Skip to main content
Log in

Modus Tonens

  • Published:
Argumentation Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Restating an interlocutor’s position in an incredulous tone of voice can sometimes serve legitimate dialectical ends. However, there are cases in which incredulous restatement is out of bounds. This article provides an analysis of one common instance of the inappropriate use of incredulous restatement, which the authors call “modus tonens.” The authors argue that modus tonens is vicious because it pragmatically implicates the view that one’s interlocutor is one’s cognitive subordinate and provides a cue to like-minded onlookers that dialectical opponents are not to be treated as epistemic peers.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See van Eemeren and Grootendorst (2004, p. 68) for an account of the commissives that are allowable in the confrontation stages of argumentative dialogue. See also Walton (1989, pp. 9–10) on the conditions for speakers to open argumentative dialogue with expressions of willingness to abide by commitment rules.

  2. See Brown and Levinson (1987) and Cutting (2002) for accounts of strategies for avoiding face-threatening gestures. Additionally, surprised restatement may be taken as following a maxim of tact or approbation where one minimizes overt criticism of others (Leech 1983, p. 107).

  3. See Tracy and Carjuzáa (1993, pp. 181–182) on identity enactment in reasoned dialogue—cognitive authorities enact that authority even with their questions. With expressions of surprise, in cases where the authority is clear, the implication is that of directive to reformulate or rethink.

  4. Such an argument would take the form of argument from authority: those who have thought about the issue of whether p or not p hold that not-p; therefore, it is reasonable to hold that not-p.

  5. Take such situations as tantamount to well-poisoning.

  6. We borrow the term browbeating from Gaus (1996, p. 124).

  7. See Walton (1989, p. 63) for an account of the listener responsibility of helpfulness.

  8. See Aikin and Anderson (2006, pp. 21–22) for aspects of arguers tacitly addressing an onlooking/non-participating audience. The force of such gestures is to communicate an assessment of the interlocutor that should be shared between the speaker and the audience. For example, expressions of exasperation with an interlocutor are not only for the interlocutor but also for the sake of those watching the exchange. Additionally, Richardson’s ‘performative bullshit’ (2006, p. 94) has the same function—a speaker directs her audience to take her arguments as good because she presents them as good, and alternately her opponent’s arguments as bad because she presents them as bad.

References

  • Aikin, Scott F., Mark Anderson. 2006. Argumentative norms in Republic I. Philosophy in the Contemporary World. 13(2): 18–24

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, G., S. Levinson. 1987. Politeness. New York: Cambridge University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Cutting, Joan. 2002. Pragmatics and discourse. New York: Routledge

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F., R. Grootendorst. 2004. A systematic theory of argumentation. New York: Cambridge University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, Gerald. 1996. Justificatory liberalism. New York: Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Leech, G. 1983. Principles of pragmatics. London: Longman

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, Brooke M., Richard Parker. 2007. Critical thinking, 8th edition. New York: McGraw Hill

    Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, Alan. 2006. Performing bullshit and the post-sincere condition. In Bullshit and philosophy, ed. G. Hardcastle, and G. Reisch, 83–97. Chicago: Open Court

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, Cass. 2003. The law of group polarization. In Debating deliberative democracy, ed. James Fishkin, Peter Laslett. London: Blackwell

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, Cass. 2006. Infotopia. New York: Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Tracy, Karen, Jioanna Carjuzáa. 1993. Identity enactment in intellectual discussion. Journal of Language and Social Psychology. 12(3): 171–194

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walton, Richard. 1989. Informal logic. New York: Cambridge University Press

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Robert B. Talisse.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Aikin, S.F., Talisse, R.B. Modus Tonens. Argumentation 22, 521–529 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-008-9103-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-008-9103-1

Keywords

Navigation