Skip to main content
Log in

Causal isolation robustness analysis: the combinatorial strategy of circadian clock research

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper distinguishes between causal isolation robustness analysis and independent determination robustness analysis and suggests that the triangulation of the results of different epistemic means or activities serves different functions in them. Circadian clock research is presented as a case of causal isolation robustness analysis: in this field researchers made use of the notion of robustness to isolate the assumed mechanism behind the circadian rhythm. However, in contrast to the earlier philosophical case studies on causal isolation robustness analysis (Weisberg and Reisman in Philos Sci 75:106–131, 2008; Kuorikoski et al. in Br J Philos Sci 61:541–567, 2010), robustness analysis in the circadian clock research did not remain in the level of mathematical modeling, but it combined it with experimentation on model organisms and a new type of model, a synthetic model.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This strategy usually presumes that the phenomenon under study is robust itself, which creates a link between the epistemic uses of the notion of robustness and the causal robustness of the real phenomena (for this distinction, see Woodward 2006).

  2. Woodward in fact also criticizes this view, see also Stegenga (2009).

  3. So far, there has not been much overlap between the philosophical literatures on experimentation and robustness analysis.

  4. Circadian clock research has been used recently by Bechtel and Abrahamsen (2010, 2011) as an exemplary case of mechanistic research that has successfully combined the decompositional approach of finding the basic components of mechanisms to the study of their interactions by modeling. On our account this “recomposition” taking place between experimental results and modeling was far from seamless and synthetic models were partly designed to fill the gap between these two activities (cf. Loettgers 2007).

References

  • Alon U, Surette M, Barkai N, Leibler S (1999) Robustness in bacterial chemotaxis. Nature 397(6715):168–171

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barkai N, Leibler S (2000) Circadian clocks limited by noise. Nature 403(20):267–268

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel W, Abrahamsen A (2010) Dynamic mechanistic explanation: computational modeling of circadian rhythms as an examplar for cognitive science. Stud Hist Philos Sci Part A 41:321–333

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel W, Abrahamsen A (2011) Complex biological mechanisms: Cyclic, oscillatory, and autonomous. In: Hooker CA (ed) Philosophy of complex systems. Handbook of the philosophy of science, vol 10. Elsevier,Oxford, pp 257–285

  • Calcott B (2011) Wimsatt and the robustness family: Review of Wimsatt’s Re-engineering Philosophy for Limited Beings. Biol Philos 26:281–293

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright N (1989) Nature’s capacities and their measurement. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright N (1999) The vanity of rigour in economics: theoretical models and Galilean experiments. Centre for philosophy of natural and social science. Discussion paper series 43/99. (Published also in Fontaine P, Leonard R (eds) The Experiment in the History of Economics. Routledge, 2005)

  • Elowitz M, Leibler S (2000) A synthetic oscillatory network of transcriptional translation. Nature 403(6767):335–338

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldbeter A (1995) A model of circadian Oscillations in the Drosophila period protein (PER). In Proceedings of the R Soc B 261:319–324

  • Goldbeter A (1996) Biochemical Oscillations and cellular rhythms: the molecular bases of periodic and chaotic behavior. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goodwin B (1963) Temporal organization in cells. Academic Press, London and New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardin PE, Hall JC, Rosbash M (1990) Feedback of the Drosophila period gene product on circadian cycling of its messenger RNA levels. Nature 343:536–540

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Humphreys P (2002) Computational models. Philos Sci 69:1–11

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Humphreys P (2004) Extending ourselves: computational science, empiricism, and scientific method. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacob F, Monod J (1961) Genetic regulatory mechanisms in the synthesis of proteins. J Mol Biol 3:318–356

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kerner E (1957) A statistical mechanics of interacting biological species. Bul of Math Biophys 19:121–146

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitano H (2004) Biological robustness. Nat Rev Genet 5:826–837

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knuuttila T (2009) Isolating representations versus credible constructions? Economic modeling in theory and practice. Erkenntnis 70:59–80

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knuuttila T, Loettgers A (in press) The productive tension: mechanisms vs. templates in modeling the phenomena. In: Humphreys P, Imbert C (eds) Representations, models, and simulations. Routledge, London

  • Konopka RJ, Benzer S (1971) Clock mutants of Drosophila melanogaster. Proc Natl Acad Sci 68(9):2112–2116

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krugman P (1991) Increasing returns and economic geography. J Political Econ 99(3):483–499

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuorikoski J, Lehtinen A, Marchionni C (2010) Economic modeling as robustness analysis. Br J Philos Sci 61:541–567

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levins R (1966) The strategy of model building in population biology. Am Sci 54:421–431

    Google Scholar 

  • Levins R (1968) Evolution in changing environments; some theoretical explorations. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Levins R (1993) A response to Orzack and Sober: formal analysis and the fluidity of science. Q Rev Biol 68:547–555

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loettgers A (2007) Model organisms, mathematical models, and synthetic models in exploring gene regulatory mechanisms. Biol Theor 2:134–142

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mäki U (1992) On the method of isolation in economics. Poznan Stud Philos Sci Humanities 26:319–354

    Google Scholar 

  • Mäki U (2005) Models are experiments, experiments are models. J Econ Meth 12:303–315

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mäki U (2009) MISSing the world. Models as isolations and credible surrogate systems. Erkenntnis 70:29–43

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mäki U (2011) Models and the locus of their truth. Synthese 180:47–63

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill JS (1843) A system of logic. Longman, Green, & co, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell SD (2008) Exporting causal knowledge in evolutionary and developmental biology. Philos Sci 75:697–706

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morrison M (2008) Fictions, representations, and reality. In: Suárez M (ed) Fictions in science: philosophical essays on modeling and idealization. Routledge, New York & London, pp 110–135

    Google Scholar 

  • Orzack SH, Sober E (1993) A Critical assessment of Levins’s The strategy of model building in population biology (1966). Q Rev Biol 68:533–546

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parker W (2009) Does matter really matter? Computer simulations, experiments and materiality. Synthesis 169(3):483–496

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stegenga J (2009) Robustness, discordance, and relevance. Philos Sci 76:650–661

    Google Scholar 

  • Stelling J, Sauer U, Szallasi Z, Doyle FJ III, Doyle J (2004) Robustness of cellular functions. Cell 118:675–685

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens M (2008) Depth: an account of scientific explanation. Harvard University Press, Harvard

    Google Scholar 

  • Strogatz S (1994) Nonlinear dynamics and chaos: with applications to physics, biology, chemistry, and engineering. Perseus Pub, Cambridge, MA

  • Sugden R (2000) Credible worlds: the status of theoretical models in economics. J Econ Meth 7(1):169–201

    Google Scholar 

  • Taguchi G, Chowdhury S, Taguchi S (2000) Robust engineering. McGraw-Hill, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Volterra V (1927) Variations and fluctuations in the numbers of coexisting animal species. In: Scudo FM, Ziegler JR (eds) 1978, The golden age of theoretical ecology: 1923–1940. Springer, Berlin, pp 65–236

    Google Scholar 

  • Wagner A (2007) Robustness & evolvability in living systems (Princeton Studies in Complexity). Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg M (2006a) Forty years of “The strategy”: Levins on model building and idealization. Biol Philos 21:623–645

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg M (2006b) Robustness analysis. Philos Sci 73:730–742

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M (2007) Three kinds of idealization. J Philos CIV(12):639–659

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg M, Reisman K (2008) The robust Volterra principle. Philos Sci 75:106–131

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whittaker E (1941) Vito Volterra. Obit Notices Fellows Royal Soc London 3:691–729

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt WC (1981) Robustness, reliability, and overdetermination. In: Brewer MB, Collins B (eds) Scientific inquiry and the social sciences–A volume in honor of Donald T. Campbell. Jossey-Bass, San Francisco, pp 124–163

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt WC (2007) Re-engineering philosophy for limited beings: approximations to reality. Harvard Univ, Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Winfree AT (1967) Biological rhythms and the behavior of populations of coupled Oscillators. J Theoret Biol 16:15–42

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward J (2006) Some varieties of robustness. J Econ Meth 13:219–240

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The authors would like to thank the Academy of Finland and the Alfred P. Sloan Foundation for the support of this research.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tarja Knuuttila.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Knuuttila, T., Loettgers, A. Causal isolation robustness analysis: the combinatorial strategy of circadian clock research. Biol Philos 26, 773–791 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-011-9279-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-011-9279-x

Keywords

Navigation