Skip to main content
Log in

A formalization of the Protagoras court paradox in a temporal logic of epistemic and normative reasons

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Artificial Intelligence and Law Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We combine linear temporal logic (with both past and future modalities) with a deontic version of justification logic to provide a framework for reasoning about time and epistemic and normative reasons. In addition to temporal modalities, the resulting logic contains two kinds of justification assertions: epistemic justification assertions and deontic justification assertions. The former presents justification for the agent’s knowledge and the latter gives reasons for why a proposition is obligatory. We present two kinds of semantics for the logic: one based on Fitting models and the other based on neighborhood models. The use of neighborhood semantics enables us to define the dual of deontic justification assertions properly, which corresponds to a notion of permission in deontic logic. We then establish the soundness and completeness of an axiom system of the logic with respect to these semantics. Further, we formalize the Protagoras versus Euathlus paradox in this logic and present a precise analysis of the paradox, and also briefly discuss Leibniz’s solution.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. \({\,{\mathcal {O}}}_i \varphi \) can be alternatively read “it is obligatory for the agent i to do \(\varphi \).” In fact, in the context of deontic logic, there is a distinction between two kinds of ought: ought-to-do (the agent ought to do an action) and ought-to-be (it ought to be the case that). The former represents a normative ought while the latter represents an ideal ought. It is common to express the normative ought in terms of the ideal ought as follows: the agent ought to do \(\varphi \) iff it ought to be the case that the agent does \(\varphi \) (cf. e.g. Hansson 2013a, p. 455). While this distinction might be significant, in the present paper we shall frequently not make a distinction between these two meanings of “ought” and we will use them interchangeably.

  2. In fact, by accepting the view that strong justified permission is distinct from permission in the weak sense of not being forbidden, we reject what is called by Moore “the reflex thesis” according to which “all legal norms of permission are merely assertions of the absence (non-existence, negation, or failure) of norms of prohibition.” (cf. Moore 1973).

  3. In the rest of the paper, we will not explicitly specify the set of agents, justification variables, and atomic propositions, whenever it is clear from the context.

  4. A constant specification \(\textsf {CS}\) for \(\textsf {JTO}\) is axiomatically appropriate provided, for every axiom instance \(\varphi \) of \(\textsf {JTO}\) and for every \(i \in \textsf {Ag}\), there are constants cd such that \(\left[ c\right] \!_i \varphi , \left[ d\right] ^{\,O}_i\! \varphi \in \textsf {CS}\), and in addition \(\textsf {CS}\) is upward closed: if \(\left[ c_{j_n}\right] \!_{i_n}\ldots \left[ c_{j_1}\right] \!_{i_1} \varphi \in \textsf {CS}\) (or \(\left[ c_{j_n}\right] ^{\,O}_{i_n}\! \ldots \left[ c_{j_1}\right] ^{\,O}_{i_1}\! \varphi \in \textsf {CS}\)), then for every \(i \in \textsf {Ag}\) there is a constant c such that \(\left[ c\right] \!_i \left[ c_{j_n}\right] \!_{i_n}\ldots \left[ c_{j_1}\right] \!_{i_1} \varphi \in \textsf {CS}\) (or \(\left[ c\right] ^{\,O}_i\! \left[ c_{j_n}\right] ^{\,O}_{i_n}\! \ldots \left[ c_{j_1}\right] ^{\,O}_{i_1}\! \varphi \in \textsf {CS}\)).

  5. See Sobel (1987) for a discussion on “first win a case” condition and “win first case” condition.

  6. If it is stipulated in the contract that Euathlus himself should plead before jurors and win his court-case, then one trivial way for Euathlus to avoid paying the fee is that he would hire a lawyer to plead before jurors. Because, if he wins with a lawyer, his victory would be non-paradoxical, and if he loses with a lawyer, he would not yet have won his first case.

  7. We suppose here that cases are numbered according to their commencement dates, rather than their conclusion dates. In addition, the court resolves the case by a yea or nay verdict, and not by dismissal or suspension. Otherwise, we need a four-valued logic for formalization. In fact, in an ancient rendition of the case (e.g. Aulus Gellius, The Attic Nights, (f.c. 150 A.D.)), the court decides to postpone its decision (deferral), and in another version (e.g. Hermogenes) the case is dismissed as not really fitting a courtroom. For more details see Jankowski (2015).

  8. In fact, in the deontic justification logic presented in Faroldi et al. (2022), the connecting principle con (see Sect. 2) implies that .

  9. See Goossens (1977, p. 72) for a discussion on “the content of the ruling” and “the ruling as an in-the-world event.”

  10. Euathlus might then sue Protagoras for malicious prosecution and ask compensation.

References

  • Aqvis L (1967) Good samaritans, contrary-to-duty imperatives, and epistemic obligations. Nous 1:361–379. https://doi.org/10.2307/2214624

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aqvist L (1995) The Protagoras case: an exercise in elementary logic for lawyers. In: Bjarup J, Blegvad M (eds) Time, Law, and Society, ARSP-Beiheft 64, pp 73–84. Franz Steiner Verlag Stuttgart

  • Artemov S (1995) Operational modal logic. Technical Report MSI 95–29, Cornell University

  • Artemov S (2001) Explicit provability and constructive semantics. Bull Symb Log 7:1–36

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Artemov S (2008) The logic of justification. The Review of Symbolic Logic 1:477–513. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1755020308090060

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Artemov S, Fitting M (2019) Justification logic: reasoning with reasons. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108348034

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Artemov S, Fitting M (2021) Justification logic. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2012/entries/logic-justification/

  • Bucheli S (2015) Some notes on temporal justification logic. CoRR arXiv:1510.07247

  • Bucheli S, Kuznets R, Studer T (2011) Justifications for common knowledge. J Appl Non-Class Log 21:35–60. https://doi.org/10.3166/JANCL.21.35-60

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Bucheli S, Ghari M, Studer T (2017) Temporal justification logic. In: Ghosh S, Ramanujam R (eds) Electronic Proceedings in Theoretical Computer Science 243:59–74. https://doi.org/10.4204/EPTCS.243.5

  • Carneiro G (2019) The logic of normative justification. Felsefe Arkivi 51:79–115

    Google Scholar 

  • Fagin R, Halpern JY, Moses Y, Vardi MY (1995) Reasoning about knowledge. MIT Press, Cambridge

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Faroldi FLG, Protopopescu T (2019) A hyperintensional logical framework for deontic reasons. Log J IGPL 27:411–433. https://doi.org/10.1093/jigpal/jzz012

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Faroldi FLG, Ghari M, Lehmann E, Studer T (2021) Impossible and conflicting obligations in justification logic. In: Liu FVDPF, Marra A, Portner P (eds) Deontic Logic and Normative Systems (DEON2020/2021), College Publications, Rickmansworth, pp 151–165

  • Faroldi FLG, Ghari M, Lehmann E, Studer T (2022) Consistency and permission in deontic justification logic. J Log Comput. https://doi.org/10.1093/logcom/exac045

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Fitting M (2005) The logic of proofs, semantically. Ann Pure Appl Log 132:1–25. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.apal.2004.04.009

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Fitting M (2016) Modal logics, justification logics, and realization. Ann Pure Appl Log 167:615–648. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.apal.2016.03.005

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • French T, van der Meyden R, Reynolds M (2005) Axioms for logics of knowledge and past time: synchrony and unique initial states. In: Advances in modal logic. Vol. 5, pp 53–72. King’s College Publications, London

  • Gabbay DM, Hodkinson I, Reynolds M (1994) Temporal logic (vol 1): mathematical foundations and computational aspects. Oxford University Press Inc., ISBN 0-19-853769-7

  • Ghari M (2014) Distributed knowledge justification logics. Theory Comput Syst 55:1–40. https://doi.org/10.1007/s00224-013-9492-x

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Ghari M (2017) Labeled sequent calculus for justification logics. Ann Pure Appl Log 168:72–111. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.apal.2016.08.006

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Ghari M (2018) Linear temporal justification logics with past operators. arXiv:1809.00167

  • Ghari M (2023) Linear temporal justification logics with past and future time modalities. Log J IGPL 31:1–38. https://doi.org/10.1093/JIGPAL/JZAB027

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Glavanicova D, Pascucci M (2021) Axiomatizing norms across time and the ‘paradox of the court’. In: Liu FVDPF, Marra A, Portner P (eds) Deontic Logic and Normative Systems (DEON2020/2021), College Publications, Rickmansworth, pp 201–218

  • Goble L (2013) Prima facie norms, normative conflicts, and dilemmas. In: Gabbay D, Horty J, Parent X, van der Meyden R, van der Torre L (eds) Handbook of deontic logic and normative systems. College Publications, pp 241–351

  • Goldblatt R (1992) Logics of time and computation. In: Center for the study of language and information, 2nd edn

  • Goossens WK (1977) Eulathus and protagoras. Logique Et Analyse 20:67–75

    Google Scholar 

  • Gore R (1999) Tableau methods for modal and temporal logics. In: D’Agostino M, Gabbay DM, Hahnle R, Posegga J (eds) Handbook of Tableau Methods, pp 297–396. Springer Netherlands

  • Halpern JY, van der Meyden R, Vardi MY (2004) Complete axiomatizations for reasoning about knowledge and time. SIAM J Comput 33:674–703. https://doi.org/10.1137/S0097539797320906

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Hansson SO (2013) Alternative semantics for deontic logic. In: Gabbay D, Horty J, Parent X, van der Meyden R, van der Torre L (eds) Handbook of deontic logic and normative systems. College Publications, pp 445–497

  • Hansson SO (2013) The varieties of permission. In: Gabbay D, Horty J, Parent X, van der Meyden R, van der Torre L (eds) Handbook of deontic logic and normative systems. College Publications, pp 195–240

  • Hilpinen R, McNamara P (2013) Deontic logic: a historical survey and introduction. In: Gabbay D, Horty J, Parent X, van der Meyden R, van der Torre L (eds) Handbook of deontic logic and normative systems. College Publications, pp 3–136

  • Jankowski B (2015) The Rhetor’s dilemma: Leibniz’s approach to an ancient case. In: Armgardt M, Canivez P, Chassagnard-Pinet S (eds) Past and Present Interactions in Legal Reasoning and Logic, pp 95–106. Springer International Publishing, Cham

  • Kuznets R, Studer T (2012) Justifications, ontology, and conservativity. In: Bolander T, Brauner T, Ghilardi S, Moss L (eds) Advances in Modal Logic, vol 9, pp 437–458. College Publications

  • Kuznets R, Studer T (2019) Logics of proofs and justifications. College Publications, Rickmansworth

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Lenzen W (1977) Protagoras contra euathlus betrachtungen zu einer sogenannten paradoxie. Ration 19:164–176

    Google Scholar 

  • Lichtenstein O, Pnueli A (2000) Propositional temporal logics: decidability and completeness. Log J IGPL 8:55–85. https://doi.org/10.1093/jigpal/8.1.55

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Lichtenstein O, Pnueli A, Zuck LD (1985) The glory of the past. In: Parikh R (ed) Logics of Programs. Logic of Programs 1985. Lecture Notes in Computer Science, vol 193. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg

  • Lomuscio A, Sergot M (2003) Deontic interpreted systems. Stud Log 75:63–92. https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1026176900459

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Lukowski P (2011) Paradoxes. Springer, Netherlands

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Moore R (1973) Legal permission. Arch Philos Law Soc Philos 59:327–346

    Google Scholar 

  • Pacuit E, Parikh R, Cogan E (2006) The logic of knowledge based obligation. Synthese 149:311–341. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-005-3877-6

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Rohani A, Studer T (2021) Explicit non-normal modal logic. In: Silva A, Wassermann R, de Queiroz R (eds) Logic, Language, Information, and Computation - WoLLIC 2021, volume 13038 of LNCS, pages 64–81. Springer

  • Sidon TY (2008) Interacting explicit evidence systems. Theory Comput Syst 43:272–293. https://doi.org/10.1007/s00224-007-9057-y

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Smullyan R (1978) What is the Name of this book?: The riddle of Dracula and other logical puzzles. Englewood Cliffs, NJ

  • Sobel JH (1987) The law student and his teacher. Theoria 53:1–18

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Standefer S (2019) Tracking reasons with extensions of relevant logics. Log J IGPL 27:543–569. https://doi.org/10.1093/JIGPAL/JZZ018

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Thomason RH (1981) Deontic logic as founded on tense logic. In: Hilpinen R (ed) New studies in deontic logic. Synthese Library, vol 152. Springer, Dordrecht

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Meghdad Ghari.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Meghdad Ghari: A preliminary version of this paper was presented in the “Annual Seminar on Mathematical Logic and its Applications”, Arak University of Technology, September 2019. The author would like to thank the organizers for their invitation. I would also like to thank Daniela Glavanic̆ová and Federico Faroldi, as well as the referees of this journal for their comments and suggestions. This research was in part supported by a grant from IPM (No. 1401030416) and carried out in IPM-Isfahan Branch.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Ghari, M. A formalization of the Protagoras court paradox in a temporal logic of epistemic and normative reasons. Artif Intell Law (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10506-023-09351-0

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10506-023-09351-0

Keywords

Navigation