Skip to main content
Log in

The Enigma of ‘Being There’: Choosing Between Ontology and Epistemology

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Axiomathes Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The aim of this paper is to show, based on Heidegger’s ontology of being and Husserl’s ontological aspects of phenomenology, the ways in which may be highlighted the ontological turned epistemological (and vice versa) enigma of the actual presence of being-in-the-world. In such perspective the content of the philosophical term ‘being there’, in the sense of an original presence in the actuality of the world, is the key issue of discussion both in terms of the ontological implication of the accompanying notion of transcendence and the epistemological relevance it can have by virtue of a phenomenon within the world. Concerning the latter in particular, except for some prompts from formal-mathematical theory, a special attention is drawn to the incompleteness of quantum theory with regard to the treatment of certain ‘ontological’ aspects of the measurement question in a quantum context. The clarification of certain epistemological ‘black box’ cases as this one by virtue of a subjectively based interpretation of the ‘being there’ is a main goal of this article as well as the ontological foundation of the ‘being there’ per se.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The question of an ‘isolated’ from the world pure ego was, in fact, left by Husserl himself quite murky or, at least, ambivalent thus offering grounds for misinterpretations or conflicting views by the phenomenologists that followed suit. At some point Husserl regarded the construction of the eidos of transcendental ego as constituted unity unthinkable without a conception of the transcendental ego as factual, (Husserl (1973), p. 385), which makes by itself the assumption of a pure, isolated from the world ego quite problematic, while furnishing by the same token substantive credentials to the concept of the Heideggerian Dasein as essentially defined by its special kind of presence-in-the-world.

  2. For Husserl the validity of the life-world, the latter a phenomenological term describing grosso modo the world as the horizon of our intersubjectively defined presence, is derived out of the a priori ‘constituting’ intentionality of transcendental subjectivity, and accordingly life-world in its ultimate ontic meaning is immanently constituted according to the universal eidetic categories of thematic consciousness and the a priori norms of subjective (temporal) unity (Husserl (1976a), Engl. transl., p. 69).

  3. See: Moran (2014), pp. 507, 510.

  4. The term osmotic appearing twice in the text is not intended to have any ontological or other meaning except for its rather loose literary use to refer to the (existing) mutual influence ontological philosophy and epistemology have developed over the last two centuries. Yet if the author would be inclined to think in terms of the more restricted physical meaning of osmotic relation, i.e., in terms of the spontaneous vs. forced flow, he would choose philosophy, in the Husserlian sense of a universal eidetic science, over science in the conventional sense as representing the spontaneity of the flow.

  5. See e.g. van Fraassen’s views in van Fraasen (1985) and van Fraasen (1991).

  6. See e.g., D. Krause’s views in Krause (2011), Arenhart and Krause (2014) and Krause and Arenhard (2020).

  7. In Two dogmas of empiricism, Quine’s view of physical as well as of abstract objects essentially as convenient posits toward “working a manageable structure into the flux of experience” is primarily driven by his pragmatist concerns and correspondingly of no particular significance as to an ontological inquiry into the sense of being of objects as such. Yet his attitude of preserving an experience-independent conceptual corpus as a means to accommodate recalcitrant experience at the ‘edges’ is a telling sign of the ways epistemological issues may conflate with ontological concerns. This is also related with Quine’s objectual interpretation of quantification, in the sense that it is not a substitutional quantification that is relevant to ontology but the quantification over the values of the variables when taken as objects in the domain over which these variables range.

  8. By eidetic laws or eidetic attributes one can roughly determine what relates to properties of objects or states-of-affairs as regularities by essential necessity and not by mere facticity. One may consult E. Husserl’s Ideas I in Husserl (1976b), Engl. transl., pp. 12-15.

  9. A. Chakravartty in Chakravartty (2017) has vowed to explain why it is that any sort of scientific ontology involves at least the tacit acceptance of some metaphysical inferences, arguing that “scientific and even everyday observations are theory laden in the sense that theoretical beliefs held prior to observation significantly shape how they are experienced and described” (Chakravartty (2017), p. 56). However, in spite of Chakravartty’s invocation of metaphysical inferences as having a significant a priori dimension due to their substantial conditioning on non-empirical considerations in terms of which the explanatory virtues of a given theory or hypothesis of observable phenomena are reducible to underlying objects, events, or properties, he actually nowhere proceeds to a discussion of the a priori dimension of metaphysical inferences in purely ontological terms, much less so in subjectively founded ones.

  10. The three forms of PII, are: PII(1), stating that it is not possible for two individuals to possess all properties and relations in common, the form PII(2) that excludes spatio-temporal properties and the strongest form PII(3) that includes only monadic, non-relational properties alluding in a certain sense to Leibniz’s views on monadology. For details see: Identity and Individuality in Quantum Theory, (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy): https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qt-idind/\(\sharp\)PII.

  11. Roughly said the closure \(\overline{S}\) of a subset S of a topological space X is the union of the set S together with its limit points, the latter meant as the points of X whose neighborhoods have non-empty intersections with S.

  12. A noematic object is constituted by certain a priori modes as a well-defined object immanent to the temporal flux of a subject’s consciousness, in simpler terms an object as meant and in the modes it is meant. More in Husserl’s it Ideas I; Husserl (1976b), Engl. transl., pp. 229-232.

  13. Immanence, a properly phenomenological term, can be roughly characterized the ‘interiority’ of consciousness in contrast to all that is ‘external’ to it. An immanent object is thought of as a correlate of intentional consciousness as opposed to a transcendent to the consciousness common physical object whose objectivity is put anyway by phenomenology into brackets.

  14. For an argumentation in favor of a refutation of the notion of mathematical objects as immutable and a-temporal ones, see: Livadas (2017), sec. 3, 5.

  15. As a matter of fact \(\omega\)-consistency is easily proved to imply simple consistency.

  16. Presentation in actuality as a general state-of-affairs should be understood in a deeper phenomenological sense as the implementation of the subjective character of the ‘being there’ in the world. I point out that for Husserl everything belonging to this world has its origin in the primeval flux of the living present (lebendige Gegenwart) which is essentially the mode of being of primeval ego (Ur-Ego), the originaliter known primeval phenomenal being, (Husserl (2001), pp. 4, 7).

  17. Arguments in favor or against quantum individuality can be indicatively found in: Dorato and Morganti (2013), Krause (2011), Arenhart and Krause (2014), Krause and Arenhard (2020), Redhead and Teller (1992).

  18. For a more detailed reference to the consistent quantum histories approach the reader can look, for example, at Isham (1994) and Griffiths (1984).

  19. A first-kind measurement is one in which the measured quantum system described by the quantum state s is taken to interact with the measuring apparatus described by the quantum state \(\varphi\), so that the total wave function before the interaction is \(s \cdot \varphi\).

  20. An interesting article on the purported implication of the Husserlian phenomenological ego in the quantum measurement question, giving as a matter of fact also some clues to the intricacies of the concept of pure ego itself, is S. French’s A Phenomenological Solution to the Measurement Problem? Husserl and the Foundations of Quantum Mechanics, French (2002).

  21. Boge refers to the decisive role attributed to consciousness in Zeh’s and Wallace’s interpretation of MWI in the sense that “only in relation to the experience of conscious beings can these (classical) ‘worlds’ (auth. add.: i.e., multiple universes) really be said to exist, because decoherence preserves one (highly entangled) state vector and never fully eliminates the off diagonal terms in a density matrix, while we (the somehow dynamically created conscious beings) do not perceive ourselves as simultaneously ‘partly’ in this and partly in that ‘branch’ ” (Boge (2018), p. 269).

  22. Friedman has argued in Friedman (1999) that Kant’s second tenet, namely that the (constitutive) a priori principles are given once and for all “independently of our observing and theorizing”, becomes untenable by the evolution of science as the ground of prescriptive principles laid down ‘à la carte’. For instance the position that, insofar as objects are perceptible and conceivable by being embedded in a three-dimensional Euclidean space, the physical space has to be three-dimensional and Euclidean became ultimately untenable (ibid., p. 1704). The untenability in question is of course due to the general relativity theory.

  23. The a priori of the life-world, after the phenomenological Epochë, is thought to be made evident as a ‘stratum’ within the universal a priori of transcendental subjectivity.

  24. See Husserl (2001), pp. 4, 7.

  25. These are of course the well-known to any knowledgeable with the fundamentals of phenomenology intentional forms of retention (primary memory) and protention (a-thematic expectation).

  26. The notion of the ‘being there’ may be also thought, in terms of the discussion above, to be relevant with what Levinas described, citing Husserl’s Lessons for a Phenomenology of Inner Time Consciousness, as the ‘where’ time, original impression, and consciousness conjugate, i.e., the original consciousness of time which is yet a null without sensation, more precisely without original impression (Levinas (1974), p. 40).

References

  • Adams R (1979) Primitive thisness and primitive identity. J Philos 76(1):5–26

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bitbol M (1998) L’ Aveuglante Proximité du Réel. Flammarion, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Boge F (2018) Quantum Mech Between Ontol Epistemol. Springer International Pub, Cham, Switzerland

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty A (2017) Scientific Ontology. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • D’Espagnat B (1999) Conceptual foundations of quantum mechanics. Perseus Books, Reading, Mass

    Google Scholar 

  • Dorato M, Morganti M (2013) Grades of individuality. A pluralistic view of identity in quantum mechanics and in the sciences. Philos Studies 163:591–610

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • French S (2002) A Phenomenological Solution to the Measurement Problem? Husserl and the Foundations of Quantum Mechanics. Studies History Philos Modern Phys 33:467–491

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman M (1999) Reconsidering Logical Positivism. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Grib AA (1993) Quantum logical interpretation of quantum mechanics: the role of time. Int J Theoretical Phys 32(12):2389–2400

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths GR (1984) Consistent Histories and the Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. J Stat Phys 36:219–272

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger M (1986) Sein und Zeit, Tübingen: M. Niemeyer Verlag. Engl. transl., Being and Time. A Translation of Sein und Zeit, (1996), Transl. J. Stambaugh, Albany: State University of New York Press

  • Heidegger M (1979) Prolegomena zur Geschichte des Zeitbegriffs, Frankfurt am Main: Vit. Klostermann. Engl. transl.: (1985) History of the Concept of Time, transl. T. Kisiel, Bloomington: Indiana University Press

  • Heidegger M (1999) Ontology - The Hermeneutics of Facticity, engl. transl. van Buren, J., Bloomington: Indiana University Press

  • Husserl E (1973) Zur Theorie der Intersubjektivität, Drit. Teil, hsgb. Kern, I., Hua XV, The Hague: M. Nijhoff

  • Husserl E (1976a), Die Krisis der Europäischen Wissenschaften und die Transzendentale Phanomenologie, Hua VI, hsgb. Walter Biemel, Den Haag: M. Nijhoff. Engl. transl.: (1970), The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology, Transl. D. Carr, Evanston: Northwestern University Press

  • Husserl E (1976b) Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie, Erstes Buch, Hua Band III/I, hsgb. K. Schuhmann, Den Haag: M. Nijhoff. Engl. transl.: (1983), Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy: First Book, Transl. F. Kersten, The Hague: M. Nijhoff

  • Husserl E (1996) Erste Philosophie, (Zweiter Teil), Hua Band VIII, hsgb. R. Boehm, Dordrecht: Kluwer

  • Husserl E (2001) Späte Texte über Zeitkonstitution, Die C-Manuscripte, Hua Materialien Band VIII, hsgb. D. Lohmar, Dordrecht: Springer

  • Isham CJ (1994) Quantum Logic and the Histories Approach to Quantum Theory. J Math Phys 35:2157–2185

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kleene SC (1980) Introduction to Metamathematics. North-Holland Pub, New-York

    Google Scholar 

  • Krause D (2011) The metaphysics of non-individuality. In: Videira AAP, Krause D (eds) Brazilian Studies in Philosophy and History of Science: An Account of Recent Works. Springer, New York, pp 125–145

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Arenhart BJ, Krause D (2014) From primitive identity to the non-individuality of quantum objects. Studies History Philos Modern Phys 46:273–282

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krause D, Arenhard J (2020) Identical particles in quantum mechanics: favouring the received view, forthcoming in Synthese Library

  • Levinas E (1974) Autrement qu’ être ou au-delà de l’ essence. M. Nijhoff, La Haye

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Livadas S (2012) The expressional limits of formal language in the notion of quantum observation. Axiomathes 22:147–169

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Livadas S (2017) What is the nature of mathematical-logical objects? Axiomathes 27(1):79–112

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Livadas S (2018) The transcendental source of logic by way of phenomenology. Axiomathes 28:325–344

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marsonet M (2018) On the Ontology/Epistemology Distinction. In: Wuppuluri S, Antonio Doria F (eds) The Map and the Territory. Exploring the Foundations of Science, Thought and Reality,. Springer, Cham, Switz, pp 15–35

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Moran D (2014) What does Heidegger Mean by the Transcendence of Dasein? Int J Philos Studies 22(4):491–514

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam H (1995) Pragmatism. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine VW (1961) Two dogmas of empiricism. From a Logical Point of View. Harper & Row Pub, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Redhead M, Teller P (1992) Particle labels and the theory of indistinguishable particles in quantum mechanics. Brit J Phil Sci 43:201–218

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach H (1920) Relativitätstheorie und Erkenntnis Apriori. Springer, Berlin

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Röck T (2019) Time for ontology? The role of ontological time in anticipation. Axiomathes 29:33–47

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith Woodruff D (2004) Mind World. Essays in Phenomenology and Ontology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraasen B (1985) Statistical behaviour of indistinguishable particles: problems of interpretation. In: Mittelstaedt P, Stachow EW (eds) Recent developments in quantum logic. BI-Wissenschaftsverlag, Mannheim, pp 161–187

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraasen B (1991) Quantum mechanics: an empiricist view. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Stathis Livadas.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Livadas, S. The Enigma of ‘Being There’: Choosing Between Ontology and Epistemology. Axiomathes 32, 1129–1149 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-021-09572-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-021-09572-5

Keywords

Navigation