Skip to main content
Log in

Universal grammar and the Baldwin effect: a hypothesis and some philosophical consequences

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Grammar is now widely regarded as a substantially biological phenomenon, yet the problem of language evolution remains a matter of controversy among Linguists, Cognitive Scientists, and Evolutionary Theorists alike. In this paper, I present a new theoretical argument for one particular hypothesis—that a “Language Acquisition Device” of the sort first posited by Noam Chomsky might have evolved via the so-called “Baldwin Effect”. Close attention to the workings of that mechanism, I argue, helps to explain a previously mysterious feature of the Language Acquisition Device—the sheer variety of languages it allows the child to learn—thereby revealing a far stronger case than adherents of the hypothesis have previously supposed. A further unheralded consequence of the hypothesis is a conceptual shift in the Chomskyan understanding of language, wherein the essentially public nature of language is freshly emphasised. This has the effect of bringing the Chomskyan view into closer accord with Saussurean accounts of language, as well as with recent trends in evolutionary theory.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For examples of such work, see e.g. Lieberman (1984) on the physical costs of the larynx and Lieberman (1989, p. 396) which describes as “impossible to even survey” the copious literature regarding “genetically transmitted neural devices that facilitate the perception of… human speech.”.

  2. Pinker (1995, p. 174) discusses the evidence that there may be “default” settings to these parameters.

  3. c.f. Pinker (1995, p. 146) on the prerequisites for learning dictated by learnability theory.

  4. Similar effects were hypothesised almost simultaneously by Henry F. Osborn (1896) and Conwy Lloyd Morgan (1896).

  5. Depew (2003) provides a useful overview of the principal varieties of such theories. The version I outline here owes most to the account given by Daniel Dennett (1993, 1996, 2003), although little of my argument hangs on the differences between the various strains.

  6. On the distinction between “plasticity” and “elasticity” in learning, see Tobin (1999, p. 7). The distinction is based upon materials science, where plastic materials subjected to a force deform permanently, while elastic materials return to their original form once the force is removed.

  7. Hinton and Nowlan (1987) was the first such study. Briscoe (2003, pp. 307–314) summarises the numerous subsequent studies, and their varying emphases and distinctions, including a variety specifically concerning language and grammar. Downes (2003) summarises the case “that there are not sufficient grounds to add the Baldwin effect to our evolutionary explanatory repertoire” (p. 33).

  8. c.f Chomsky’s discussion (1980, p. 8ff) of what Husserl termed the “Galilean style” of theory formation. How realistic the idealisation is may be open to question, but it greatly assists us in gaining conceptual clarity about the evolution of language.

  9. A very similar idealisation regarding a “homogeneous speech community” is at the root of Chomsky’s theorising—see ibid. p. 25.

  10. As the Minimalist Program seeks to reduce the number of grammatical principles to one, I have pluralised the statement in line with the older Principles and Parameters model; the original reads “… a finitely specified generative procedure (function) that enumerates an infinite set…”. This has been done with a view to aiding understanding of our model and the relation in which it stands to the language. Apart from suspending judgement on Minimalism, little violence is done to Chomsky’s views by the change; a very similar, though less concise, account is given in Chomsky (1980, p. 220).

  11. Kneale and Kneale (1984, p. 364) trace this insight to the seventeenth-century “Port Royal Logic” of Arnauld and Nicole which, via Descartes, strongly influenced Chomsky.

  12. Though I have treated the E-language/I-language and performance/competence distinctions as more or less coextensive for the purposes of this paper, they are distinct concepts. In Rules and Representations (1980, p. 59) Chomsky expresses misgivings about the term “competence”, which “avoids entanglement with the slew of problems relating to ‘knowledge’, but… is misleading in that it suggests ‘ability’, an association that I would like to sever.” Due to such considerations, Chomsky later rephrased the distinction as one between “I-language” and “E-language”. I have generally found it less ambiguous to use the older vocabulary, and will continue to do so here.

  13. For a detailed discussion of this idea with specific reference to Baldwin effects, niche construction, and language acquisition, see Depew (2003), Downes (2003), Deacon (2003) Godfrey-Smith (2003) and Dennett (2003).

  14. For a contemporary example of the speed at which this can take place, and the high degree of grammatical creativity it may involve, see Adams (2003).

  15. It is, needless to say, unlikely that public language remained perfectly static for the duration of the LAD’s evolution. Nevertheless, I am relying here, following Chomsky (1980, p. 8ff), on a “Galilean” idealisation of the subject. For more sophisticated accounts of the interaction of culture and evolutions—albeit accounts too complex for the purposes of the present idealisation—see in particular Sterelny (2004, 2006) and Wimsatt and Griesemer (2007), as well as the literature on “niche construction” discussed in “Competence and performance” below, where the interactive nature of the LAD/environment relation is emphasised.

  16. Pinker and Bloom (1990, p. 723) noted this effect, and foresaw that it may be connected to the multiplicity of human languages, though they continue to discuss the question in terms of generalized learning mechanisms. Pinker (1994, chap. 8), though dealing with language diversity, does not follow up the Baldwin effect possibility.

  17. Though the possible evolutionary origins of competence have more recently been discussed by him in conjunction with his colleagues Tecumseh Fitch and Marc Hauser, where a distinction is made between the evolvable faculty of language in its “broad” (FLB) and uniquely human “narrow” (FLN) senses. See in particular section 1.3 of Fitch et al. (2005), as well as Hauser et al. (2002).

References

  • Adams M (2003) Slayer slang: a Buffy the vampire slayer lexicon. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexander R (1989) Evolution of the human psyche. In: Mellars P, Stringer C (eds) The human revolution: behavioural and biological perspectives on the origins of modern humans. Edinburgh University Press, Edinburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • Avital E, Jablonka E (2000) Animal traditions: behavioural inheritance in evolution. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Baldwin JM (1896) A new factor in evolution. Am Nat 30(441–51):536–553

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bates E, MacWhinney B (1982) Functionalist approaches to grammar. In: Wanner E, Gleitman LR (eds) Language acquisition: the state of the art. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Bates E, Thal D, Marchman V (1989) Symbols and syntax: a Darwinian approach to language development. In: Krasnegor N, Rumbaugh D, Studdert-Kennedy M, Schiefelbusch R (eds) The biological foundations of language development. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Bateson P, Mameli M (2007) The innate and the acquired: useful clusters or a residual distinction from folk biology? Dev Psychobiol 49:818–831

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bickerton D (1983) Creole languages. Sci Am 249(1):108–115

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Briscoe T (2003) Grammatical assimilation. In: Christiansen MH, Kirby S (eds) Language evolution. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky N (1968) Quine’s empirical assumptions. Synthese 19(1): 53–68. Expanded as (1969) Some empirical assumptions in modern philosophy of language. In: Morgenbesser S, Suppes P, White M (eds) Philosophy, science, and method: essays in honor of Ernest Nagel. St. Martin’s Press, New York, pp 260–85

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky N (1972) Language and mind. Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky N (1975) Reflections on language. Pantheon, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky N (1980) Rules and representations. Basil Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky N (1988) Language and problems of knowledge: the Managua lectures. MIT Press, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky N (1995) The minimalist program. MIT, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky N (2000) New horizons in the study of language and mind. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky N (2002) On nature and language. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky N (2005a) Some simple evo-devo theses: how true might they be for language? MS. URL=www.linguistics.stonybrook.edu/old_events/nyct05/abstracts/Chomsky.pdf Accessed 4 May 2010

  • Chomsky N (2005b) Three factors in language design. Linguist Inq 36(1):1–22

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christiansen MH, Chater N (2008) Language as shaped by the brain. Behav Brain Sci 31:489–558

    Google Scholar 

  • de Saussure F (1959) Course in general linguistics. Philosophical Library, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Deacon TW (2003) Multilevel selection in a complex adaptive system: the problem of language origins. In: Weber BH, Depew DJ (eds) Evolution and learning: the Baldwin effect reconsidered. MIT, London, pp 81–106

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett DC (1993) Consciousness explained. Penguin, Harmondsworth

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett DC (1996) Darwin’s dangerous idea: evolution and the meanings of life. Penguin, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett DC (2003) The Baldwin effect: a crane, not a skyhook. In: Weber BH, Depew DJ (eds) Evolution and learning: the Baldwin effect reconsidered. MIT, London, pp 69–79

    Google Scholar 

  • Depew DJ (2003) Baldwin and his many effects. In: Weber BH, Depew DJ (eds) Evolution and learning: the Baldwin effect reconsidered. MIT, London, pp 3–31

    Google Scholar 

  • Dor D, Jablonka E (2000) From cultural selection to genetic selection: a framework for the evolution of language. Selection 1:33–55

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Downes S (2003) Baldwin effects and the expansion of the explanatory repertoire in evolutionary biology. In: Weber BH, Depew DJ (eds) Evolution and learning: the Baldwin effect reconsidered. MIT, London, pp 33–51

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunbar R (2003) The origin and subsequent evolution of language. In: Christiansen MH, Kirby S (eds) Language evolution. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans N, Levinson SC (2009) The myth of language universals: language diversity and its importance for cognitive science. Behav Brain Sci 32:429–492

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitch WT, Hauser MD, Chomsky N (2005) The evolution of the language faculty: clarifications and implications. Cognition 97:179–210

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gellner E (1989) Culture, constraint and community: semantic and coercive compensations for the genetic under-determination of Homo Sapiens Sapiens. In: Mellars P, Stringer C (eds) The human revolution: behavioural and biological perspectives on the origins of modern humans. Edinburgh University Press, Edinburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • Geschwind N (1980) Some comments on the neurology of language. In: Caplan D (ed) Biological studies of mental processes. MIT, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (1996) Complexity and the function of mind in nature. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2003) Between Baldwin skepticism and Baldwin boosterism. In: Weber BH, Depew DJ (eds) Evolution and learning: the Baldwin effect reconsidered. MIT, London, pp 53–68

    Google Scholar 

  • Greenberg JH, Osgood CE, Jenkins JJ (1963) Memorandum concerning language universals. In: Greenberg JH (ed) Universals of language. MIT, London, pp xv–xxvii

    Google Scholar 

  • Griesemer JR (1992) Niche: historical perspectives. In: Keller EF, Lloyd E (eds) Keywords in evolutionary biology. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, pp 231–240

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths P (2002) What is innateness? Monist 85(1):70–85

    Google Scholar 

  • Hauser MD, Chomsky N, Fitch WT (2002) The faculty of language: What is it, who has it, and how did it evolve? Science 298:1569–1579

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hinton GE, Nowlan SJ (1987) How learning can guide evolution. Complex Syst 1:495–502

    Google Scholar 

  • Hockett CF (1963) The problem of universals in language. In: Greenberg JH (ed) Universals of language. MIT, London, pp 1–29

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurford JR (2003) The language mosaic and its evolution. In: Christiansen MH, Kirby S (eds) Language evolution. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka E, Lamb MJ (2005) Evolution in four dimensions: genetic, epigenetic, behavioural, and symbolic variation in the history of life. MIT, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackendoff R (2003) The foundations of language; Brain, meaning, grammar, evolution. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Kneale W, Kneale M (1984) The development of logic. Clarendon, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Komarova NL, Nowak MA (2003) Language, learning, and evolution. In: Christiansen MH, Kirby S (eds) Language evolution. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin RC (1982) Organism and environment. In: Plotkin HC (ed) Learning, development, and culture. Wiley, New York, pp 151–170

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin RC (1985) The organism as subject and object of evolution. In: Levins R, Lewontin RC (eds) The dialectical biologist. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin RC (2000) Foreword to the second edition. In: Oyama S (ed) The ontogeny of information: developmental systems and evolution, 2nd edn. Duke University Press, Durham, pp vii–xv

    Google Scholar 

  • Lieberman P (1984) The biology and evolution of language. Harvard University Press, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Lieberman P (1989) The origins of some aspects of human language and cognition. In: Mellars P, Stringer C (eds) The human revolution: behavioural and biological perspectives on the origins of modern humans. Edinburgh University Press, Edinburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • MacLaurin J (2002) The resurrection of innateness. Monist 85(1):105–130

    Google Scholar 

  • Mameli M (2008) On innateness: the clutter hypothesis and the cluster hypothesis. J Philos 12:719–737

    Google Scholar 

  • Mameli M, Bateson P (2006) Innateness and the sciences. Biol Philos 21:155–188

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maratsos M (1988) Innateness and plasticity in language acquisition. In: Rice M, Schiefelbusch R (eds) The teachability of language. P. H. Brookes, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Maratsos M (1990) Middle positions on language, cognition, and evolution. Behav Brain Sci 13:744–745

    Google Scholar 

  • McGinn C (1993) Problems in philosophy: the limits of enquiry. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan CL (1896) On modification and variation. Science 4:733–740

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nettle D, Dunbar R (1997) Social markers and the evolution of reciprocal exchange. Curr Anthropol 38:93–98

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Odling-Smee FJ, Laland KN, Feldman M (1996) Niche construction. Am Nat 147:641–648

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Osborn HF (1896) Ontogenic and phylogenic variation. Science 4(100):786–789

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oyama S (1985) The ontogeny of information. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Petitto L-A (2005) How the brain begets language. In: McGilvray J (ed) The Cambridge companion to Chomsky. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 84–101

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Piatelli-Palmarini M (1989) Evolution, selection, and cognition: from “learning” to parameter setting in biology and in the study of language. Cognition 31:1–44

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pinker S (1994) The language instinct: the new science of language and mind. Penguin, Harmondsworth

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinker S (1995) Language acquisition. In: Gleitman LR, Liberman MY (eds) An invitation to cognitive science vol.1—language. MIT Press, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinker S (2002) The blank slate: the modern denial of human nature. Allen Lane, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinker S, Bloom P (1990) Natural language and natural selection. Behav Brain Sci 13:707–784

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinker S, Jackendoff R (2009) The reality of a universal language faculty. Behav Brain Sci 32:465–466

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quine WVO (1960) Word and object. MIT, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle JR (2002) End of the revolution: Chomsky’s thermidor. New York Rev Books XLIX(3):33–36

    Google Scholar 

  • Sperber D (1990) The evolution of the language faculty: a paradox and its solution. Behav Brain Sci 13:756–758

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny K (2004) The Baldwin effect and its significance: a review. In: Weber B, Depew D (eds) Evolution and learning: the Baldwin effect reconsidered. Evol Dev 6: 295–300

  • Sterelny K (2006) Memes revisited. Br J Philos Sci 57:145–165

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Studdert-Kennedy M (1991) Language development from an evolutionary perspective. In: Krasnegor N, Rumbaugh D, Schiefelbusch R, Studdert-Kennedy M (eds) Biological and behavioural determinants of language development. L. Erlbaum, Hillsdale

    Google Scholar 

  • Tobin A (1999) Amazing grace: sources of phenotypic variation in genetic boosterism. In: Carson RA, Rothstein MA (eds) Behavioral genetics: the clash of culture and biology. Johns Hopkins University Press, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams GC (1966) Adaptation and natural selection: a critique of some current evolutionary thought. Princeton University Press, Chichester

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt WC, Griesemer J (2007) Reproducing entrenchments to scaffold culture: the central role of development in cultural evolution. In: Sansom R, Brandon R (eds) Integrating evolution and development: from theory to practice. MIT, Cambridge, pp 227–323

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am greatly indebted to James Levine, Brian Garvey, Greg Radick, Jon Hodge and Morten Christiansen, among others, as well as to the editor and anonymous reviewers, for extremely helpful comments and advice at various stages.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Shane Nicholas Glackin.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Glackin, S.N. Universal grammar and the Baldwin effect: a hypothesis and some philosophical consequences. Biol Philos 26, 201–222 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-010-9225-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-010-9225-3

Keywords

Navigation