Skip to main content
Log in

Strategy for Animalism

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Axiomathes Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The central argument for animalism is the thinking animal problem (TAP): if you are not an animal, there are two thinkers within the region you occupy, i.e., you and your animal body. This is absurd. So you are an animal. The main objection to this argument is the thinking brain problem (TBP): animalism faces a problem that is structurally analogous to TAP. Specifically, if animalism is true, you and your brain both think. This is absurd. So animalism is false. The purpose of this paper is to propose strategies animalists can endorse to solve TBP. I first show that animalists can solve TBP by arguing that it is not sound. This solution to TBP raises questions about personal identity over time and the mereological relation between the person and the brain. I argue that animalists can answer the personal identity question by endorsing non-biological persistence conditions as well as biological ones. For the mereological question, I first show that animalism is incompatible with four-dimensionalism and eliminativism. I then argue that animalists should endorse the dominant sortal account to answer the mereological question.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For this line of reasoning, see Carter (1988), Mackie (1999a), Merricks (2001, pp. 85–86), Olson (1997, pp. 106–107; 2007, pp. 35–39), Snowdon (1990), and van Inwagen (1990, p. 290, n. 45).

  2. Olson (2007, pp. 215–219) considers a more general version of the thinking brain problem, according to which every part of the person containing a brain (e.g., upper halves, left-hand complements) is a candidate for being a thinker. He calls this the ‘thinking parts problem.’ However, it is controversial whether there are such super-cellular parts (cf. Burke 2003). Stipulation: in this paper, I shall assume that there are no super-cellular parts of a person. I rather focus on TBP because most of us (except for eliminativists, as we shall see in Sect. 4) believe that there are brains.

  3. Some might want to develop a similar solution appealing to Thomasson’s idea about ‘analytic entailment’ (Thomasson 2007). They might say that the claim about the person “analytically entails” (this is Thomasson’s term) the claim about the brain, and vice versa. In other words, the truth of the claim about the person guarantees the truth of the claim about the brain. On this solution, ‘I think’ analytically entails ‘My brain thinks.’ Because there is “no rivalry” between the two claims, a competent speaker can infer one from the other. In fact, our imagined objectors might say that there is only one thinker inside my skin because they would count the number of thinkers by analytic entailment. However, if ‘I think’ entails ‘My brain thinks,’ we need to know why. The analytic entailment view simply says that a competent person uses language in a certain way to count entities. But it does not explain why we should use language in that way, even though the person and her brain are two distinct entities. So I believe the analytic entailment view is a linguistic solution and not an ontological one (cf. Baker, “Amie Thomasson on Ordinary Objects”). After all, TBP is not about how we use language to refer to a thinker. It is rather a serious ontological problem. It is about whether there is a thinker that is psychologically indistinguishable from me. I also reject counting the number of thinkers by analytic entailment for similar reasons I shall reject the present solution to TBP in the text.

  4. Sutton (2014) attempts to solve TAP by arguing that it is not valid: the animal’s thinking is not additive to the person’s thinking so there is no multiplication of thinkers, even though the person is not identical with the animal. But if my argument in this paper is correct, her solution to TAP fails.

  5. For an objection to Blatti’s ‘animal ancestors argument,’ see Gillett (2013). After all, what TAP implies is that each of us is an animal in the sense of being identical with one (e.g., the only thinker within the region a person occupies). I believe animalists would accept this implication.

  6. By using this reasoning, Lowe (2001) argues that animalists should abandon animalism to solve TBP. For this argument, he, of course, assumes that (1) and (2) are true. Campbell and McMahan (2010) and Parfit (2012) would also say (3) is false because they believe the person is her thinking part, such as a brain or cerebrum. This ‘embodied person view’ is obviously incompatible with animalism.

  7. It seems that Parfit denies the existence of persons, but he actually does not endorse eliminativism (nihilism) about persons (Parfit 1984, p. 341).

  8. For recent discussions of various versions of animalism, see Bailey (2015) and Thornton (2016).

  9. Johnston (2007) develops the ‘remnant person problem,’ which is analogous to the BIV case. He argues that if animalism is true, then you cannot be the detached brain (or cerebrum) and this leads to a dilemma: either the remnant person has been with the person until its detachment, or suddenly comes into existence. Neither option is plausible. So, he concludes, animalism is false. But Johnston’s argument attacks only one version of animalism, the view that we as animals have entirely biological persistence conditions. Animalists can identify you with the remnant person and argue that biological continuity is not necessary for personal identity. With this strategy, animalists can also argue that Johnston’s own psychological continuity theory faces a dilemma analogous to the remnant person problem (Johnston 1987). Suppose that you lapse into a persistent vegetative state. If psychological continuity is necessary for you to persist, you are not the living organism in this state. This leads to two options: either it has been with you until you lose mental states, or comes into existence when you perish. Neither option is plausible. So it is not the case that psychological continuity is necessary for personal identity. This obviously goes against Johnston’s psychological criterion of personal identity.

  10. Constitutionalists, such as Baker (2000), Johnston (1987), Noonan (1998), and Shoemaker (2008), do not find this problematic. But animalism is incompatible with constitutionalism as animalists attack it by appeal to TAP: constitutionalism leads to the multiplication of thinkers.

  11. I believe animalists do not want to consider other theories, such as constitutionalism (for the reason discussed in the text and in footnote 10) and mereological essentialism (animalists typically say we can persist over time by gaining or losing parts).

  12. So these eliminativists would disagree with Unger (1979). As I said in Sect. 2, the goal of this paper is to develop the animalist solution to TBP. So I assume that eliminativism about persons is incompatible with animalism.

  13. Van Inwagen says that if atoms arranged brainwise in one’s head are detached and kept functioning in a vat, a life flows into the ‘brain’ in a vat. As a result, atoms arranged brainwise in a vat compose an object. He thinks this object is not a brain but the original human animal that is whittled down to brain size. So, on his view, the brain still does not exist in a vat, as well as in one’s head. See van Inwagen (1990, pp. 172–173).

  14. For the ‘remnant person problem,’ see footnote 9.

  15. For a more detailed discussion on the incompatibility of animalism and eliminativism, see Lim (2017).

  16. For the history of this puzzle, see Rea (1997, xviii). Recall that my argument in this paper focuses on the thinking brain problem only. So I use the Tib–Tibble case to make an analogy to that, not its more general version, i.e., the thinking parts problem. See footnote 2 for my stipulation about super-cellular parts of a person.

  17. According to Rea, “an object satisfies a sortal in the classificatory way just in case that sortal gives the metaphysically best answer to the “What is it?” question for that object, and an object satisfies a sortal in the nominal way just in case the object exemplifies the distinctive qualitative features of those things that satisfy the sortal in the classificatory way” (Rea 2000, p. 172). If this is correct, the BIV is a person in the classificatory sense and a brain in the nominal sense.

References

  • Ayers M (1991) Locke, vol 2. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Bailey A (2015) Animalism. Philos Compass 10:867–883

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baker LR (unpublished) Amie Thomasson on ordinary objects. http://people.umass.edu/~lrb/files/bak08amiM.pdf. Accessed 20 Apr 2018

  • Baker LR (2000) Persons and bodies: a constitution view. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Belshaw C (2011) Animals, identity, and persistence. Australas J Philos 89:401–419

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blatti S (2012) A new argument for animalism. Analysis 72:685–690

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burke M (1994) Preserving the principle of one object to a place: a novel account of the relations among objects, sorts, sortals, and persistence conditions. Philos Phenomenol Res 54:591–624

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burke M (2003) Is my head a person? In: Petrus K (ed) On human persons. Ontos Verlag, Frankfurt, pp 107–125

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell T, McMahan J (2010) Animalism and the varieties of conjoined twinning. Theor Med Bioeth 31:285–301

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carter WR (1988) Our bodies, our selves. Australas J Philos 66:308–319

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman F (1991) Confrontations with the reaper. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillett C (2013) What you are and the evolution of organs, souls, and superorganisms: a reply to Blatti. Analysis 73:271–279

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heller M (1990) The ontology of physical objects: four dimensional hunks of matter. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Horgan T (1993) On what there isn’t. Philos Phenomenol Res 53:693–700

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnston M (1987) Human beings. J Philos 84:59–83

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnston M (2007) Human beings revisited: my body is not an animal. In: Zimmerman D (ed) Oxford studies in metaphysics, vol 3. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 33–74

    Google Scholar 

  • Langford S (2014) On what we are and how we persist. Pac Philos Q 95:356–371

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis D (1983) Survival and identity. In: Lewis D (ed) Philosophical papers, vol 1. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 55–72

    Google Scholar 

  • Lim J (2011) Bodies and persons: an essay on animalism. Doctoral Dissertation, University of Virginia

  • Lim J (2017) The incompatibility of animalism and eliminativism. Philos Forum 48:395–407

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lowe EJ (2000) An introduction to the philosophy of mind. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lowe EJ (2001) Identity, composition, and the simplicity of the self. In: Corcoran K (ed) Soul, body, and survival. Cornell University Press, Ithaca, pp 139–158

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackie D (1999a) Animalism versus lockeanism: no contest. Philos Q 49:369–376

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mackie D (1999b) Personal identity and dead people. Philos Stud 95:219–242

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell J (1997) Reductionism and the first person. In: Dancy J (ed) Reading parfit. Blackwell, Oxford, pp 230–250

    Google Scholar 

  • Merricks T (1998) There are no criteria of identity over time. Noûs 32:106–124

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merricks T (2001) Objects and persons. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Noonan H (1998) Animalism versus lockeanism: a current controversy. Philos Q 48:302–318

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olson E (1997) The human animal. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Olson E (2007) What are we?. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit D (1984) Reasons and persons. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit D (2012) We are not human beings. Philosophy 87:5–28

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rea M (1997) Material constitution: a reader. Rowman & Littlefield, Lanham

    Google Scholar 

  • Rea M (2000) Constitution and kind membership. Philos Stud 97:169–193

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sharpe K (2015) Animalism and person essentialism. Metaphysica 16:53–72

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker S (2008) Persons, animals, and identity. Synthese 162:313–324

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sider T (2001) Four-dimensionalism: an ontology of persistence and time. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Snowdon P (1990) Persons, animals, and ourselves. In: Gill C (ed) The person and the human animal. Clarendon, Oxford, pp 83–107

    Google Scholar 

  • Snowdon P (2014) Animals, persons, ourselves. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stone J (2005) Why there are still no people. Philos Phenomenol Res 70:174–192

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sutton C (2014) The supervenience solution to the too-many-thinkers problem. Philos Q 64:619–639

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomasson A (2007) Ordinary objects. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Thornton A (2016) Varieties of animalism. Philos Compass 11:515–526

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Unger P (1979) I do not exist. In: Macdonald GF (ed) Perception and identity. MacMillan, London, pp 235–251

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Van Inwagen P (1990) Material beings. Cornell University Press, Ithaca

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiggins D (1996) Reply to Paul Snowdon. In: Lovibond S, Williams SG (eds) Essays for David Wiggins. Blackwell, Oxford, pp 244–248

    Google Scholar 

  • Zimmerman D (2003) Material people. In: Loux M, Zimmerman D (eds) The Oxford handbook of metaphysics. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 492–526

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Earlier versions of this paper have been presented at the Midsouth Philosophy Conference and the North Carolina Philosophical Society meeting.  I am grateful to the audiences on those occasions for insightful questions and comments.  I am also grateful to two anonymous referees, Bill Faw, and Jeremy Skrzypek for very helpful comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Joungbin Lim.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Lim, J. Strategy for Animalism. Axiomathes 28, 419–433 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-018-9378-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-018-9378-2

Keywords

Navigation