Biology & Philosophy

, Volume 29, Issue 5, pp 675–697 | Cite as

Fighting the good cause: meaning, purpose, difference, and choice

Research

Abstract

Concepts of cause, choice, and information are closely related. A cause is a choice that can be held responsible. It is a difference that makes a difference. Information about past causes and their effects is a valuable commodity because it can be used to guide future choices. Information about criteria of choice is generated by choosing a subset from an ensemble for ‘reasons’ and has meaning for an interpreter when it is used to achieve an end. Natural selection evolves interpreters with ends. Surviving genes embody a textual record of past choices that had favorable outcomes. Consultation of these archives guides current choices. Purposive choice is well-informed difference making.

Keywords

Final causes Formal causes Information Teleology Recursion Selection Choice Difference Text Interpretation 

References

  1. Adami C (2002) What is complexity? BioEssays 24:1085–1094CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Adami C, Ofria C, Collier TC (2000) Evolution of biological complexity. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 97:4463–4468CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Aristotle (1984) The complete works of Aristotle. Princeton University Press, PrincetonGoogle Scholar
  4. Atkins PW (1994) The second law. W. H. Freeman, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  5. Ayala FJ (1970) Teleological explanations in evolutionary biology. Phil Sci 37:1–15CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Bacon F (1596) Maxims of the lawGoogle Scholar
  7. Bacon F (1885) The advancement of learning. In Wright WA (ed) Clarendon Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  8. Bateson G (1972) Steps to an ecology of mind. University of Chicago Press, ChicagoGoogle Scholar
  9. Bergstrom CT, Rosvall M (2011) The transmission sense of information. Biol Phil 26:159–176CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Capurro R, Hjørland B (2003) The concept of information. Annu Rev Inform Sci Tech 37:343–411CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Colgate SA, Ziock H (2011) A definition of information, the arrow of information, and its relationship to life. Complexity 16:54–62CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Dawkins R (1976) The selfish gene. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  13. Dawkins R (1982) The extended phenotype. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  14. Delbrück M (1949) A physicist looks at biology. Trans Connecticut Acad Arts Sci 38:173–190Google Scholar
  15. Delbrück M (1971) Aristotle-totle-totle. In: Monod J, Borek E (eds) Of microbes and life. Columbia University Press, New York, pp 50–55Google Scholar
  16. Dennett DC (1995) Darwin’s dangerous idea. Simon and Schuster, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  17. Finnegan DJ (2012) Retrotransposons. Curr Biol 22:R432–R437CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Fisher RA (1934) Indeterminism and natural selection. Phil Sci 1:99–117CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Fisher RA (1941) Average excess and average effect of a gene substitution. Ann Eugen 11:53–63CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Frank SA (2009) Natural selection maximizes fisher information. J Evol Biol 22:231–244CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Frank SA (2012) Natural selection. III. Selection versus transmission and the levels of selection. J Evol Biol 25:227–243CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Frede M (1980) The original notion of cause. In: Schofield M, Burnyeat M, Barnes J (eds) Doubt and dogmatism. Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp 217–249Google Scholar
  23. Gliddon CJ, Gouyon PH (1989) The units of selection. Trends Ecol Evol 4:204–208CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Godfrey-Smith P (2009) Darwinian populations and natural selection. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  25. Gouyon PH, Gliddon C (1988) The genetics of information and the evolution of avatars. In: de Jong G (ed) Population genetics and evolution. Springer, Berlin, pp 119–123CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Gregory RL (1981) Mind in science. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  27. Grene M (1972) Aristotle and modern biology. J Hist Ideas 33:395–424CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Griffiths PE (2013) Lehrman’s dictum: information and explanation in developmental biology. Dev Psychobiol 55:22–32CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Griffiths PE, Neumann-Held EM (1999) The many faces of the gene. Bioscience 49:656–662CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Haig D (1992) Genomic imprinting and the theory of parent-offspring conflict. Semin Dev Biol 3:153–160Google Scholar
  31. Haig D (1997) The social gene. In: Krebs JR, Davies NB (eds) Behavioural ecology, 4th edn. Blackwell Scientific, Oxford, pp 284–304Google Scholar
  32. Haig D (2011a) Sympathy with Adam Smith and reflexions on self. J Econ Org Behav 77:4–13CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Haig D (2011b) Does heritability hide in epistasis between linked SNPs? Eur J Hum Genet 19:123CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Haig D (2012a) The strategic gene. Biol Phil 27:461–479CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Haig D (2012b) Retroviruses and the placenta. Curr Biol 22:R609–R613CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Haig D (2013a) Genomic vagabonds: endogenous retroviruses and placental evolution. BioEssays 35:845–846Google Scholar
  37. Haig D (2013b) Proximate and ultimate causes: How come? and What for? Biol Phil 28:781–786CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Haig D, Henikoff S (2004) Deciphering the genomic palimpsest. Curr Opin Genet Dev 14:599–602Google Scholar
  39. Haig D, Trivers R (1995) The evolution of parental imprinting: a review of hypotheses. In: Ohlsson R, Hall K, Ritzen M (eds) Genomic imprinting: causes and consequences. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 17–28Google Scholar
  40. Hamilton WD (1975) Gamblers since life began: barnacles, aphids, elms. Q Rev Biol 50:175–180CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Hanchard N, Elzein A, Trafford C, Rockett K, Pinder M et al (2007) Classical sickle beta-globin haplotypes exhibit a high degree of long-range haplotype similarity in African and Afro-Caribbean populations. BMC Genet 8:52CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Hitchcock C (2007) Prevention, preemption, and the principle of sufficient reason. Phil Rev 116:495–532CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Hofstadter DR (1979) Gödel, Escher, Bach. Basic Books, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  44. Hofstadter DR (2007) I am a strange loop. Basic Books, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  45. Kant I (2000) Critique of the power of judgment (trans: Guyer P, Matthews E). Cambridge University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  46. Laland KN, Odling-Smee J, Hoppitt W, Uller T (2013a) More of how and why: cause and effect in biology revisited. Biol Phil 28:719–745CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Laland KN, Odling-Smee J, Hoppitt W, Uller T (2013b) More of how and why: a response to commentaries. Biol Phil 28:793–810CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Lewis D (2000) Causation as influence. J Phil 97:182–197CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. Lewontin RC (1974) The analysis of variance and the analysis of causes. Am J Hum Genet 26:400–411Google Scholar
  50. Lewontin RC (2000) Foreword. In: Oyama S (ed) The ontogeny of information, 2nd edn. Duke University Press, Durham, NC, pp vii–xvGoogle Scholar
  51. Mellor J (2005) The dynamics of chromatin remodeling at promoters. Mol Cell 19:147–157CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. Moffatt B (2011) Conflations in the causal account of information undermine the parity thesis. Phil Sci 78:284–302CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Nash O (1936) The bad parents’ book of verse. Simon and Schuster, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  54. Neher RA, Shraiman BI (2009) Competition between recombination and epistasis can cause a transition from allele to genotype selection. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 106:6866–6871CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  55. Neher RA, Kessinger TA, Shraiman BI (2013) Coalescence and genetic diversity in sexual populations under selection. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 110:15836–15841CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  56. Okasha S (2012) Social justice, genomic justice and the veil of ignorance: Harsanyi meets Mendel. Econ Phil 28:43–71CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  57. Oyama S (2000) The ontogeny of information. Developmental systems and evolution, 2nd edn. Duke University Press, DurhamGoogle Scholar
  58. Pearson L (1952) Prophasis and aitia. Trans Proc Am Philol Assoc 83:203–223Google Scholar
  59. Peirce CS (1877) Illustrations of the logic of science. First paper. The fixation of belief. Pop Sci Mon 12:1–15Google Scholar
  60. Peirce CS (1905) What pragmaticism is. Monist 15:161–181. (title corrected)Google Scholar
  61. Pittendrigh CS (1961) On temporal organization in living systems. Harvey Lect 56:93–125Google Scholar
  62. Pittendrigh CS (1993) Temporal organization: reflections of a Darwinian clock-watcher. Annu Rev Physiol 55:17–54CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  63. Price GR (1995) The nature of selection. J Theor Biol 175:389–396CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  64. Ridley M (2000) Mendel’s demon. Weidenfeld and Nicholson, LondonGoogle Scholar
  65. Russell B (1913) On the notion of cause. Proc Aristot Soc 13:1–26Google Scholar
  66. Sartorio C (2005) Causes as difference makers. Phil Stud 123:71–96CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  67. Shea N (2007) Representation in the genome and in other inheritance systems. Biol Phil 22:313–331CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  68. Sterne L (1767) The life and opinions of Tristram Shandy, gentlemanGoogle Scholar
  69. Tennyson A (1849) In memoriam. AHHGoogle Scholar
  70. Weismann A (1890) Prof. Weismann’s theory of heredity. Nature 41:317–323CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  71. Williams GC (1966) Adaptation and natural selection. Princeton University Press, PrincetonGoogle Scholar
  72. Williams GC (1992) Natural selection. Domains, levels, and challenges. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  73. Winnie JA (2000) Information and structure in molecular biology: comments on Maynard Smith. Phil Sci 67:517–526CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2014

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of Organismic and Evolutionary BiologyHarvard UniversityCambridgeUSA

Personalised recommendations