Abstract
Despite the voluminous literature on biological functions produced over the last 40 years, few philosophers have studied the concept of function as it is used in neuroscience. Recently, Craver (forthcoming; also see Craver 2001) defended the causal role theory against the selected effects theory as the most appropriate theory of function for neuroscience. The following argues that though neuroscientists do study causal role functions, the scope of that theory is not as universal as claimed. Despite the strong prima facie superiority of the causal role theory, the selected effects theory (when properly developed) can handle many cases from neuroscience with equal facility. It argues this by presenting a new theory of function that generalizes the notion of a ‘selection process’ to include processes such as neural selection, antibody selection, and some forms of learning—that is, to include structures that have been differentially retained as well as those that have been differentially reproduced. This view, called the generalized selected effects theory of function, will be defended from criticism and distinguished from similar views in the literature.
This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution.

Notes
The difference between selectionist and non-selectionist accounts of synaptic structure formation will be described in the following section.
Not all biologists, nor philosophers of biology, would accept neural selection as a type of ‘natural selection.’ This is because, in their view, reproduction is a sine qua non of natural selection (e.g., Okasha 2003; see Bouchard 2008 for an opposing view and Godfrey-Smith 2007 for an overview of definitions of ‘natural selection’ and a description of the role of ‘reproduction’).
This is not the primary route through which Millikan attributes functions to novel traits. Rather, she relies on a distinction between ‘direct’ and ‘derived’ proper functions to make sense of the functions of novel traits (e.g., Millikan 1984, 41–42; 1989, 288). Although this is a reasonable distinction in some contexts, it has the unattractive conclusion that one must seek out a ‘direct function’ for many of the novel traits that one would like to ascribe functions to, even if it is not obvious what that direct function is. For example, brain changes underlying reading ability or the ability to play Tetris may have derived proper functions, but it is not clear from which direct proper functions those functions are derived.
This ambiguity is reflected in the disparate ways he formulates the definition of ‘function.’ In his earlier presentation, the function of an entity is explicitly defined in terms of a ‘selection process’ (1987, 65). In his later presentation, the function of an entity is explicitly defined in terms of any self-perpetuating process: “X has the function of doing Y if and only if item X is now present as a result of causing Y” (1993, 45). In this latter view, being selected for is merely a ‘paradigm’ for the theory and not part of the definition.
Godfrey-Smith (1992), like Papineau, explicitly includes both the products of natural selection as well as learning in an early account of biological function: “a selective basis for functional characterization is available whenever learned characters are maintained within the cognitive system because of their consequences” (ibid., 292). However, the problem with this view is that it does not specify that these learned characters must be the result of selection and not merely a generic, self-perpetuating process. Godfrey-Smith (1993, 199) rejects his earlier account of function and insists, along with Millikan, that in order for something to possess a function it must undergo reproduction, thus severing the link between evolution and learning. However, he may have avoided this admittedly unattractive conclusion (ibid.) if he had restricted functions to the parts of biological systems that undergo selection but which do not necessarily reproduce.
Brandon (forthcoming) draws a similar conclusion by pointing to the valuable co-existence of historical and ahistorical concepts in many scientific disciplines.
References
Allen C, Bekoff M (1995) Biological function, adaptation, and natural design. Philos Sci 62:609–622
Amundson R, Lauder GV (1994) Function without purpose: the uses of causal role function in evolutionary biology. Biol Philos 9:443–469
Antonini A, Stryker MP (1993) Rapid remodeling of axonal arbors in the visual cortex. Science 260:1819–1821
Bedau M (1992) Where’s the good in teleology? Philos Phenomenol Res 52:781–805
Bigelow J, Pargetter R (1987) Functions. J Philos 84:181–196
Blair RJ (2003) Neurological basis of psychopathy. Br J Psychiatry 182:5–7
Boorse C (1976) Wright on functions. Philos Rev 85:70–86
Bouchard F (2008) Causal processes, fitness, and the differential persistence of lineages. Philos Sci 75:560–570
Bouchard F (forthcoming) How ecosystem evolution strengthens the case for functional pluralism. In: Huneman P (ed) Functions: selection and mechanisms. Synthese Library, Boston, pp 56–71
Brandon RN (1990) Adaptation and environment. Princeton University Press, Princeton
Brandon RN (forthcoming) A general case for functional pluralism. In: Huneman P (ed) Functions: selection and mechanisms. Synthese Library, Boston, pp 72–78
Brown MC, Jansen JKS, Van Essen D (1976) Polyneural innervation of skeletal muscle in new-born rats and its elimination during maturation. J Physiol 261:387–422
Burnet FM (1959) The clonal selection theory of acquired immunity. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
Changeux J-P, Danchin A (1976) Selective stabilization of developing synapses as a mechanism for the specification of neuronal networks. Nat 264:705–711
Craver C (2001) Role functions, mechanisms, and hierarchy. Philos Sci 68:53–74
Craver C (forthcoming) Functions and mechanisms: a perspectivalist view. In: Huneman P (ed) Functions: selection and mechanisms. Synthese Library, Boston, pp 199–220
Crick F (1989) Neural Edelmanism. Trends Neurosci 12:240–248
Cziko G (1995) Without miracles: universal selection theory and the second Darwinian revolution. MIT Press, Cambridge
Darden L, Cain JA (1989) Selection type theories. Philos Sci 56:106–129
Davies PS (2001) Norms of nature: naturalism and the nature of functions. MIT Press, Cambridge
Deacon TW (1989) The neural circuitry underlying primate calls and human language. Hum Evol 4:367–401
Edelman G (1978) Group selection and phasic reentrant signaling: a theory of higher brain function. In: Edelman GE, Mountcastle VB (eds) The Mindful brain: cortical organization and the group-selective theory of higher brain function. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 51–100
Edelman G (1987) Neural Darwinism: the theory of neuronal group selection. Basic Books, New York
Garson J (2008) Function and teleology. In: Sarkar S, Plutynski A (eds) A companion to the philosophy of biology. Blackwell, Malden, MA, pp 525–549
Garson J (2010) Schizophrenia and the dysfunctional brain. J Cog Sci 11:215–246
Godfrey-Smith P (1992) Indication and adaptation. Synthese 92:283–312
Godfrey-Smith P (1993) Functions: consensus without unity. Pac Philos Q 74:196–208
Godfrey-Smith P (1994) A modern history theory of functions. Noûs 28:344–362
Godfrey-Smith P (2007) Conditions for evolution by natural selection. J Philos 104:489–516
Gould SJ, Lewontin RC (1979) The spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian paradigm: a critique of the adaptationist programme. Proc R Soc B 205(1161):581–598
Griffiths PE (1993) Functional analysis and proper function. Br J Philos Sci 44:409–422
Griffiths PE (2006) Function, homology, and character individuation. Philos Sci 73:1–25
Haier RJ, Karama S, Leyba L, Jung RE (2009) MRI assessment of cortical thickness and functional activity changes in adolescent girls following three months of practice on a visual-spatial task. BMC Res Notes 2:174–180
Hardcastle VG (1999) Understanding functions: a pragmatic approach. In: Hardcastle VG (ed) Where biology meets psychology: philosophical essays. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 27–43
Hull DL, Langman RE, Glenn SS (2001) A general account of selection: biology, immunology and behavior. Behav Brain Sci 24:511–527
Kingsbury J (2008) Learning and selection. Biol Philos 23:493–507
Kitcher P (1993) Function and design. Midwest Stud Philos 18:379–397
Lewens T (2007) Functions. In: Matthen M, Stevens C, Gabbay DM, Thagard P, Woods J (eds) Philosophy of biology. Elsevier, Amsterdam, pp 525–547
Mace CA (1949 [1935]) Mechanical and teleological causation. In: Feigl H, Sellars W (eds) Readings in philosophical analysis. Appleton-Century-Crofts, Inc, New York, pp 534–539
MacLaurin J, Sterelny K (2008) What is biodiversity? University of Chicago Press, Chicago
Mathews TJ, Ventura SJ (1997) Birth and fertility rates by educational attainment: United States, 1994. Mon Vital Statistics Rep 45(10):1–19
Matteo M, Saborido C, Moreno A (2009) An organizational account of biological functions. British J Philos Sci 60:813–841
McDowell JJ (2009) Behavioral and neural Darwinism: selectionist function and mechanism in adaptive behavior dynamics. Behav Process. doi:10.1016/j.beproc.2009.11.011
McLaughlin P (2001) What functions explain: Functional explanation and self-reproducing systems. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
Millikan RG (1984) Language, thought, and other biological categories. MIT Press, Cambridge
Millikan RG (1989) In defense of proper functions. Philos Sci 56:288–302
Mitchell SD (1995) Function, fitness, and disposition. Biol Philos 10:39–54
Neander K (1983) Abnormal psychobiology. Dissertation, La Trobe
Neander K (1991) Functions as selected effects: the conceptual analyst’s defense. Philos Sci 58:168–184
Okasha S (2003) Does the concept of “clade selection” make sense? Philos Sci 70:739–751
Papineau D (1987) Reality and representation. Blackwell, New York
Papineau D (1993) Philosophical naturalism. Blackwell, Oxford
Petersen SE, Fox PT, Snyder AZ, Raichle ME (1990) Activation of extrastriate and frontal cortical areas by visual words and word-like stimuli. Sci 249:1041–1044
Pettmann C, Henderson CE (1998) Neuronal cell death. Neuron 20:647–653
Prior EW (1985) What is wrong with etiological accounts of biological function? Pac Philos Q 66:310–328
Purves D (1994) Neural activity and the growth of the brain. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
Purves D, Lichtman JW (1980) Elimination of synapses in the developing nervous system. Sci 210:153–157
Quartz SR, Sejnowski TJ (1997) The neural basis of cognitive development: a constructivist manifesto. Behav Brain Sci 20:537–596
Rajewsky K (1996) Clonal selection and learning in the antibody system. Nat 381:751–758
Robins SK, Craver CF (2009) Biological clocks: explaining with models of mechanisms. In: Bickle J (ed) The oxford handbook of philosophy and neuroscience. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 41–67
Ruse ME (1971) Functional statements in biology. Philos Sci 38:87–95
Sarkar S (2005) Molecular models of life: Philosophical papers on molecular biology. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA
Schaffner K (1993) Discovery and explanation in biology and medicine. University of Chicago Press, Chicago
Scheffler I (1958) Thoughts on teleology. Br J Philos Sci 9:265–284
Schlaggar BL, McCandliss BD (2007) Development of neural systems for reading. Ann Rev Neurosci 30:475–503
Schultz W (1998) Predictive reward signal of dopamine neurons. J Neurophysiol 80:1–27
Schultz W, Dickenson A (2000) Neuronal coding of prediction errors. Ann Rev Neurosci 23:473–500
Schwartz PH (1999) Proper function and recent selection. Philos Sci 66:S210–S222
Sober E (1984) The nature of selection. MIT Press, Cambridge
Walsh DM (1996) Fitness and function. British J Philos Sci 47:553–574
Walsh DM, Ariew A (1996) A taxonomy of functions. Can J Philos 26:493–514
Wiesel TN, Hubel DH (1963) Single-cell responses in striate cortex of kittens deprived of vision in one eye. J Neurophysiol 26:1003–1017
Wimsatt WC (1972) Teleology and the logical structure of function statements. Stud Hist Philos Sci 3:1–80
Wong ROL, Lichtman JW (2002) Synapse elimination. In: Squire LR, Bloom FE, McConnell SK, Roberts JL, Spitzer NC, Zigmond MJ (eds) Fundamental neuroscience, 2nd edn. Academic Press, Amsterdam, pp 533–554
Wouters A (2003) Four notions of biological function. Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 34:633–668
Wright L (1973) Functions. Philos Rev 82:139–168
Acknowledgments
The author wishes to express his gratitude to Carl Craver, Gualtiero Piccinini, Anya Plutynski, and the University of Utah philosophy of biology lab group for comments and criticism on an earlier draft.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Garson, J. Selected effects and causal role functions in the brain: the case for an etiological approach to neuroscience. Biol Philos 26, 547–565 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-011-9262-6
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-011-9262-6
Keywords
- Teleology
- Function
- Neuroscience
- Mechanism
- Selection
- Neural Darwinism