Biology & Philosophy

, Volume 28, Issue 6, pp 957–979 | Cite as

Pluralism in evolutionary controversies: styles and averaging strategies in hierarchical selection theories

  • Rasmus Grønfeldt Winther
  • Michael J. Wade
  • Christopher C. Dimond
Article

Abstract

Two controversies exist regarding the appropriate characterization of hierarchical and adaptive evolution in natural populations. In biology, there is the Wright–Fisher controversy over the relative roles of random genetic drift, natural selection, population structure, and interdemic selection in adaptive evolution begun by Sewall Wright and Ronald Aylmer Fisher. There is also the Units of Selection debate, spanning both the biological and the philosophical literature and including the impassioned group-selection debate. Why do these two discourses exist separately, and interact relatively little? We postulate that the reason for this schism can be found in the differing focus of each controversy, a deep difference itself determined by distinct general styles of scientific research guiding each discourse. That is, the Wright–Fisher debate focuses on adaptive process, and tends to be instructed by the mathematical modeling style, while the focus of the Units of Selection controversy is adaptive product, and is typically guided by the function style. The differences between the two discourses can be usefully tracked by examining their interpretations of two contested strategies for theorizing hierarchical selection: horizontal and vertical averaging.

Keywords

Hierarchical selection Sewall Wright R.A. Fisher Units of selection Levels of selection Styles of scientific research Models Adaptation Averaging strategies Averaging fallacy Group selection 

Supplementary material

10539_2013_9378_MOESM1_ESM.docx (21 kb)
Supplementary material 1 (DOCX 23 kb)

References

  1. Allen C, Bekoff M, Lauder G (eds) (1998) Nature’s purposes: analyses of function and design in biology. MIT Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  2. Ariew A, Cummins R, Perlman M (eds) (2002) Functions: new essays in the philosophy of psychology and biology. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  3. Bar-Yam Y (2000) Formalizing the gene centered view of evolution. Adv Complex Syst 2:277–281. Url:http://arxiv.org/abs/physics/0002016
  4. Borrello M (2003) Synthesis and selection: Wynne Edwards challenge to David Lack. J Hist Biol 36:531–566CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Borrello Mark (2010) Evolutionary restraints. The contentious history of group selection. University of Chicago Press, ChicagoCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Brandon RN (1982) The levels of selection. PSA 1982(1):315–323Google Scholar
  7. Brandon RN (1985) Adaptation explanations: are adaptations for the good of replicators or interactors? In: Depew DJ, Weber BH (eds) Evolution at a crossroads: the new biology and the new philosophy of science. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 81–96Google Scholar
  8. Brandon RN (1990) Adaptation and environment. Princeton University Press, PrincetonGoogle Scholar
  9. Bueno O, Colyvan M (2011) An inferential conception of the application of mathematics. Noûs 45(2):345–374CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Buller D (ed) (1999) Function, selection and design. SUNY Press, AlbanyGoogle Scholar
  11. Burian RM (1983) Adaptation. In: Grene M (ed) Dimensions of Darwinism. Themes and counterthemes in twentieth-century evolutionary theory. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 287–314Google Scholar
  12. Cassidy J (1978) Philosophical aspect of the group selection controversy. Philos Sci 45:575–594CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Coyne JA, Barton NH, Turelli M (1997) Perspective: a critique of Sewall Wright’s shifting balance theory of evolution. Evolution 51:643–671CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Coyne JA, Barton NH, Turelli M (2000) Is Wright’s shifting balance process important in evolution? Evolution 54:306–317Google Scholar
  15. Crombie AC (1994) Styles of scientific thinking in the European tradition. 3 vols. Duckworth, LondonGoogle Scholar
  16. Damuth J, Heisler IL (1988) Alternative formulation of multilevel selection. Biol Philos 3:407–430CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Dawkins R (1976) The selfish gene. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  18. Demuth J, Wade MJ (2007a) Population differentiation in the beetle, Tribolium castaneum. I. Genetic architecture. Evolution 61:494–509CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Demuth J, Wade MJ (2007b) Population differentiation in the beetle, Tribolium castaneum. II: Haldane’s Rule and incipient speciation. Evolution 61:694–699CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Elwick J (2007) Styles of reasoning in the British life sciences: shared assumptions, 1820–1858. Pickering & Chatto, LondonGoogle Scholar
  21. Feldman R, Warfield TA (2010) Disagreement. Oxford University Press, New YorkCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Fisher RA (1918) The correlation between relatives on the supposition of Mendelian inheritance. Trans R Soc Edinb 3:399–433Google Scholar
  23. Fisher RA (1937) The design of experiments. Oliver & Boyd, EdinburghGoogle Scholar
  24. Fisher RA (1941) Average excess and average effect of a gene substitution. Ann Eugen 11:53–63CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Fisher RA (1953) Population genetics. The Croonian lecture. Proc R Soc B 141:510–523CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Fisher RA (1958) The genetical theory of natural selection. Dover Publications, Inc., New York (2nd edition of 1930 Oxford University Press 1st edition)Google Scholar
  27. Frank SA, Slatkin M (1992) Fisher’s fundamental theorem of natural selection. Trends Ecol Evol 7(3):92–95CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Gavrilets S (1999) A dynamical theory of speciation on holey adaptive landscapes. Am Nat 154(1):1–22CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Goodnight CJ, Wade MJ (2000) The ongoing synthesis: a reply to Coyne, Barton, and Turelli. Evolution 54:317–324Google Scholar
  30. Gould SJ, Lewontin RC (1979) The spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian paradigm: a critique of the adaptationist programme. Proc R Soc Lond B 205:581–598CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Gould SJ, Vrba ES (1982) Exaptation—a missing term in the science of form. Paleobiology 8:4–15Google Scholar
  32. Hacking I (2002) Historical ontology. Harvard University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  33. Hacking I (2009) Scientific reason. National Taiwan University Press, TaipeiGoogle Scholar
  34. Hamilton A, Dimond CC (2012) Groups, individuals, and evolutionary restraints: the making of the contemporary debate over group selection. Biol Philos 27(2):299–312CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Hammerstein P (1996) Darwinian adaptation, population genetics and the streetcar theory of evolution. J Math Biol 34:511–532CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Hempel GC (1994) The logic of functional analysis (1959). Reprinted in Martin M, McIntyre LC. Readings in the philosophy of social science. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 349–375Google Scholar
  37. Hodge MJS (1992) Biology and philosophy (including ideology): a study of Fisher and Wright. In: Sarkar S (ed) The founders of evolutionary genetics. Kluwer, Dordrecht, pp 231–293CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Hughes RIG (1997) Models and representation. Philos Sci 64:S325–S336CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Johnson N (2008) Sewall Wright and the development of shifting balance theory. Nature Education 1(1). http://www.nature.com/scitable/topicpage/sewall-wright-and-the-development-of-shifting-30508
  40. Joseph G (1980) The many sciences and the one world. J Philos 77:773–791CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Keller L (1999) Levels of selection in evolution. Princeton University Press, PrincetonGoogle Scholar
  42. Kellert SH, Longino HE, Waters CK (eds) (2006) Scientific pluralism (Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science). University of Minnesota Press, MinneapolisGoogle Scholar
  43. Kerr B, Godfrey-Smith P (2002) Individualist and multi-level perspectives on selection in structured populations. Biol Philos 17:477–517CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Kitcher P (1993) Function and design. Midwest Stud Philos XVIII:379–397CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Krimbas CB (1984) On adaptation, Neo-Darwinian tautology, and population fitness. Evol Biol 17:1–57CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Kwa C (2011) Styles of knowing. A new history of science from ancient times to the present. University of Pittsburgh Press, PittsburghGoogle Scholar
  47. Lack D (1954) The natural regulation of animal numbers. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  48. Lack D (1966) Population studies of birds. Clarendon Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  49. Lewontin RC (1974) The genetic basis of evolutionary change. Columbia University Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  50. Lewontin RC, Cohen D (1969) On population growth in a randomly varying environment. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 62(4):1056–1060CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Lloyd EA (1988) The structure and confirmation of evolutionary theory. Greenwood Press, WestportGoogle Scholar
  52. Lloyd EA (2000a) Groups on groups. Biol Philos 15:389–401CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Lloyd EA (2000b) Units and levels of selection. An anatomy of the units of selection debates. In: Singh R, Krimbas C, Paul D, Beatty J (eds) Thinking about evolution: historical, philosophical and political perspectives. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 267–291Google Scholar
  54. Lloyd EA (2005a) Why the gene will not return. Philos Sci 72:287–310CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  55. Lloyd EA (2005b) Units and levels of selection. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2005 edition). Url:http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2005/entries/selection-units/
  56. Maynard Smith J, Szathmáry E (2009) The origins of life. From the birth of life to the origins of language. Oxford University Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  57. Mitchell S (2003) Biological complexity and integrative pluralism. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  58. Mitman G (1992) The state of nature ecology, community, and American social thought, 1900–1950. University of Chicago Press, ChicagoGoogle Scholar
  59. Morrison M (2000) Unifying scientific theories: physical concepts and mathematical structures. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  60. Morrison M (2006) Unification, explanation and explaining unity: the Fisher–Wright controversy. Br J Philos Sci 57:233–245CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  61. Okasha S (2004) The “averaging fallacy” and the levels of selection. Biol Philos 19:167–184CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  62. Okasha S (2007) Evolution and the levels of selection. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  63. Otto SP, Hastings IM (1998) Mutation and selection within an individual. Genetica 102(103):507–524CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  64. Pickstone JV (2001) Ways of knowing. A new history of science, technology and medicine. University of Chicago Press, ChicagoGoogle Scholar
  65. Plutynski A (2005) Parsimony and the Fisher–Wright debate. Biol Philos 20:697–713CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  66. Price GR (1970) Selection and covariance. Nature 227:520–521CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  67. Provine W (1986) Sewall Wright and evolutionary biology. University of Chicago Press, ChicagoGoogle Scholar
  68. Reichenbach H (1956) The direction of time. University of California Press, BerkeleyGoogle Scholar
  69. Schwartz J (2002) Population genetics and sociobiology. Conflicting views of evolution. Perspect Biol Med 45:224–240CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  70. Skipper RJ (2002) The persistence of the RA Fisher—Sewall Wright controversy. Biol Philos 17:341–367CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  71. Sober E (1984) Sets, species, and evolution: comments on Philip Kitcher’s “species”. Philos Sci 51:334–341CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  72. Sober E (1993) The nature of selection. Evolutionary theory in philosophical focus. University of Chicago Press, Chicago [First Published MIT Press, 1984]Google Scholar
  73. Sober E, Lewontin RC (1982) Artifact, cause and genic selection. Philos Sci 49:157–180CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  74. Sober E, Wilson DS (1998) Unto others: the evolution and psychology of unselfish behavior. Harvard University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  75. Sober E, Wilson DS (2002) Perspectives and Parameterizations. Biol Philos 17:529–537CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  76. Sober E, Wilson DS (2011) Adaptation and natural selection revisited. J Evol Biol 24:462–468CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  77. Sterelny K, Griffiths P (1999) Sex and death. An introduction to philosophy of biology. University of Chicago Press, ChicagoGoogle Scholar
  78. Sterelny K, Kitcher P (1988) The return of the gene. J Philos 85:339–361CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  79. Uyenoyama MK, Feldman MW (1980) Evolution of altruism under group selection in large and small populations in fluctuating environments. Theor Popul Biol 17:380–414CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  80. Wade MJ (1980) An experimental study of kin selection. Evolution 34(5):844–855CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  81. Wade MJ (1992) Sewall Wright: gene interaction and the shifting balance theory. In: Antonovics J, Futyuma D (eds) Oxford surveys of evolutionary biology VI. Oxford University Press, NY, pp 35–62Google Scholar
  82. Wade MJ (1996) Adaptation in subdivided populations: kin selection and interdemic selection. In: Rose MR, Lauder G (eds) Evolutionary biology and adaptation. Sinauer Associates, Sunderland, pp 381–405Google Scholar
  83. Wade MJ, Goodnight CJ (1998) Perspective: the theories of Fisher and Wright in the context of metapopulations. When nature does many small experiments. Evolution 52:1537–1553CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  84. Waters CK (2005) Why genic and multilevel selection theories are here to stay. Philos Sci 72:311–333CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  85. Welsh AH, Peterson AT, Altmann AS (1988) The fallacy of averages. Am Nat 132:277–288CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  86. Williams GC (1966) Adaptation and natural selection. Princeton University Press, PrincetonGoogle Scholar
  87. Williams GC (1992) Natural selection: domains, levels, and challenges. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  88. Wilson RA (2003) Pluralism, entwinement and the levels of selection. Philos Sci 70:531–552CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  89. Wilson DS, Sober E (1989) Reviving the Superorganism. J Theor Biol 136:337–356CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  90. Wimsatt WC (1980) Reductionist research strategies and their biases in the units of selection controversy. In: Nickles T (ed) Scientific discovery: case studies. Reidel, Dordrecht, pp 213–259CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  91. Wimsatt WC (2007) Re-engineering philosophy for limited beings piecewise approximations to reality. Harvard University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  92. Winther RG (2006a) Fisherian and Wrightian perspectives in evolutionary genetics and model-mediated imposition of theoretical assumptions. J Theor Biol 240:218–232CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  93. Winther RG (2006b) On the dangers of making scientific models ontologically independent: taking Richard Levins’ warnings seriously. Biol Philos 21:703–724CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  94. Winther RG (2006c) Parts and theories in compositional biology. Biol Philos 21:471–499CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  95. Winther RG (2011) Part–whole science. Synthese 178:397–427CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  96. Winther RG (2012) Interweaving categories: styles, paradigms, and models. Stud Hist Philos Sci A. Accessed Online 1 July 2012. http://philpapers.org/rec/WINICS
  97. Winther RG (2013) Evo-devo as a trading zone. In: Love A (ed) Conceptual change in biology: scientific and philosophical perspectives on evolution and development, Boston studies in the philosophy of science. Springer Verlag, Dordrecht. Accessed Online 1 July 2012. http://philpapers.org/rec/WINEAA-4
  98. Wolf JB, Brodie EB III, Wade MJ (eds) (2000) Epistasis and the evolutionary process. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  99. Wright S (1929) Evolution in a Mendelian population. Anat Rec 44:287Google Scholar
  100. Wright S (1930) Review of genetical theory of natural selection by RA Fisher. J Hered 21:349–356Google Scholar
  101. Wright S (1931) Evolution in Mendelian populations. Genetics 10:97–159Google Scholar
  102. Wright S (1945) Tempo and mode in evolution: a critical review. Ecology 26:415–419CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  103. Wright S (1959) Physiological genetics, ecology of populations, and natural selection. Perspect Biol Med 3:107–151Google Scholar
  104. Wright S (1969) Evolution and the genetics of populations. The theory of gene frequencies, vol 2. University of Chicago Press, ChicagoGoogle Scholar
  105. Wright S (1977) Evolution and the genetics of populations. Experimental results and evolutionary deductions, vol 3. University of Chicago Press, ChicagoGoogle Scholar
  106. Wright S (1980) Genic and organismic selection. Evolution 34:825–843CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  107. Wynne-Edwards VC (1962) Animal dispersion in relation to social behavior. Oliver and Boyd, EdinburghGoogle Scholar
  108. Wynne-Edwards VC (1985) Backstage and upstage with “animal dispersion”. In: Dewsbury D (ed) Studying animal behavior: autobiographies of the founders. University of Chicago Press, ChicagoGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  • Rasmus Grønfeldt Winther
    • 1
  • Michael J. Wade
    • 2
  • Christopher C. Dimond
    • 3
  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of California, Santa CruzSanta CruzUSA
  2. 2.Department of BiologyIndiana UniversityBloomingtonUSA
  3. 3.Center for Biology and SocietyArizona State UniversityTempeUSA

Personalised recommendations