Biology & Philosophy

, Volume 27, Issue 1, pp 49–71 | Cite as

A teleosemantic approach to information in the brain

Article

Abstract

The brain is often taken to be a paradigmatic example of a signaling system with semantic and representational properties, in which neurons are senders and receivers of information carried in action potentials. A closer look at this picture shows that it is not as appealing as it might initially seem in explaining the function of the brain. Working from several sender-receiver models within the teleosemantic framework, I will first argue that two requirements must be met for a system to support genuine semantic information: 1. The receiver must be competent—that is, it must be able to extract rewards from its environment on the basis of the signals that it receives. 2. The receiver must have some flexibility of response relative to the signal received. In the second part of the paper, this initial framework will be applied to neural processes, pointing to the surprising conclusion that signaling at the single-neuron level is only weakly semantic at best. Contrary to received views, neurons will have little or no access to semantic information (though their patterns of activity may carry plenty of quantitative, correlational information) about the world outside the organism. Genuine representation of the world requires an organism-level receiver of semantic information, to which any particular set of neurons makes only a small contribution.

Keywords

Neurons Sender-receiver Signaling Semantic information Flexibility 

References

  1. Bergstrom CT, Rosvall M (2009) The transmission sense of information. Biology & Philosophy 26:159–176Google Scholar
  2. Dennett DC (1984) Elbow room: the varieties of free will worth wanting. MIT Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  3. Dennett DC (1986) Content and consciousness. Routledge, LondonGoogle Scholar
  4. Dretske FI (1981) Knowledge and the flow of information. MIT Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  5. Ergenzinger ER et al (1998) Cortically induced thalamic plasticity in the primate somatosensory system. Nat Neurosci 1(3):226–229Google Scholar
  6. Faisal AA, Selen LP, Wolpert DM (2008) Noise in the nervous system. Nature Rev Neurosci 9(4):292–303Google Scholar
  7. Godfrey-Smith P (2006) Mental representation, naturalism, and teleosemantics. In: MacDonald G, Papineau D (eds) Teleosemantics. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 42–68Google Scholar
  8. Jablonka E (2002) Information: its interpretation, its inheritance, and its sharing. Philosophy Sci 69(4):578–605Google Scholar
  9. Lettvin JY, Maturana W, McCulloch S, Pitts WH (1968) What the frog’s eye tells the frog’s brain. Reprinted from Ch. 7 of The mind: biological approaches to its functions, Corning WC, Balaban M, pp 233–258Google Scholar
  10. Lewontin R (2000) Foreword to 2nd revised expanded edition of The ontogeny of information: developmental systems and evolution, Oyama S (ed). Duke University Press, DurhamGoogle Scholar
  11. Liu G (2004) Local structural balance and functional interaction of excitatory and inhibitory synapses in hippocampal dendrites. Nat Neurosci 7(4):373–379Google Scholar
  12. Millikan RG (1989) Biosemantics. J Philosophy 86(6):281–297Google Scholar
  13. Mitchell SD (2000) Dimensions of scientific law. Philosophy of Sci 67(2):242–265Google Scholar
  14. Queller DC, Strassman JE (2009) Beyond sociality: the evolution of organismality. Phil Trans R Soc Lond B 364:3143–3155Google Scholar
  15. Regehr WG, Carey MR, Best AR (2009) Activity-dependent regulation of synapses by retrograde messengers. Neuron 63(2):154–170Google Scholar
  16. Schultz W (2006) Behavioral theories and the neurophysiology of reward. Annual Rev Psychol 57(1):87–115Google Scholar
  17. Seyfarth RM, Cheney DL, Marler P (1980) Vervet monkey alarm calls: semantic communication in a free-ranging primate. Animal Behav 28(4):1070–1094Google Scholar
  18. Shannon CE (1948) A mathematical theory of communication. The Bell Syst Technical J 27:379–423, 623–656Google Scholar
  19. Shea N (2007a) Representation in the genome and in other inheritance systems. Biol Philosophy 22:313–331Google Scholar
  20. Shea N (2007b) Consumers need information: supplementing teleosemantics with an input condition. Philosophy Phenomenological Res 75(2):404–435Google Scholar
  21. Sherman SM, Guillery RW (2009) Exploring the thalamus and its role in cortical function, 2nd edn. The MIT Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  22. Skyrms B (1980) Causal necessity: a pragmatic investigation of the necessity of laws. Yale University Press, New HavenGoogle Scholar
  23. Skyrms B (2010) Signals: evolution, learning, and information. Oxford University Press, USGoogle Scholar
  24. Sterelny K (2003) Thought in a hostile world: the evolution of human cognition. Blackwell Publishing, MaldenGoogle Scholar
  25. Voglis G, Tavernarakis N (2006) The role of synaptic ion channels in synaptic plasticity. EMBO Reports 7:1104–1110Google Scholar
  26. Woodward J (2000) Explanation and invariance in the special sciences. The British J Philosophy Sci 51(2):197–254Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Tufts UniversityMedfordUSA

Personalised recommendations