Acta Biotheoretica

, Volume 62, Issue 4, pp 479–498 | Cite as

A Philosophical Evaluation of Adaptationism as a Heuristic Strategy

Regular Article

Abstract

Adaptationism has prompted many a debate in philosophy of biology but the focus is usually on empirical and explanatory issues rather than methodological adaptationism (MA). Likewise, the context of evolutionary biology has provided the grounding for most discussions of the heuristic role of adaptationism. This paper extends the debate by drawing on case studies from physiology and systems biology to discuss the productive and problematic aspects of adaptationism in functional as well as evolutionary studies at different levels of biological organization. Gould and Lewontin’s Spandrels-paper famously criticized adaptationist methodology for implying a risk of generating ‘blind spots’ with respect to non-selective effects on evolution. Some have claimed that this bias can be accommodated through the testing of evolutionary hypotheses. Although this is an important aspect of overcoming the pitfalls of adaptationism, I argue that the issue of methodological biases is broader than the question of testability. I demonstrate the productivity of adaptationist heuristics but also discuss the deeper problematic aspects associated with the imperialistic tendencies of the strong account of MA.

Keywords

Methodological adaptationism Optimality Design principles Reverse engineering Design analogies Heuristic 

Abbreviations

EA

Empirical adaptationism

MA

Methodological adaptationism

References

  1. Alon U (2003) Biological networks: the tinkerer as an engineer. Science 301:1866–1867CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Alon U (2007a) An introduction to systems biology: design principles of biological circuits. Chapman & Hall, Boca RatonGoogle Scholar
  3. Alon U (2007b) Network motifs: theory and experimental approaches. Nat Rev Genet 8:450–481CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Alon U (2007c) Simplicity in biology. La nature 446:497CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Amundson R (1994) Two concepts of constraint: adaptationism and the challenge from developmental biology. Philos Sci 61:556–578CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Babu MM, Luscombe NM, Aravind L, Gerstein M, Teichmann SA (2004) Structure and evolution of transcriptional regulatory networks. Curr Opin Struct Biol 14:283–291CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Brandon R, Rausher M (1996) Testing adaptationism: a comment on Orzack and Sober. Am Nat 148:189–201CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Clarke M (1970) Function of the spermaceti organ of the sperm whale. Nature 228:873–874CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Clarke M (1978) Buoyancy control as a function of the spermaceti organ in the sperm whale. J Mar Biol Assoc UK 58:27–71CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Conant G, Wagner A (2003) Convergent evolution of gene circuits. Nat Genet 34:264–266CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Cordero OX, Hogeweg P (2006) Feed-forward loop circuits as a side effect of genome evolution. Mol Biol Evol 23:1931–1936CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Dawkins R (1976) The selfish gene. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  13. Dekel E, Mangan S, Alon U (2005) Environmental selection of the feed-forward loop circuit in gene-regulation networks. Phys Biol 2:81–88CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Dennett DC (1995) Darwin’s dangerous idea: evolution and the meanings of life. Penguin, LondonGoogle Scholar
  15. Felsenstein J (1985) Phylogenies and the comparative method. Am Nat 125:1–15CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Forber P (2009) Spandrels and a pervasive problem of evidence. Biol Philos 24:247–266CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Godfrey-Smith P (2001) Three kinds of adaptationism. In: Orzack SH, Sober E (eds) Adaptationism and optimality. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 335–357CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Goodwin B (1994) How the Leopard changed its sports. The evolution of complexity. Phoenix, LondonGoogle Scholar
  19. Gould SJ (1996) The mismeasure of man. Norton and Company, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  20. Gould SJ, Lewontin RC (1979) The spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian paradigm: a critique of the adaptationist programme. Proc R Soc B 205:581–598CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Griffiths PE (1996) The historical turn in the study of adaptation. Br J Philos Sci 47:511–532CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Hansen T, Pienaar J, Orzack S (2008) A comparative method for studying adaptation to a randomly evolving environment. Evolution 62:1965–1977Google Scholar
  23. Hogeweg P (2012) Toward a theory of multilevel evolution: long-term information integration shapes the mutational landscape and enhances evolvability. In: Soyer O (ed) Evolutionary systems biology. Springer, London, pp 195–223CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Houston A (2009) San Marco and evolutionary biology. Biol Philos 24:215–230CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Kimura M (1985) The neutral theory of molecular evolution. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  26. Knabe JF, Nehaniv CL, Schilstra MJ (2008) Do motifs reflect evolved function? No convergent evolution of genetic regulatory network subgraph topologies. BioSystems 94:68–74CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Knight CG, Pinney JW (2009) Making the right connections; biological networks in the light of evolution. BioEssays 10:1080–1090CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Konagurthy AS, Lesk AM (2008) On the origin of distribution patterns of motifs in biological networks. BMC Syst Biol 2:73CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Koonin EV (2011) Are there laws of genome evolution? PLoS Comput Biol 7:e1002173CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Kuo DP, Banzhaf W, Leier A (2006) Network topology and the evolution of dynamics in an artificial genetic regulatory network model created by whole genome duplication and divergence. BioSystems 85:177–200CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Lewens T (2004) Organisms and artifacts: design in nature and elsewhere. MIT Press, Cambridge, MAGoogle Scholar
  32. Lewens T (2009) Seven types of adaptationism. Biol Philos 24:161–182CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Lynch M (2007a) The evolution of genetic networks by non-adaptive processes. Nat Rev Genet 8:803–813CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Lynch M (2007b) The frailty of adaptive hypotheses for the origins of organismal complexity. Proc Natl Acad Sci 104:8597–8604CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Madsen P (2002) Kaskelothvalens store næse. Aktuel Naturvidenskab 3:8–11Google Scholar
  36. Madsen PT, Payne R, Kristiansen NU, Wahlberg M, Kerr I, Møhl B (2002) Sperm whale sound production studied with ultrasound time/depth-recording tags. J Exp Biol 205:1899–1906Google Scholar
  37. Madsen PT, Wisniewska D, Beedholm K (2010) Single source sound production and dynamic beam formation in echolocating harbour porpoises (Phocoena phocoena). J Exp Biol 213:3105–3110CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Mangan S, Zaslaver A, Alon U (2003) The coherent feedforward loop serves as a sign-sensitive delay element in transcription networks. J Mol Biol 334:197–204CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Mayr E (1983) How to carry out the adaptationist program? Am Nat 121:324–333CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Mazurie A, Bottani S, Vergassola M (2005) An evolutionary and functional assessment of regulatory network motifs. Genome Biol 6:35.1–35.12CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Milo R, Shen-Orr S, Itzkovitz S, Kashtan N, Chklovskii D, Alon U (2002) Network motifs: simple building blocks of complex networks. Science 298:824–827CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Møhl B (2001) Sound transmission in the nose of the sperm whale Physeter catodon. A post mortem study. J Comp Physiol 187:335–340CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Møhl B, Madsen PT, Wahlberg M, Whitlow W, Nachtigall P, Righway S (2003) Sound transmission in the spermaceti complex of a recently expired sperm whale calf. Acoust Soc Am ARLO 4(1):19Google Scholar
  44. Müller G, Newman SA (2003) Origination of organismal form: beyond the gene in developmental and evolutionary biology. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MAGoogle Scholar
  45. Nielsen R (2009) Adaptationism: 30 years after Gould and Lewontin. Evolution 63:2487–2490CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Norris KS, Harvey GW (1972) A theory for the function of the spermaceti organ of the sperm whale (Physeter catodon L.). In: Galler SR et al (eds) Animal orientation and navigation. NASA, Washington, DC, pp 397–417Google Scholar
  47. Norris K, Møhl B (1983) Can odontocetes debilitate prey with sound? Am Nat 122:85–104CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. O’Malley M (2012) Evolutionary systems biology: historical and philosophical perspective on an emerging synthesis. Adv Exp Med Biol 751:1–28CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. Orzack S, Sober E (1994a) How (not) to test an optimality model. Trends Ecol Evol 9:265–267CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Orzack S, Sober E (1994b) Optimality models and the test of adaptationism. Am Nat 143:361–380CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Orzack S, Sober E (1996) How to formulate and test adaptationism. Am Nat 148:202–210CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. Orzack S, Sober E (2001) Adaptation, phylogenetic inertia, and the method of controlled comparisons. In: Orzack S, Sober E (eds) Adaptationism and optimality. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 45–63CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Pigliucci M (2009) An extended synthesis for evolutionary biology. Ann NY Acad Sci 1168:218–228CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  54. Pigliucci M, Kaplan J (2000) The fall and rise of Dr Pangloss: adaptationism and the spandrels paper 20 years later. Trends Ecol Evol 15:66–70CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  55. Resnik D (1997) Adaptationism: hypothesis or heuristic. Biol Philos 12:39–50CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  56. Richardson R (2007) Evolutionary psychology as maladapted psychology. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MAGoogle Scholar
  57. Salvado B, Karathia H, Chimenos A, Vilaprinyo E, Omholt S, Sorribas A, Alves R (2011) Methods for and results from the study of design principles in molecular systems. Math Biosci 231:3–18CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  58. Schickore J, Steinle F (eds) (2009) Revisiting discovery and justification, historical and philosophical perspectives on the context distinction. Springer, DordrechtGoogle Scholar
  59. Shen-Orr S, Milo R, Mangan S, Alon U (2002) Network motifs in the transcriptional regulation network of Escherichia coli. Nat Genet 31:64–68CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  60. Sober E (1993) Philosophy of biology. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  61. Sober E (1996) Evolution and optimality: feathers, bowling balls, and the thesis of adaptationism. Philos Exch 26:41–55Google Scholar
  62. Solé RV, Valverde S (2006) Are network motifs the spandrels of cellular complexity? Trends Ecol Evol 21:419–422CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  63. Steinacher A, Soyer O (2012) Evolutionary principles underlying structure and response dynamics of cellular networks. In: Soyer O (ed) Evolutionary systems biology. Springer, London, pp 225–247CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  64. Sterely K (2007) Dawkins vs. Gould, survival of the fittest. Icon Books Ltd., CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  65. Tyson J, Novák B (2010) Functional motifs in biochemical reaction networks. Annu Rev Phys Chem 61:219–240CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  66. Ward JJ, Thorton JM (2007) Evolutionary models for formation of network motifs and modularity in the Saccharomyces transcription factor network. PLoS Comp Biol 3:e198CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  67. Whitehead H (2003) Sperm whales, social evolution in the ocean. The University of Chicago Press, LondonGoogle Scholar
  68. Wilkins J, Godfrey-Smith P (2009) Adaptationism and the adaptive landscape. Biol Philos 24:199–214CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  69. Wilson M, Hanlon R, Tyack P, Madsen PT (2008) Big bang? Intense ultrasound does not have any detectable effects on the squid Loligo pealeii. Bioacoustics 17:321–323CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  70. Wimsatt WC (2007) Re-engineering philosophy for limited beings: piecewise approximations to reality. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MAGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2014

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of Physics and Astronomy, Centre for Science StudiesAarhus UniversityAarhusDenmark

Personalised recommendations