Biology & Philosophy

, Volume 30, Issue 1, pp 19–37 | Cite as

Using causal models to integrate proximate and ultimate causation

Article

Abstract

Ernst Mayr’s classical work on the nature of causation in biology has had a huge influence on biologists as well as philosophers. Although his distinction between proximate and ultimate causation recently came under criticism from those who emphasize the role of development in evolutionary processes, the formal relationship between these two notions remains elusive. Using causal graph theory, this paper offers a unified framework to systematically translate a given “proximate” causal structure into an “ultimate” evolutionary response, and illustrates evolutionary implications of various kinds of causal mechanisms including epigenetic inheritance, maternal effects, and niche construction. These results not only reveal the essential interplay between proximate and ultimate causation in the study of evolution, but also provide a formal method to evaluate or discover non-standard or yet unknown evolutionary phenomena.

Keywords

Proximate and ultimate causation Extended synthesis  Epigenetic inheritance Niche construction Causal models Price equation 

References

  1. Amundson R (2005) The changing role of the embryo in evolutionary thought: roots of evo-devo. Cambridge University Press, New YorkCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Beatty J (1994) The proximate/ultimate distinction in the multiple careers of Ernst Mayr. Biol Philos 9(3):333–356CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Calcott B (2013) Why how and why arent enough: more problems with Mayrs proximate–ultimate distinction. Biol Philos 28(5):767–780Google Scholar
  4. Cheverud JM (1984) Evolution by kin selection: a quantitative genetic model illustrated by maternal performance in mice. Evolution 38(4):766–777CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Coyne JA, Barton NH, Turelli M (1997) Perspective: a critique of Sewall Wright’s shifting balance theory of evolution. Evolution 51(3):643–671CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Coyne JA, Barton NH, Turelli M (2000) Is Wright’s shifting balance process important in evolution? Evolution 54(1):306–317CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Feldman MW, Cavalli-Sforza L (1976) Cultural and biological evolutionary processes, selection for a trait under complex transmission. Theor Popul Biol 9(2):238–259CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Glymour B (2011) Modeling environments: interactive causation and adaptations to environmental conditions. Philos Sci 78:448–471CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Goodnight CJ, Wade MJ (2000) The ongoing synthesis: a reply to Coyne, Barton, and Turelli. Evolution 54(1):317–324CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Helanterä H, Uller T (2010) The Price equation and extended inheritance. Philos Theory Biol 2:e101Google Scholar
  11. Jablonka E, Lamb MJM (2005) Evolution in four dimensions: genetic, epigenetic, behavioral, and symbolic variation in the history of life. The MIT Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  12. Kirkpatrick M, Lande R (1989) The evolution of maternal characters. Evolution 43(3):485–503CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Laland K, Odling-Smee J, Hoppitt W, Uller T (2012) More on how and why: cause and effect in biology revisited. Biol Philos 28(5):719–745Google Scholar
  14. Laland K, Sterelny K, Odling-Smee J (2011) Cause and effect in biology revisited: is Mayr’s proximate–ultimate dichotomy still useful? Science 334:1512–1516CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Laland KN, Odling-Smee FJ, Feldman MW (1996) The evolutionary consequences of niche construction: a theoretical investigation using twolocus theory. J Evolut Biol 9:293–316CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Laland KN, Odling-Smee FJ, Feldman MW (1999) Evolutionary consequences of niche construction and their implications for ecology. Proc Natl Acad Sci 96:10242–10247CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Laland KN, Odling-Smee J, Feldman MW (2000) Niche construction, biological evolution, and cultural change. Behav Brain Sci 23(1):131–146 discussion 146–175CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Lewontin RC (1983) Gene, organism, and environment. In: Bendall DS (ed) Evolution from molecules to men. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 273–285Google Scholar
  19. Lush JL (1937) Animal breeding plans. Collegiate Press Inc, AmesGoogle Scholar
  20. Maynard Smith J (1982) Evolution and the theory of games. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Mayr E (1961) Cause and effect in biology. Science 134:1501–1506CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. McAdam AG, Boutin S (2004) Maternal effects and the response to selection in red squirrels. Proc R Soc B Biol Sci 271(1534):75–79CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. McCullagh P (1987) Tensor methods in statistics. Chapman and Hall/CRC, Boca RatonGoogle Scholar
  24. Odling-Smee F, Laland K, Feldman M (1996) Niche construction. Am Nat 147(4):641–648CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Okasha S (2006) Evolution and the levels of selection. Oxford University Press, OxfordCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Otsuka J (forthcoming) Causal Foundations of Evolutionary Genetics. Br J Philos SciGoogle Scholar
  27. Pearl J (2000) Causality: models, reasoning, and inference. Cambridge University Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  28. Pigliucci M (2001) Phenotypic plasticity: beyond nature and nurture. The Johns Hopkins University Press, BaltimoreGoogle Scholar
  29. Pigliucci M (2007) Do we need an extended evolutionary synthesis? Evolution 61(12):2743–2749CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Pigliucci M, Muller GB (2010) Evolution: the extended synthesis. MIT Press, CambridgeCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Price GR (1970) Selection and covariance. Nature 227:520–521CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Robertson A (1966) A mathematical model of the culling process in dairy cattle. Anim Prod 8(1):95–108CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Shipley B (2000) Cause and correlation in biology: a user’s guide to path analysis, structural equations and causal inference. Cambridge University Press, New YorkCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Spirtes P, Glymour C, Scheines R (2000) Causation, prediction, and search, 2nd edn. The MIT Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  35. Sterelny K (2013) Cooperation in a complex world: the role of proximate factors in ultimate explanations. Biol Theory 7(4):358–367CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Tal O, Kisdi E, Jablonka E (2010) Epigenetic contribution to covariance between relatives. Genetics 184(4):1037–1050CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Thierry B (2005) Integrating proximate and ultimate causation: just one more go! Curr Sci 89(7):1181–1183Google Scholar
  38. Valente BD, Rosa GJM, De los Campos G, Gianola D, Silva MA (2010) Searching for recursive causal structures in multivariate quantitative genetics mixed models. Genetics 185:633–644CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Valente BD, Rosa GJM, Silva MA, Teixeira RB, Torres RA (2011) Searching for phenotypic causal networks involving complex traits: an application to European quail. Genet Sel Evol 43:37Google Scholar
  40. van Fraassen BC (1980) The scientific image. Oxford University Press, OxfordCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Wade MJ (1992) Sewall Wright: gene interaction and the shifting balance theory. In: Futuyma DJ, Antonovics J (eds) Oxford surveys in evolutionary biology, vol 8. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 35–62Google Scholar
  42. Wade MJ, Goodnight CJ (1998) Perspective: the theories of Fisher and Wright in the context of metapopulations: when nature does many small experiments. Evolution 52(6):1537–1553CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Wade MJ, Kalisz S (1990) The causes of natural selection. Evolution 44(8):1947–1955CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. West-Eberhard MJ (2003) Developmental plasticity and evolution. Oxford University Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  45. Wright S (1921) Correlation and causation. J Agric Res 20:557–585Google Scholar
  46. Wright S (1930) The genetical theory of natural selection. J Hered 21(8):349–356Google Scholar
  47. Wright S (1934) The method of path coefficients. Ann Math Stat 5:161–215CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2014

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of California, DavisDavisUSA

Personalised recommendations