Axiomathes

, Volume 24, Issue 3, pp 291–312 | Cite as

A Process Ontology

Original Paper

Abstract

The paper assumes that to be of practical interest process must be understood as physical action that takes place in the world rather than being an idea in the mind. It argues that if an ontology of process is to accommodate actuality, it must be represented in terms of relative probabilities. Folk physics cannot accommodate this, and so the paper appeals to scientific culture because it is an emergent knowledge of the world derived from action in it. Process is represented as a contradictory probability distribution that does not depend on a spatio-temporal frame. An actuality is a probability density that grounds the values of probabilities to constitute their distributions. Because probability is a conserved value, probability distributions are subject to the constraint of symmetry and must be zero-sum. An actuality is locked-in by other actualities to become a zero-sum symmetry of probability values. It is shown that the locking-in of actualities constructs spatio-temporal locality, lends actualities specificity, and makes them a contradiction. Localization is the basis for understanding empirical observation. Because becoming depends on its construction of being, processes exist as trajectories. The historical trajectories of evolution and revolution as well as the non-historical trajectory of strong emergence are how processes are observed to exist.

Keywords

Process Probability Contradiction Emergence Historical science 

References

  1. Anderson PW (1972) More is different: broken symmetry and the nature of the hierarchical structure of science. Science N.S. 177(4047):393–396Google Scholar
  2. Archer MS (1982) Morphogenesis versus structuration: on combining structure and action. Br J Sociol 33(4):455–483CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Audi P (2012) A clarification and defense of the notion of grounding (preprint). In: Correia F, Schnieder B (eds) Grounding and explanation. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. URL:http://www.paulaudi.net/Audi_Clarification_of_Grounding.pdf
  4. Baddeley A (2000) Short-term and working memory. In: Tulving E, FIM Craik (eds) The Oxford handbook of memory, Chap. 5. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 77–92Google Scholar
  5. Bambach CR (1995) Heidegger, Dilthey, and the crisis of historicism. Cornell University Press, IthacaGoogle Scholar
  6. Bergson H (1998) Creative evolution. Dover, MineolaGoogle Scholar
  7. Bohm D (1980) Wholeness and the implicate order. Routledge and Kegan Paul, LondonGoogle Scholar
  8. Bower B (1986) Who’s the boss? Sci News 129(17):266–267CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Bruner J (1990) Acts of meaning. Harvard University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  10. Butterfield J (2010) Against Pointillisme: a call to arms (preprint). In: Dieks D et al (ed) Explanation, prediction and confirmation: new trends and old ones reconsidered. Springer, Berlin. URL:http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/5550/1/APCA1.pdf
  11. Cat J (2006) Fuzzy empiricism and fuzzy-set causality: what is all the fuzz about? Philos Sci 73(1):26–41CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Ceusters W (2011) Biomedical Ontologies: Toward Sound Debate. Tech. rep. URL:http://www.referent-tracking.com/RTU/sendfile/?file=CeustersCommentaryOnMaojoLongVersion.pdf
  13. Chalmers DJ (2006) Strong and weak emergence (preprint). In: Clayton P, Davies P (eds) The re-emergence of emergence: the emergentist hypothesis from science to religion, Chap. 11. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 244–256. URL:http://consc.net/papers/emergence.pdf
  14. Churchland PM (1988) Perceptual plasticity and theoretical neutrality: a reply to Jerry Fodor. Philos Sci 55(2):167–187CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Churchland PM (2005) Functionalism at forty: a critical retrospective. J Philos 102(1):33–50Google Scholar
  16. Cleland CE (2002) Methodological and epistemic differences between historical science and experimental science. Philos Sci 69(3):447–451CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Cohen-Cory S (2002) The developing synapse: construction and modulation of synaptic structures and circuits. Science N.S. 298(5594):770–776Google Scholar
  18. Demerath NJ (1996) Who now debates functionalism? From ‘system, change and conflict’ to ′culture, choice, and praxis’. Sociol Forum 11(2):333–345CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Demos R (1926) Possibility and becoming. J Philos 23(9):234–240CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Dries M (2008) Towards adualism: becoming and nihilism in Nietzsche’s philosophy. In: Dries M (ed) Nietzsche on time and history. Walter de Gruyter, Berlin, pp 113–145CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Engels F (1940) Dialectics of nature. International Publishers, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  22. Feyerabend PK (1966) Dialectical materialism and the quantum theory. Slav Rev 25(3):414–417CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Fiske MA (1965) Paradisus Homo Amicus. Speculum 40(3):436–459CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Fitelson B, Hájek A, Hall N (2013) Probability (preprint). In: Pfeiffer J, Rausch S, Sarkar S (ed) The Routledge encyclopedia of philosophy of science. Routledge, New York. http://philosophyfaculty.ucsd.edu/faculty/ccallender/Papers/Probability.pdf
  25. Goldstein J (1999) Emergence as a construct: history and issues. Emergence Complex Organ 1(1):49–72Google Scholar
  26. Guarino N, Oberle D, Staab S (2009) What is an ontology ? In: Handbook on ontologies. Springer, Berlin, pp 1–17Google Scholar
  27. Hauser MD, Chomsky N, Fitch WT (2002) The faculty of language: what is it, who has it, and how did it evolve? Science N.S. 298(5598):1569–1579Google Scholar
  28. Hellie B (2008) Janann Ismael’s ‘probability and physics’ (unpublished). URL:http://individual.utoronto.ca/benj/jenann.pdf
  29. Hershock PD (1996) Liberating intimacy: enlightenment and social virtuosity in Ch’an buddhism. State University of New York Press, AlbanyGoogle Scholar
  30. Hovda P, Cross T (2013) Grounding relation(s): introduction. Essays Philos 14(1):1–6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Kimmelman M (2013) Who rules the street in Cairo? The residents who build it. The New York TimesGoogle Scholar
  32. Koyré A (1968) Metaphysics and measurement: essays in scientific revolution. Chapman and Hall, LondonGoogle Scholar
  33. Krips H (1989) Propensity interpretation for quantum probabilities. Philos Q 39(156):308–333CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Krüger L (1986) Probability as a theoretical concept in physics. In: Proceedings of the biennial meeting of the philosophy of science association, pp 273–287Google Scholar
  35. Martin P (2007) Probability as a physical motive. Entropy 9:42–57CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Mellor DH (2005) Probability: a philosophical introduction. Routledge, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  37. Motterlini M (ed) (2000) For and against method: including Lakatos’s lectures on scientific method and the Lakatos-Feyerabend correspondence. University of Chicago Press, ChicagoGoogle Scholar
  38. Nāgārjuna (1987) Nāgārjuna’s “seventy stanzas": a buddhist psychology of emptiness. In: Komito DR (ed) Snow Lion Publications, IthacaGoogle Scholar
  39. Norton JD (2003) Causation as folk science. Philos Impr 3(4):1–22Google Scholar
  40. Norton JD (2007) Probability disassembled. Br J Philos Sci 58(2):141–171CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Norton JD (2009) Is there an independent principle of causality in physics? Br J Philos Sci 60(3):475–486CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Pickering A (1986) Against correspondence: a constructivist view of experiment and the real. In: Proceedings of the biennial meeting of the philosophy of science association, pp 196–206Google Scholar
  43. Preston B (1998) Cognition and tool use. Mind Lang 13(4):513–547Google Scholar
  44. Rescher N (2000) Process philosophy: a survey of basic issues. University of Pittsburgh Press, PittsburghGoogle Scholar
  45. Schaffer J (2009) On what grounds what. In: Chalmers D, Manley D, Wasserman R (eds) Metametaphysics, Chap. 12. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 357–383Google Scholar
  46. Schultz W et al (2008) Explicit neural signals reflecting reward uncertainty. Philos Trans Biol Sci 363(1511):3801–3811CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Sellars W (1963) Science, perception and reality. Humanities Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  48. Shadmehr R, Smith MA, Krakauer JW (2010) Error correction, sensory prediction, and adaptation in motor control. Annu Rev Neurosci 33:89–108CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. Simon HA (1962) The architecture of complexity. Proc Am Philos Soc 106(6):467–482Google Scholar
  50. Simone A (2008) Some reflections on making popular culture in Urban Africa. Afr Stud Rev 51(3):75–89CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Smith B (2008b) Ontology (science). In: Proceeding of the 2008 conference on formal ontology in information systems: proceedings of the fifth international conference (FOIS 2008) frontiers in artificial intelligence and applications, vol 183, pp 21–35Google Scholar
  52. Stich S (1992) What is a theory of mental representation? Mind N.S. 101(402):243–261Google Scholar
  53. Timpanaro S (1975) On materialism. New Left Books, LondonGoogle Scholar
  54. Vervoort L (2013) Bell’s theorem: two neglected solutions (preprint). Found Phys 1–23. URL:arxiv.org/pdf/1203.6587Google Scholar
  55. Weatherson B (2002) Intrinsic vs. extrinsic properties. In: Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. URL:http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/intrinsic-extrinsic/
  56. White PA (1999) Toward a causal realist account of causal understanding. Am J Psychol 112(4):605–642CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  57. Whyte LL (1950) The next development in man. Mentor-New American Library, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  58. Wilson JM (2002) Causal powers, forces, and superdupervenience. Grazer Philosophische Studien 63:53–78Google Scholar
  59. Wilson JM (2013) No work for a theory of grounding (manuscript). UiO Colloquium. URL:http://philpapers.org/rec/WILTMO-16
  60. Wong HY (2006) Emergents from fusion. Philos Sci 73(3):345–367CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  61. Worrall J (1982) Scientific realism and scientific change. Philos Q 32(128):201–231CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  62. Zimmer C (2008) How smart is the octopus? Slate MagazineGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Professor EmeritusCentral Connecticut State UniversityNew BritainUSA

Personalised recommendations