Abstract
Viebahn (Pac Philos Q 99:749–762, 2018. https://doi.org/10.1111/papq.1222) has recently argued that several tests for ambiguity, such as the conjunction-reduction test, are not reliable as tests for polysemy, but only as tests for homonymy. I look at the more fine-grained distinction between regular and irregular polysemy and I argue for a more nuanced conclusion: the tests under discussion provide systematic evidence for homonymy and irregular polysemy but need to be used with more care to test for regular polysemy. I put this conclusion at work in the context of the debate over the alleged referential-attributive ambiguity of the definite article. In reply to various criticisms, defenders of the ambiguity view argue that this is a case of polysemy. But opponents object that the dual use of the definite article fails tests for ambiguity. The debate seems to have come to stalemate, unless the relevance of the tests is determined for cases of alleged polysemy. I conclude that the balance of considerations incline towards rejecting the ambiguity thesis.
This is a preview of subscription content,
to check access.Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
Donnellan (1966) includes in his discussion cases of misdescription, in which the speaker has in mind and intends to talk about an object that does not satisfy the DD she uses. The use is still referential, but on Reimer’s (1998) and Devitt’s (2004, 2007) version of Referentialism the object is not the semantic referent of the DD. There are other versions of Referentialism, such as Marti’s (2008), which takes the intended object to be the semantic referent even if it does not satisfy the descriptive content uniquely.
Bach’s and Kripke’s arguments make use of empirical claims, which, although plausible, are not supported by empirical investigation. Thus, Elbourne’s (2013: 109) question is to the point: “And just how many languages has Bach surveyed in establishing his generalization? We are not told.”. In fact, Amaral (2008: 294–295) writes, it is not true that there are no languages that remove the ambiguity of the definite article: Amaral cites evidence concerning Malagasy, an Austronesian language, and Mönchengladbach, a Low Franconian dialect spoken in the northwest of Germany, where there are two definite articles, corresponding to the two uses.
Actually, Kripke (1977) goes a long a way towards acknowledging this point (although he does not explicitly mention the distinction between homonymy and polysemy): “The more we can explain relations among senses, and the more “natural” and “inevitable” the relationship, the more we will expect the different senses to be preserved in a wide variety of other languages” (1977: 275). However, Kripke does not formulate the polysemy hypothesis.
See the discussion in Sennet (2015: §4) concerning this point.
Sennet also notes that “the conjunction reduction test assumes that the following cannot serve as legitimate implicature cancellation: “Jim and Steve own bats, but Jim’s has wings and Steve’s is made of wood”” (Sennet 2002: 93).
One famous example of zeugma is Chomsky’s (1957) ‘Colorless green ideas sleep furiously’. The sentence is grammatically correct but nonsensical.
Although Sennet (2002) invokes the “conjunction and reduction test”, he in fact uses the version of the test designed for argument-taking expressions, i.e. “the argument coordination test”.
Sennet (2002: 87) and Koralus (2013: 283) both argue that the DD ‘the prince and queen’ could not be used attributively with respect to the prince. However, I do not find their arguments compelling. According to Sennet (2002: 87), an attributive use of ‘the prince’ “requires that there is a change of meaning” as between the first use of ‘the prince’ in (11), where it is used referentially, and the second use in (13). Sennet comments: “To posit any such inscrutable change of meaning is at best a desperate move. Desperate moves are a sign of a bad view” (2002: 87). But this argument is problematic: even if the use in (11) is referential and in (13) is attributive this does not mean there is a change in the meaning of the DD between the two sentences, given that at this point of the argument it cannot be assumed that DDs have two meanings. At this point we are only checking whether the cross interpretation is available. If it is, this is a reason to think it does not have two meanings. In turn, Koralus (2013: 283), who also discusses the example, takes ‘the prince’, when used referentially in (11), to be a misdescription of some individual in the palace that looked like a prince without being one, while there is no actual price. Consequently, he argues that if we were to interpret both ‘the prince’ and ‘<the> queen’ attributively, then (13) would turn out false, contrary to intuition. But if ‘the prince’ is a misdescription and there is no unique prince, then (13) is semantically false, according to both Russellians and most Referentialists (see also footnote 1). Cases of misdescriptions introduce further unnecessary complications, so it is better to leave them out of the discussion.
See the discusses in Gillon (2004) for the technical details.
Koralus (2013: 283) applies this test to DDs, but his example is rather cumbersome and involves intensional contexts, which introduce further complications (such as scope ambiguities) that I wish to avoid here.
Viebahn comment that the lack of zeugmaticity in (23) to (25) “presumably has to do with the fact that these cases involve polysemous target expressions and only subtle differences in meaning—differences that are hard to detect without careful reflection” (2018: 6). But, this cannot be the whole explanation, given the presence of zeugma in sentences (26) and (28). I come back to this point in Sect. 4.
As Vicente (2015: 58) writes, “In these cases (i.e. regular polysemy), non-zeugmatic co-predication is typically possible, as in ‘the book is heavy but very entertaining’”.
I leave out a discussion of the referential-attributive uses of pronouns and proper names for the reason that they are not determiner phrases.
See also the discussion of this proposal in Elbourne (2013: 110–112).
The truth-conditions resulting from the Gödelian completion are slightly different from those the Referentialist postulates in that the latter takes the semantic content to be Ga, and the presupposition to be that there is a unique x such that Fx and x = a. See Reimer (1998: 93) and Devitt (2004: 282).
See also Ruhl (1989: 97) for a discussion of the related distinction between semantics and pragmatic metonymy.
References
Amaral FS (2008) Definite descriptions are ambiguous. Analysis 68(300):288–297
Apresjan JUD (1974) Regular polysemy. Linguistics Interdiscip J Lang Sci 12(142):5–32
Asher N (2011) Lexical meaning in context: a web of words. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
Bach K (1998) Ambiguity. In: Routledge encyclopedia of philosophy. http://online.sfsu.edu/~kbach/ambguity.html. Cited 1 Nov 2018
Bach K (2004a) Descriptions: points of reference. In: Reimer M, Bezuidenhout A (eds) Descriptions and beyond. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 189–229
Bach K (2004b) On referring and not referring. In: Gundel Jeanette K, Hedberg Nancy (eds) Reference: interdisciplinary perspectives. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 13–58
Bach K (2007) Referentially used descriptions: a reply to Devitt. Eur J Anal Philos 3(2):33–48
Bezuidenhout A (1997) Pragmatics, semantic undetermination and the referential/attributive distinction. Mind 106(423):375–409
Bontly TD (2005) Modified occam’s razor: parsimony, pragmatics, and the acquisition of word meaning. Mind Lang 20(3):288–312
Brocher A, Foraker S, Koenig J-P (2016) Processing of irregular polysemes in sentence reading. J Exp Psychol Learn Mem Cogn 42(11):1798–1813
Chastain C (1975) Reference and context. In: Gunderson Keith (ed) Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science: language mind and knowledge, vol 7. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, pp 194–269
Chomsky N (1957) Syntactic structures. Mouton, Berlin
Cruse DA (1986) Lexical semantics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
Dever J (2001) Complex demonstratives. Linguist Philos 24(3):271–330
Devitt M (1981) Donnellan’s distinction. Midwest Stud Philos 6(1):511–526
Devitt M (2004) The case for referential descriptions. In: Reimer M, Bezuidenhout A (eds) Descriptions and beyond. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Devitt M (2007) Referential descriptions and conversational implicatures. Eur J Anal Philos 3(2):7–32
Devitt M (2013) What makes a property “semantic”? In: Capone A, Franco LP, Carapezza M (eds) Perspectives on pragmatics and philosophy. Springer, New York, pp 87–112
Donnellan KS (1966) Reference and definite descriptions. Philos Rev 75(3):281–304
Donnellan KS (1978) Speaker reference, descriptions, and anaphora. In: Cole P (ed) Syntax and semantics 9: pragmatics. Academic Press, New York, pp 47–68
Eddington CM, Tokowicz M (2015) How meaning similarity influences ambiguous word processing. Psychon Bull Rev 22:13–37
Elbourne P (2013) Definite descriptions. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Fodor JD, Sag IA (1982) Referential and quantificational indefinites. Linguist Philos 5(3):355–398
Geeraerts D (1993) Vagueness’s puzzles, polysemy’s vagaries. Cogn Linguist 4(3):223–272
Georgi G (2012) Reference and ambiguity in complex demonstratives. In: Kabasenche WP, O’Rourke M, Slater MH (eds) Reference and referring. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 357–384
Gillon BS (2004) Ambiguity, indeterminacy, deixis, and vagueness: evidence and theory. In: Davis S, Gillon BS (eds) Semantics: a reader. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 157–190
Gomez-Torrente M (2015) Quantifiers and referential use. In: Torza A (ed) Quantifiers, quantifiers, and quantifiers: themes in logic, metaphysics, and language. Springer, New York, pp 97–124
Grice PH (1969) Vacuous Names. In: Davidson D, Hintikka J (eds) Words and objections. Reidel, Dordrecht, pp 118–145
Jackendoff R (2002) Foundations of language: brain, meaning, grammar, evolution. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Kamp H, Reyle U (1993) From discourse to logic: introduction to model-theoretic semantics of natural language, formal logic and discourse representation theory. Kluwer, Dordrecht
Kaplan D (1977) Demonstrative. In: Almog J et al (eds) Themes from Kaplan. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 481–563
King JC (1988) Are indefinite descriptions ambiguous? Philos Stud 53:417–440
King JC (2001) Complex demonstratives: a quantificational account. MIT Press, Cambridge
Koralus P (2013) Descriptions, ambiguity, and representationalist theories of interpretation. Philos Stud 162(2):275–290
Kripke S (1977) Speaker’s reference and semantic reference. Midwest Stud Philos 2:255–276
Ludlow P, Neale S (1991) Indefinite descriptions: in defense of Russell. Linguist Philos 14:171–202
Marti G (2008) Direct reference and definite descriptions. Dialectica 62(1):43–57
Mckinsey M (1979) The ambiguity of definite descriptions. Theoria 45(2):78–89
Neale S (1990) Descriptions. MIT Press, Cambridge
Neale S (2004) This, that, and the other. In: Reimer M, Bezuidenhout A (eds) Descriptions and beyond. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Nowak E (2014) Demonstratives without rigidity or ambiguity. Linguist Philos 37(5):409–436
Peacocke C (1975) Proper names, reference and rigid designation. In: Blackburn S (ed) Meaning, reference and necessity. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
Pethö G (2007) On irregular polysemy. In: Rakova M, Pethö G, Rákosi C (eds) The cognitive basis of polysemy: new sources of evidence for theories of word meaning. Peter Lang, Bern
Pustejovsky J (1995) The generative lexicon. MIT Press, Cambridge
Rabagliati H, Snedeker J (2013) The truth about chickens and bats: ambiguity avoidance distinguishes types of polysemy. Psychol Sci 24(7):1354–1360
Ravin Y, Leacock C (2000) Polysemy: theoretical and computational approaches. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Reimer M (1992) Incomplete descriptions. Erkenntnis 37(3):347–363
Reimer M (1998) Donnellan’s distinction/Kripke’s test. Analysis 58:89–100
Rouchota V (1992) On the referential/attributive distinction. Lingua 87:137–167
Rouchota V (1994) On indefinite descriptions. J Linguist 30(2):441–475
Ruhl C (1989) On monosemy—a study in linguistic semantics. State University of New York Press, Albany
Sainsbury RM (1979) Russell. Routledge, London
Schoubye AJ (2012) Against the argument from convention. Linguist Philos 35(6):515–532
Sennet A (2002) An ambiguity test for definite descriptions. Philos Stud 111(1):81–95
Sennet A (2015) Ambiguity. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2015/entries/ambiguity. Cited 1 Nov 2018
Sperber D, Wilson D (1995) Relevance. Wiley, New York
Vicente A (2015) The green leaves and the expert: polysemy and truth-conditional variability. Lingua 157:54–65
Vicente A, Falkum IL (2017) Polysemy. In: Oxford research encyclopedia of linguistics. Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acrefore/9780199384655.013.325
Viebahn E (2018) Ambiguity and zeugma. Pac Philos Q 99:749–762. https://doi.org/10.1111/papq.12229
Wettstein HK (1981) Demonstrative reference and definite descriptions. Philos Stud 40(2):241–257
Zacharska B (2010) Definite descriptions: semantic or pragmatic polysemy? Univ Coll Lond Work Pap Linguist 22:56–63
Zwicky AM, Sadock MS (1975) Ambiguity tests and how to fail them. In: Kimball JP (ed) Syntax and semantics, vol 4. Academic Press, New York, pp 1–36
Acknowledgements
Funding was provided by Ministerio de Economía, Industria y Competitividad, Gobierno de España (ES) (Grant No. FFI2016-80636-P).
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Additional information
Publisher's Note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Moldovan, A. Descriptions and Tests for Polysemy. Axiomathes 31, 229–249 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-019-09445-y
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-019-09445-y