm internalization occurs when a normative rule is adopted via automatic, functionally specific “System 1” processes that also cause us to become intrinsically motivated to conform to and enforce that rule. Norm avowal occurs when a norm is intentionally adopted via slow, effortful “System 2” processes, with the explicit goal of self-regulation (Kelly 2022).
One concern about tying the concept of normative regularities to patterns of behavioral conformity is that many familiar examples of social norms focus on behavioral prohibitions about what agents must not do rather that behavioral prescriptions about what they should do. Intuitively, members of a community not taking a certain action does not seem like the sort of thing that one could easily observe. Fortunately, there are ways around this obstacle. One way to infer whether a behavior of a certain type is prohibited is to look for signs that it elicits negative social maintenance. If every time a child writes with their left hand, an adult strikes them and forces them to use their right hand instead, that is a sign that writing with the left hand is prohibited. Notably, this approach would have limited use when it comes to studying strong behavioral prohibitions that are rarely or never violated. However, the presence of such normative prohibitions can be inferred by drawing comparisons between otherwise similar communities: if, for example, left-handedness is relatively common in some communities but is rare in others, that is a sign that left-handedness might be prohibited, even if one never observes it being punished. Together, evidence of negative social maintenance and comparisons across communities can enable us to detect normative prohibitions even in cases where these prohibitions are not explicitly avowed.
A complicating factor here is that how and when we punish others for norm violations is often shaped by other norms, values, and institutions. In practice, the negative social maintenance practice for one normative regularity may depend upon a whole network of other norms regulating whether or not punishment is permissible and who is permitted to carry it out.
Gossip can also function as a vector for the acquisition of social norms: negative gossip about a behavior can often serve as evidence that it is normatively prohibited (Westra 2021).
This view is analogous to Pinker and Jackendoff’s (2005) claim that the human language faculty is a complex system that evolved piecemeal but nevertheless has a single adaptive function (communication).
Of course, one need not accept Dennett’s position on the nature of the propositional attitudes in order to think of social norms as real patterns in this sense.
We are grateful to two anonymous reviewers from this journal, Jonathan Birch, Laura Danón, Simon Fitzpatrick, Cecilia Heyes, Joseph Jebari, William O’Shea, Stephen Stich, Jordan Theriault, and especially Daniel Kelly for their detailed comments on earlier drafts of this paper. We are also grateful to audiences at the Normative Animals conference, the 2022 meeting of the Southern Society for Philosophy and Psychology, the ASENT Research Group at the London School of Economics, the Department of History and Philosophy of Science at the University of Cambridge, the Situated Cognition Research Group at Bochum University, the Department of Philosophy and Religious Studies at Peking University, and to the participants of the Evolution of Normativity Workshop.
References
Abrams D, Bown N, Marques JM, Henson M (2000) Pro-norm and anti-norm deviance within and between groups. J Pers Soc Psychol 78:906–912. https://doi.org/10.1037/0022-3514.78.5.906
Andrews K (2020) Naïve Normativity: The Social Foundation of Moral Cognition. J Am Philos Assoc 6:36–56. https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2019.30
Andrews K (2012) Do apes read minds?: Toward a new folk psychology. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA
Andrews K, Spaulding S, Westra E (2020) Introduction to Folk Psychology: Pluralistic Approaches. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02837-3
Apperly I, Butterfill SA (2009) Do humans have two systems to track beliefs and belief-like states? Psychol Rev 116:953–970. https://doi.org/10.1037/a0016923
Barrett HC, Bolyanatz A, Crittenden AN et al (2016) Small-scale societies exhibit fundamental variation in the role of intentions in moral judgment. Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A 113:4688–4693. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1522070113
Batson CD, Dyck J, Brandt J et al (1988) Five studies testing two new egoistic alternatives to the empathy-altruism hypothesis. J Personal Soc Psychol 55:52–77
Baumard N, André JB, Sperber D (2013) A mutualistic approach to morality: The evolution of fairness by partner choice. Behav Brain Sci 36:59–78. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X11002202
Bedau HA, Kelly E (2019) Punishment. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Winter 201
Bègue L, Beauvois J-L, Courbet D et al (2015) Personality Predicts Obedience in a Milgram Paradigm. J Pers 83:299–306. https://doi.org/10.1111/JOPY.12104
Bekoff M, Pierce J (2009) Wild justice: The moral lives of animals. University of Chicago Press
Bicchieri C (2006) The Grammar of Society. Cambridge University Press, New York
Bicchieri C (2017) Norms in the Wild: How to Diagnose, Measure, and Change Social Norms. Oxford University Press, New York
Bicchieri C, McNally P (2018) Shrieking Sirens: Schemata, scripts, and social norms. How change occurs
Birch J (2020) Toolmaking and the Origin of Normative Cognition. Biol Philos 1–47. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-020-09777-9
Boyd R, Richerson PJ (1992) Punishment allows the evolution of cooperation (or anything else) in sizable groups. Ethol Sociobiol 13:171–195. https://doi.org/10.1016/0162-3095(92)90032-Y
Braithwaite J (2002) Restorative justice & responsive regulation. Oxford University press on demand
Brosnan SF, De Waal FBM (2003) Monkeys reject unequal pay. Nature 425:297–299. https://doi.org/10.1038/nature01963
Carlsmith KM (2006) The roles of retribution and utility in determining punishment. J Exp Soc Psychol 42:437–451. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jesp.2005.06.007
Chester DS, DeWall CN (2016) The pleasure of revenge: Retaliatory aggression arises from a neural imbalance toward reward. Soc Cogn Affect Neurosci 11:1173–1182. https://doi.org/10.1093/scan/nsv082
Chudek M, Heller S, Birch S, Henrich J (2012) Prestige-biased cultural learning: bystander’s differential attention to potential models influences children’s learning. Evol Hum Behav 33:46–56. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2011.05.005
Chudek M, Henrich J (2011) Culture-gene coevolution, norm-psychology and the emergence of human prosociality. Trends Cogn Sci 15:218–226. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2011.03.003
Cialdini RB, Kallgren CA, Reno RR (1991) A focus theory of normative conduct: A theoretical refinement and reevaluation of the role of norms in human behavior. Advances in experimental social psychology. Elsevier, pp 201–234
Cialdini RB, Reno RR, Kallgren CA (1990) A focus theory of normative conduct: Recycling the concept of norms to reduce littering in public places. J Pers Soc Psychol 58:1015
Clark CJ, Baumeister RF, Ditto PH (2017) Making punishment palatable: Belief in free will alleviates punitive distress. Conscious Cogn 51:193–211
Clarke S, Beck J (2021) The Number Sense Represents (Rational) Numbers.Behav Brain Sci1–57
Colombo M (2014) Two neurocomputational building blocks of social norm compliance. Biol Philos 29:71–88. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-013-9385-z
Crockett MJ, Özdemir Y, Fehr E (2014) The value of vengeance and the demand for deterrence. J Exp Psychol Gen 143:2279–2286. https://doi.org/10.1037/xge0000018
Cummins R (2000) How does it work?“ versus” what are the laws?“: Two conceptions of psychological explanation. In: Keil FC, Wilson RA (eds) Explanation and cognition. MIT press, Cambridge, MA, pp 117–144
Curry OS, Jones Chesters M, Van Lissa CJ (2019) Mapping morality with a compass: Testing the theory of ‘morality-as-cooperation’ with a new questionnaire. J Res Pers 78:106–124. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jrp.2018.10.008
Curtin CM, Barrett HC, Bolyanatz A et al (2020) Kinship intensity and the use of mental states in moral judgment across societies. Evol Hum Behav 1–15. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2020.07.002
Danón L (2019) Animal normativity. Phenomenol Mind 17:176–187. https://doi.org/10.13128/pam-8035
de Waal FBM (2008) Putting the Altruism Back into Altruism: The Evolution of Empathy. Annu Rev Psychol 59:279–300. https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev.psych.59.103006.093625
Dennett DC (1991) Real patterns. J Philos Philos 88:27–51
DeYoung CG, Peterson JB, Higgins DM (2002) Higher-order factors of the Big Five predict conformity: Are there neuroses of health? Pers Individ Dif 33:533–552. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0191-8869(01)00171-4
Dunbar RIM (2004) Gossip in evolutionary perspective. Rev Gen Psychol 8:100–110. https://doi.org/10.1037/1089-2680.8.2.100
Dwyer S, Huebner B, Hauser MD (2010) The linguistic analogy: Motivations, results, and speculations. Top Cogn Sci 2:486–510. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1756-8765.2009.01064.x
Fehr E, Fischbacher U (2004) Third-party punishment and social norms. Evol Hum Behav 25:63–87. https://doi.org/10.1016/S1090-5138(04)00005-4
Feinberg M, Willer R, Schultz M (2014) Gossip and Ostracism Promote Cooperation in Groups. Psychol Sci 25:656–664. https://doi.org/10.1177/0956797613510184
Feinberg M, Willer R, Stellar J, Keltner D (2012) The virtues of gossip: Reputational information sharing as prosocial behavior. J Pers Soc Psychol 102:1015–1030. https://doi.org/10.1037/a0026650
Fiebich A, Coltheart M (2015) Various Ways to Understand Other Minds: Towards a Pluralistic Approach to the Explanation of Social Understanding. Mind Lang 30:235–258. https://doi.org/10.1111/mila.12079
Fitzpatrick S (2020) Chimpanzee normativity: evidence and objections. Biol Philos 35:1–28. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-020-09763-1
Funk F, McGeer V, Gollwitzer M (2014) Get the Message: Punishment Is Satisfying If the Transgressor Responds to Its Communicative Intent. Personal Soc Psychol Bull 40:986–997. https://doi.org/10.1177/0146167214533130
Gelfand MJ, Jackson JC (2016) From one mind to many: The emerging science of cultural norms. Curr Opin Psychol 8:175–181. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.copsyc.2015.11.002
Gelfand MJ, Raver JL, Nishii L et al (2011) Differences between tight and loose cultures: A 33-nation study. Sci (80-) 332:1100–1104. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1197754
Gintis H, Smith E, Bowles S (2001) Costly Signaling and Cooperation. J Theor Biol 213:1–29
Graham J, Haidt J, Nosek BA (2009) Liberals and Conservatives Rely on Different Sets of Moral Foundations. J Pers Soc Psychol 96:1029–1046. https://doi.org/10.1037/a0015141
Gray K, Waytz A, Young L (2012) The moral dyad: A fundamental template unifying moral judgment. Psychol Inq 23:206–215
Greene JD (2015) The rise of moral cognition. Cognition 135:39–42. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2014.11.018
Greene JD, Sommerville RB, Nystrom LE et al (2001) An fMRI investigation of emotional engagement in moral judgment. Sci (80-) 293:2105–2108
Haidt J (2001) The emotional dog and its rational tail: a social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychol Rev 108:814
Haidt J, Koller SH, Dias MG (1993) Affect, culture, and morality, or is it wrong to eat your dog? J Pers Soc Psychol 65:613
Hamlin JK, Tan E (2020) The emergence of moral responses and sensitivity. In: Jensen LA (ed) The Oxford Handbook of Moral Development: An Interdisciplinary Perspective. Oxford University Press Oxford, UK, Oxford, p 267
Heintz C (2018) Cultural Attraction Theory. Int Encycl Anthropol 1–10. https://doi.org/10.1002/9781118924396.wbiea2311
Henrich J (2020) The weirdest people in the world: How the west became psychologically peculiar and particularly prosperous. Farrar, Straus and Giroux
Henrich J (2017) The secret of our success: how culture is driving human evolution, domesticating our species, and making us smarter. Princeton University Press
Ho MK, MacGlashan J, Littman ML, Cushman F (2017) Social is special: A normative framework for teaching with and learning from evaluative feedback. Cognition 167:91–106. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2017.03.006
Hofmann W, Brandt MJ, Wisneski DC et al (2018) Moral Punishment in Everyday Life. Personal Soc Psychol Bull 44:1697–1711. https://doi.org/10.1177/0146167218775075
Hogg MA, Abrams D, Brewer MB (2017) Social identity: The role of self in group processes and intergroup relations. Gr Process Intergr Relations 20:570–581. https://doi.org/10.1177/1368430217690909
Hrdy SB (2011) Mothers and others. Harvard University Press
Jebari J (2018) Empirical moral rationalism and the social constitution of normativity. Philos Stud. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-018-1134-3
Jensen NH, Petersen MB, Høgh-Olesen H, Ejstrup M (2015) Testing Theories about Ethnic Markers: Ingroup Accent Facilitates Coordination, Not Cooperation. Hum Nat 26:210–234. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12110-015-9229-4
Jordan JJ, Hoffman M, Bloom P, Rand DG (2016) Third-party punishment as a costly signal of trustworthiness. Nature 530:473–476. https://doi.org/10.1038/nature16981
Jordan JJ, Rand DG (2020) Signaling When No One Is Watching: A Reputation Heuristics Account of Outrage and Punishment In One-Shot Anonymous Interactions. J Pers Soc Psychol 118:57–88. https://doi.org/10.1037/pspi0000186.supp
Kelly D (2020) Internalized norms and intrinsic motivations: Are normative motivations psychologically primitive?Emot Res36–45
Kelly D (2022) Two Ways To Adopt a Norm: The (Moral?) Psychology of Internalization and Avowal. In: Vargas M, Doris J (eds) Oxford Handbook of Moral Psychology. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 285–309
Kelly D, Davis T (2018) Social norms and human normative psychology. Soc Philos Policy 35:54–76. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0265052518000122
Kelly D, Setman S (2020) The Psychology of Normative Cognition. In: Zalta EN (ed) Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Spring 202. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, pp 1–28
Kelly D, Stich S, Haley KJ et al (2007) Harm, affect, and the moral/conventional distinction. Mind Lang 22:117–131. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0017.2007.00302.x
Kenward B, Karlsson M, Persson J (2011) Over-imitation is better explained by norm learning than by distorted causal learning. Proceedings Biol Sci 278:1239–46. https://doi.org/10.1098/rspb.2010.1399
Keupp S, Behne T, Rakoczy H (2013) Why do children overimitate? Normativity is crucial. J Exp Child Psychol 116:392–406. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jecp.2013.07.002
Kneer M, Machery E (2019) No luck for moral luck. Cognition 182:331–348. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2018.09.003
Korsgaard C (2006) Morality and the distinctiveness of human action. In: Ober J, Macedo S, de Waal FBM (eds) Primates and philosophers: How morality evolved. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ, pp 98–119
Kosloff S, Irish S, Perreault L et al (2017) Assessing relationships between conformity and meta-traits in an Asch-like paradigm. 12:90–100. https://doi.org/10.1080/15534510.2017.1371639. https://doi.org/101080/1553451020171371639
Kumar V (2016) The Empirical Identity of Moral Judgment. Philos Q 66:783–804. https://doi.org/10.1093/pq/pqw019
Lewis D (1969) Convention: A philosophical study. John Wiley & Sons, Oxford
Maibom HL (2005) Moral unreason: The case of psychopathy. Mind Lang 20:237–257. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.0268-1064.2005.00284.x
Marques J, Abrams D, Paez D, Martinez-Taboada C (1998) The role of categorization and in-group norms in judgments of groups and their members. J Pers Soc Psychol 75:976–988. https://doi.org/10.1037/0022-3514.75.4.976
Marr D (2010) Vision: A computational investigation into the human representation and processing of visual information. MIT press, cambride
McCullough ME, Kurzban R, Tabak BA (2013) Cognitive systems for revenge and forgiveness. Behav Brain Sci 36:1–15. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X11002160
McElreath R, Boyd R, Richerson PJ (2003) Shared norms and the evolution of ethnic markers. Curr Anthropol 44:122–129. https://doi.org/10.1086/345689
McGeer V (2007) The regulative dimension of folk psychology. In: Hutto DD, Ratcliffe M (eds) Folk psychology re-assessed. Springer, pp 137–156
McNamara RA, Willard AK, Norenzayan A, Henrich J (2019) Weighing outcome vs. intent across societies: How cultural models of mind shape moral reasoning. Cognition 182:95–108. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2018.09.008
Mikhail J (2011) Elements of moral cognition: Rawls’ linguistic analogy and the cognitive science of moral and legal judgment. Cambridge University Press
Mikhalevich I, Powell R (2020) Minds without spines: Evolutionarily inclusive animal ethics. Anim Sentience 5:1
Miller CB (2014) Character and moral psychology. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Nichols S (2004) Sentimental rules: On the natural foundations of moral judgment. Oxford University Press
O’Neill E (2017) Kinds of norms. Philos Compass 12:1–15. https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12416
Petersen MB, Sell A, Tooby J, Cosmides L (2012) To punish or repair? Evolutionary psychology and lay intuitions about modern criminal justice. Evol Hum Behav 33:682–695. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2012.05.003
Pinker S, Jackendoff R (2005) The faculty of language: What’s special about it? Cognition 95:201–236. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2004.08.004
Prinz J (2007) The emotional construction of morals. Oxford University Press
Railton P (2006) Normative Guidance. Oxford Stud Metaethics, pp 3–33
Rakoczy, H., Warneken, F., & Tomasello, M. (2008). The sources of normativity: young children's awareness of the normative structure of games. Developmental psychology, 44(3), 875.
Reber R, Norenzayan A (2012) The Shared Fluency Theory of Social Cohesiveness. In: Proust J, Fortier M (eds) Metacognitive Diversity. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Richerson PJ, Boyd R (2005) Not by genes alone: How culture transformed human evolution. University of Chicago press
Sarin A, Ho MK, Martin JW, Cushman FA (2021) Punishment is Organized around Principles of Communicative Inference. Cognition 208:104544. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2020.104544
Schlingloff L, Moore R (2017) Do chimpanzees conform to social norms? In: Andrews K, Beck J (eds) Routledge handbook of philosophy of animals minds. Routledge, New York
Schmidt M, Butler L, Heinz J, Tomasello M (2016a) Young Children See a Single Action and Infer a Social Norm: Promiscuous Normativity in 3-Year-Olds. Psychol Sci 27:1360–1370. https://doi.org/10.1177/0956797616661182
Schmidt MFH, Butler LP, Heinz J, Tomasello M (2016b) Young Children See a Single Action and Infer a Social Norm : Promiscuous Normativity in 3-Year-Olds. https://doi.org/10.1177/0956797616661182
Schmidt MFH, Rakoczy H (2019) On the Uniqueness of Human Normative Attitudes. In: Roughley N, Bayertz K (eds) The Normative Animal? On the Anthropological Significance of Social, Moral, and Linguistic Norms. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 121–136
Scott-Phillips T, Blancke S, Heintz C (2018) Four misunderstandings about cultural attraction. Evol Anthropol 27:162–173. https://doi.org/10.1002/evan.21716
Shweder RA, Mahapatra M, Miller JG (1987) Culture and moral development. In: Kagan J, Lamb S (eds) The emergence of morality in young children. University of Chicago press, Chicago, pp 1–83
Simpson SJ, Raubenheimer D (2012) The Nature of Nutrition: A Unifying Framework from Animal Adaptation to Human Obesity. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ
Sinnott-Armstrong W, Wheatley T (2014) Are moral judgments unified? Philos Psychol 27:451–474. https://doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2012.736075
Spaulding S (2018) How We Understand Others: Philosophy and Social Cognition. Routledge, London
Sperber D (1996) Explaining culture: A naturalistic approach. Wiley-Blackwell, Oxford
Sripada C (2020) The atoms of self-control. Noûs
Sripada C, Stich SP (2006) A Framework for the Psychology of Norms. In: Carruthers P, Laurence S, Stich S (eds) The Innate Mind Volume 3: Culture and Cognition. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 280–301
Sterelny K (2021) The Pleistocene Social Contract. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Stich SP (2006) Is morality an elegant machine or a kludge? J Cogn Cult 6:181–189. https://doi.org/10.1163/156853706776931349
Stich SP (2019) The quest for the boundaries of morality. In: Zimmerman A, Jones K, Timmons M (eds) The Routledge Handbook of Moral Epistemology. Routledge, New York, pp 15–37
Strohminger N, Nichols S (2014) The essential moral self. Cognition 131:159–171. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2013.12.005
Számadó S, Balliet D, Giardini F et al (2021) The language of cooperation: reputation and honest signalling. Philos Trans R Soc B Biol Sci 376. https://doi.org/10.1098/RSTB.2020.0286
Tajfel H (1981) Human groups and social categories: Studies in social psychology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK
Theriault JE, Young L, Barrett LF (2021) The sense of should: A biologically-based framework for modeling social pressure. Phys Life Rev 36:100–136. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.plrev.2020.01.004
Tomasello M (2019) The Moral Psychology of Obligation. Behav Brain Sci 43:1–58. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X19001742
Tomasello M (2020) The role of roles in uniquely human cognition and sociality. J Theory Soc Behav 50:2–19. https://doi.org/10.1111/jtsb.12223
Tomasello M (2012) Two Key Steps in the Evolution of Human Cooperation: The Interdependence Hypothesis. Curr. Anthropol
Turiel E (1983) The development of social knowledge: Morality and convention. Cambridge University Press
Veissière SPL, Constant A, Ramstead MJD et al (2019) Thinking Through Other Minds: A Variational Approach to Cognition and Culture. Behav Brain Sci. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X19001213
von Rohr CR, Burkart JM, van Schaik CP (2011) Evolutionary precursors of social norms in chimpanzees: A new approach. Biol Philos 26:1–30. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-010-9240-4
Warneken F, Tomasello M (2007) Helping and Cooperation at 14 Months of Age. Infancy 11:271–294
Westra E (2021) Folk personality psychology: mindreading and mindshaping in trait attribution. Synthese 198:8213–8232. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02566-7
Wiessner P, Pupu N (2012) Toward peace: Foreign arms and indigenous institutions in a Papua New Guinea society. Sci (80-) 337:1651–1654
Wu J, Balliet D, Van Lange PAM (2016) Reputation, Gossip, and Human Cooperation. Soc Personal Psychol Compass 10:350–364. https://doi.org/10.1111/spc3.12255
Young L, Dungan J (2012) Where in the brain is morality? Everywhere and maybe nowhere. Soc Neurosci 7:1–10. https://doi.org/10.1080/17470919.2011.569146
Zawidzki TW (2013) Mindshaping: A New Framework for Understanding Human Social Cognition. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA
Zion JW (1998) The Dynamics of Navajo Peacemaking. J Contemp Crim Justice 14:58–74
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Additional information
Publisher’s Note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Rights and permissions
Springer Nature or its licensor holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.
About this article
Cite this article
Westra, E., Andrews, K. A pluralistic framework for the psychology of norms. Biol Philos 37, 40 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-022-09871-0
Received:
Revised:
Accepted:
Published:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-022-09871-0