Abstract
The Samaritan’s Dilemma has largely been investigated, frequently by assuming that Samaritans help recipients out of altruism. Yet, Buchanan did not make any behavioral assumption regarding the Samaritan’s motives. In this paper, we explicitly introduce this assumption in Buchanan’s original model and analyze how it changes the nature of the game. We show that altruism alone does not explain the Dilemma. A parameter that captures the disutility the Samaritan feels when helping someone who does not reciprocate her benevolence must be introduced to make sense of the different version of Buchanan’s Samaritan’s Dilemma. We also show that the Samaritan’s Dilemma is an evolutionary stable outcome, which confirms Buchanan’s intuitions. Finally, a third important point put forward in the paper is that the more altruistic are the Samaritans, the less likely it is that they will show the kind of strategic courage envisaged by Buchanan, which is one of the most important traits Samaritans should display to avoid being trapped in a Dilemma.
This is a preview of subscription content,
to check access.

Similar content being viewed by others
Change history
30 March 2023
A Correction to this paper has been published: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10101-023-00294-5
Notes
See for instance, Thompson (1980), Veall (1986), Charlton (1987), Kotlikoff (1987), Lindbeck and Weibull (1988), Hansson and Stuart (1989), Wagner (1989), Bruce and Waldman (1990, 1991), Coate (1995), Easterly (2003), Lagerlof (2004), Poulsen and Svendsen (2005), Blouin and Pallage (2008), Leeson (2008), Burns (2009), John and Storr (2009) and Skarbek (2016).
Throughout his 1975 text, Buchanan (1975a: 75) identifies as “pragmatic” those behaviors that are implemented without any form of strategic thinking, that arise automatically (even unconsciously) in response to certain type of situations. Interestingly, he saw this type of behavioral automatisms as one of the main causes behind the existence of the Dilemma.
See Fontaine (2007) for a detailed historical account of Buchanan’s role and the place “The Samaritan’s Dilemma” in the history of economic analyses of altruism. Fontaine convincingly argues, and provides evidence, that Buchanan was interested in altruism and philanthropy. Yet, when he wrote his article, Buchanan was concerned by other issues that had not much to do with altruism (see Fleury and Marciano 2018).
To be more precise, we show that this form of altruism is not sufficient to make sense of both forms of Buchanan’s Samaritan’s Dilemma. With other forms of altruism, it is possible to show that altruism generates a Samaritan’s Dilemma (see Marciano 2022). This does not however invalidate our result: if the Samaritan’s Dilemma was the consequence of altruism, then it should exist with any form of altruistic concern.
In particular, the game is a Passive Samaritan’s Dilemma as long as \(2\alpha > 4\alpha - h - c > 3\alpha - h > \alpha\); and an Active Samaritan’s Dilemma as long as \(3\alpha - h > 4\alpha - h - c > 2\alpha > \alpha\). Clearly, there are multiple set of parameters satisfying these conditions.
Of course, one can think of many real-life situations where helpers may condition their assistance on the recipients’ future behavior, as well as others where the recipients’ intentions can be signalled or inferred during the matching procedure. In addition, allowing for repeated interactions would ultimately change the model’s predictions. While each of these scenarios is by no means irrelevant and generate a number of problems that can be addressed through other game-theoretic techniques, our focus here is on the multitude of everyday contingencies that fits with the above assumptions—e.g., see the examples of the passer-by giving a coin to a panhandler or helping a driver change a flat tire in the Introduction.
The last assumption, \(\rho \left( {0,0} \right) = \rho \left( {1,1} \right) = \rho \in \left( {0,1} \right)\) is made to avoid notational clutter. While all our results would be slightly different in quantitative terms by allowing for the possibility that \(\rho \left( {0,0} \right) \ne \rho \left( {1,1} \right)\), none would be altered qualitatively.
Meaning that all trajectories starting from any initial pair \(\left( {x_{0} ,y_{0} } \right) = \left( {1,\hat{y}} \right)\), \(\left( {x_{0} ,y_{0} } \right) = \left( {0,\hat{y}} \right)\), \(\left( {x_{0} ,y_{0} } \right) = \left( {\hat{x},0} \right)\) and \(\left( {x_{0} ,y_{0} } \right) = \left( {\hat{x},1} \right)\) will lie on the side with \(x = 1\), \(x = 0\), \(y = 0\) and \(y = 1\) respectively, where \(0 \le \hat{x} \le 1\) and \(0 \le \hat{y} \le 1\).
When there are no-own population effects, the players’ choices do not depend on the behavior of the other members of their population. In our framework, this can be seen from the fact that \(\frac{{\partial \left[ {U\left( 1 \right) - U\left( 0 \right)} \right]}}{\partial x} = 0\) and \(\frac{{\partial \left[ {V\left( 1 \right) - V\left( 0 \right)} \right]}}{\partial y} = 0\).
Moreover, Buchanan makes an additional remark concerning the influence of group size on individual behavior. In small groups, individuals anticipate that their behavior will affect what others do, so they adopt an ethical rule of conduct—they cooperate. In large groups, they believe that what they do will have no consequence and therefore behave egoistically—they do not cooperate.
The situation is surely not new in game theory, and resembles a classic “Battle of the Sexes” where neither of the two Nash equilibria simultaneously maximizes the payoff of the two players.
Interestingly, this strategic property of the Samaritan’s Dilemma is never mentioned by Buchanan in his original contribution, probably, because it sounded like a sort of contradiction to the very point he was trying to make about the need for recipients to make some effort and work.
In The Limits of Liberty (1975b), written at about the same period “The Samaritan’s Dilemma” was published, Buchanan used the same game to defend a social contract and a contractualist view of institutions.
We thank a reviewer for having insisted on the importance of such situations and having suggested us that recipients too could display courage or adhere to an ethic of responsibility that leads them to work more when helped, instead of not working more when helped. Modeling the situation would nonetheless lead us too far away from the objective of the paper.
References
Axelrod R (1980) More effective choice in the prisoner's dilemma. J Conflict Resolut 24(3):379–403
Axelrod R (1984) The evolution of cooperation. Basic Books, New York
Becker GS (1974) A theory of social interactions. J Polit Econ 82:1063–1093
Bergstrom T (1989) A fresh look at the rotten kid theorem–and other household mysteries. J Polit Econ 97(5):1138–1159
Blouin M, Pallage S (2008) Humanitarian relief and civil conflict. J Confl Resolut 52(4):548–565
Boettke PJ, Martin A (2010) Exchange, production, and Samaritan dilemmas. Mimeo. http://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/33199/
Boone P (1996) Politics and the effectiveness of foreign aid. Eur Econ Rev 40:289–329
Bovard J (1983) Feeding Everybody: How federal food programs grew and grew. Policy Rev 26(Fall):42–51
Browne MJ, Hoyt RE (2000) The demand for flood insurance: empirical evidence. J Risk Uncertainty 20(3):291–306
Bruce N, Waldman M (1990) The rotten-kid theorem meets the Samaritan’s Dilemma. Q J Econ 105(1):155–165
Bruce N, Waldman M (1991) Transfers in kind: why they can be efficient and nonpaternalistic. Am Econ Rev 81(5):1345–1351
Buchanan JM (1965) Ethical rules, expected values, large numbers. Ethics 76(1):1–13
Buchanan JM (1968a) The demand and supply of public goods. Liberty Fund, Carmel
Buchanan JM (1968b) A behavioral theory of pollution. Econ Inq 6(5):347–358
Buchanan JM (1975a) The Samaritan’s Dilemma. In: Phelps ES (ed) Altruism, morality and economic theory. Sage Foundation, New York, pp 71–85
Buchanan JM (1975b) The limits of liberty between Anarchy and Leviathan. University of Chicago, Chicago
Buchanan JM (1978) Markets, states, and the extent of morals. Am Econ Rev 68(2):364–368
Burns BR (2009) Solving Samaritan's Dilemmas in irrigation investment. mimeo
Burnside C, Dollar D (2000) Aid, policies, and growth. Am Econ Rev 90(4):847–868
Charlton MW (1987) The food aid conundrum and Canadian aid strategy: the issue of donor control. Int J 42(3):473–508
Coate S (1995) Altruism, the Samaritan’s Dilemma, and government transfer policy. Am Econ Rev 85(1):46–57
Corbett S, Fikkert B (2009) When helping hurts: how to alleviate poverty without hurting the poor...and yourself. Moody Publishers, Chicago
Coyne CJ (2008) After war: the political economy of exporting democracy. Stanford University Press, Stanford
Easterly W (2003) Can foreign aid buy growth? J Econ Perspect 17(3):23–48
Fleury JB, Marciano A (2018) The making of a constitutionalist: James Buchanan on education. Hist Polit Econ 50(3):511–548
Fontaine P (2007) From philanthropy to altruism: incorporating unselfish behavior into economics, 1961–1975. Hist Polit Econ 39(1):1–46
Futagami R, Kamada K, Sato T (2004) Government transfers and the Samaritan’s Dilemma in the family. Public Choice 118(1/2):77–86
Gibson CC, Andersson K, Ostrom E, Shivakumar S (2005) The Samaritan’s Dilemma. The political economy of development aid. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Goodman NP, Herzberg RQ (2020) Gifts as governance: church welfare and the Samaritan’s Dilemma. J Inst Econ 16:703–714
Hansson I, Stuart C (1989) Social security as trade among living generations. Am Econ Rev 79(5):1182–1195
Hirshleifer J (1977) Shakespeare versus Becker on altruism: the Importance of having the last word. J Econ Lit 15(2):500–502
John A, Storr VH (2009) Can the west help the rest? A review essay of Sachs’ the end of poverty and easterly’s the white man’s burden. J Priv Enterp 25(1):125–140
Jonker LB, Taylor PD (1978) Evolutionarily stable strategies and game dynamics. Math Biosci 40:145–156
Kotlikoff LJ (1987) Justifying public provision of social security. J Policy Anal Manage 6(4):674–689
Lagerlof J (2004) Efficiency-enhancing signalling in the Samaritan’s dilemma. Econ J 114(492):55–68
Lee DR (1987) The tradeoff between equality and efficiency: short-run politics and long-run realities. Public Choice 53(2):149–165
Leeson PT (2008) Escaping poverty: foreign aid, private property, and economic development. J Priv Enterp 23(2):39–64
Lindbeck A, Weibull JW (1988) Altruism and time inconsistency: the economics of fait accompli. J Polit Econ 96(6):1165–1182
Marciano A (2022) Sado-masochism in Buchanan’s Samaritan’s Dilemma: a constitutional perspective. Homo Œconomicus. https://doi.org/10.1007/s41412-022-00126-7
Pasour EC Jr (1991) The Samaritan's Dilemma and the welfare state. Policy, summer, pp 55–57
Phelps E (ed) (1975) Altruism, morality, and economic theory. Russel Sage Foundation
Poulsen AU, Svendsen GT (2005) Social capital and endogenous preferences. Public Choice 123(1/2):171–196
Rajan RG, Subramanian A (2005) Aid and growth: What does the cross-country evidence really show? NBER working paper w11513. https://doi.org/10.3386/w11513, http://www.nber.org/papers/w11513
Raschky PA, Weck-Hannemann H (2007) Charity hazard - a real hazard to natural disaster insurance? Environ Hazards 7(4):321–329
Schmidtchen D (1999) To help or not to help: the Samaritan’s dilemma revisited, CSLE Discussion Paper No. 99-09. Universität des Saarlandes, Center for the Study of Law and Economics (CSLE), Saarbrücken
Schmidtz D (2000) Islands in a sea of obligation: limits of the duty to rescue. Law Philos 19:683–705
Skarbek EC (2016) Aid, ethics, and the Samaritan’s Dilemma: strategic courage in constitutional entrepreneurship. J Inst Econ 12(2):371–393
Stone D (2008) The Samaritan’s Dilemma: should government help your neighbor? Nation Books
Thompson EA (1980) Charity and nonprofit organizations. In: Clarkson K, Martin D (eds) Economics of Non proprietary Organizations. JAI Press, Inc., Greenwich, CT, pp 125–138
Tullock G (1977) Economics and sociobiology: a comment. J Econ Lit 15(2):502–506
Veall MR (1986) Public pensions as optimal social contracts. J Public Econ 31(2):237–251
Wagner RE (1989) To promote the general welfare. Pacific Research Institute, San Francisco
Wagner RE (2005) Redistribution, poor relief, and the welfare state. In: Backhaus J, Wagner RE (eds) Handbook of public finance. Springer, Berlin, pp 385–405
Williamson C (2010) Exploring the failure of foreign aid: the role of incentives and information. Rev Austrian Econ 23:17–33
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Additional information
Publisher's Note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
The original online version of this article was revised: Due to a production error, the affiliation details for the author Alain Marciano were incorrect. Now, it has been corrected.
Previous versions of the paper were presented at the Adam Smith Seminar (Center of Conflict of Resolution, Munich, 29 March 2021), CEPN (Predatory state, conflict and resistance, 18 June 2021), Annual conference of the Association Française d'Économie du Droit (14–15 October 2021), Nice-Nancy-Montpellier online workshop (2 December 2021), and at the Séminaire d’Économie Théorique et Appliquée (THEMA, Cergy Université, 25 octobre 2022). We thank all the participants for their comments. In particular, Benoît Le Maux, Antoine Pietri, and Mehrdad Vahabi.
Appendix 1
Appendix 1
Proof of Lemma 2
The \(\left( {x^{*} ,y^{*} } \right)\) equilibrium exists when \(x^{*}\) and \(y^{*}\) both \(\in \left( {0,1} \right)\). This, in turn, requires that two of the following conditions are simultaneously satisfied:
Rearranging condition (4′) yields condition (1); rearranging conditions (6′) and (7′) yields, respectively, conditions (8) and (9). The concluding statement in Lemma 1 follows from the fact that conditions (1) and (9) are simultaneously satisfied when the game is a Passive Samaritan’s dilemma, since both are implied by condition (3), while the parametrization defined in condition (1) is inconsistent with any of the possible combinations across conditions (4′)–(7′), so that \(\left( {x^{*} ,y^{*} } \right)\) never exists when the game is an Active Samaritan’s dilemma.□
Proof of Proposition 1
The Jacobian matrix of the system is given by:
As it is well-known, a stationary point is attractive if both the eigenvalues of the Jacobian matrix evaluated at that equilibrium have negative real parts. In addition, when either of the partial derivative \({\text{d}}\dot{x}/{\text{d}}y\) and/or \({\text{d}}\dot{y}/{\text{d}}x\) is = 0—which happens whenever \(x = 0\) or \(x = 1\) and/or \(y = 0\) or \(y = 1\)—the eigenvalues exactly correspond to the partial derivatives \({\text{d}}\dot{x}/{\text{d}}x\) and \({\text{d}}\dot{y}/{\text{d}}y\). With these facts in mind, the topological properties of the four vertices \(\left( {0, 0} \right)\), \(\left( {0, 1} \right)\), \(\left( {1, 0} \right)\) and \(\left( {1, 1} \right)\) can be straightforwardly checked by evaluating the sign of \({\text{d}}\dot{x}/{\text{d}}x\) and \({\text{d}}\dot{y}/{\text{d}}y\) at each of the four vertices, since the partial derivatives \({\text{d}}\dot{x}/{\text{d}}y\) and \({\text{d}}\dot{y}/{\text{d}}x\) are always = 0 at each of these points.
At \(\left( {0,0} \right)\) we have that:
Hence, we have three cases:
-
1.
if \(1 - e - \rho < 0\) and \(h + c - \rho \alpha < 0\), \(\left( {0,0} \right)\) is a sink (asymptotically stable).
-
2.
If \(1 - e - \rho > 0\) and \(h + c - \rho \alpha > 0\), \(\left( {0,0} \right)\) is source (asymptotically unstable).
-
3.
If \(1 - e - \rho < 0\) and \(h + c - \rho \alpha > 0\), or \(1 - e - \rho > 0\) and \(h + c - \rho \alpha < 0\), \(\left( {0,0} \right)\) is a saddle (asymptotically unstable).
Given Lemma 1, when the game is either an Active or a Passive Samaritan’s Dilemma, \(\left( {0,0} \right)\) is always a sink.
At \(\left( {1,1} \right)\) we have that:
Hence, we have three cases:
-
1.
if \(e - \rho < 0\) and \(\alpha \left( {1 - \rho } \right) - h < 0\), \(\left( {1,1} \right)\) is a sink (asymptotically stable).
-
2.
If \(e - \rho > 0\) and \(\alpha \left( {1 - \rho } \right) - h > 0\), \(\left( {1,1} \right)\) is source (asymptotically unstable).
-
3.
If \(e - \rho < 0\) and \(\alpha \left( {1 - \rho } \right) - h > 0\) or \(e - \rho > 0\) and \(\alpha \left( {1 - \rho } \right) - h < 0\), \(\left( {1,1} \right)\) is a saddle (asymptotically unstable).
Given Lemma 1, when the game is an Active Samaritan’s Dilemma, \(\left( {1,1} \right)\) is always a saddle; when the game is a Passive Samaritan’s Dilemma, \(\left( {1,1} \right)\) is always a sink.
At \(\left( {1,0} \right)\) we have that
Hence, we have three cases:
-
1.
if \(\rho + e - 1 < 0\) and \(h - \left( {1 - \rho } \right)\alpha < 0\), \(\left( {1,0} \right)\) is a sink (asymptotically stable).
-
2.
If \(\rho + e - 1 > 0\) and \(h - \left( {1 - \rho } \right)\alpha > 0\), \(\left( {1,0} \right)\) is source (asymptotically unstable).
-
3.
If \(\rho + e - 1 < 0\) and \(h - \left( {1 - \rho } \right)\alpha > 0\), or \(\rho + e - 1 > 0\) and \(h - \left( {1 - \rho } \right)\alpha < 0\), \(\left( {0,1} \right)\) is a saddle (asymptotically unstable).
Given Lemma 1, when the game is an Active Samaritan’s Dilemma, \(\left( {1,0} \right)\) is always a saddle; when the game is a Passive Samaritan’s Dilemma, \(\left( {1,0} \right)\) is always a source.
At \(\left( {0,1} \right)\) we have that
Hence, we have three cases:
-
1.
if \(\rho - e < 0\) and \(\rho \alpha - h - c < 0\), \(\left( {0,1} \right)\) is a sink (asymptotically stable).
-
2.
If \(\rho - e > 0\) and \(\rho \alpha - h - c > 0\), \(\left( {0,1} \right)\) is source (asymptotically unstable).
-
3.
If \(\rho - e < 0\) and \(\rho \alpha - h - c > 0\), or \(\rho - e > 0\) and \(\rho \alpha - h - c < 0\), \(\left( {0,1} \right)\) is a saddle (asymptotically unstable).
Given Lemma 1, when the game is an Active Samaritan’s Dilemma, \(\left( {0,1} \right)\) is always a saddle; when the game is a Passive Samaritan’s Dilemma, \(\left( {0,1} \right)\) is always a source.
To prove the stability properties of the \(\left( {x^{*} ,y^{*} } \right)\) equilibrium, we study its Trace and Determinant and see that:
From Lemma 1, we already know that \(\left( {2\rho - 1} \right)\alpha - c > 0\) and \(2\rho - 1 > 0\) are simultaneously satisfied when condition (3) is satisfied. In this case, \({\text{Det }}J_{{\left( {x^{*} ,y^{*} } \right)}} < 0\), which proves that \(\left( {x^{*} ,y^{*} } \right)\) is a saddle when the game is a Passive Samaritan’s dilemma. In addition, there exists parametrizations for which \({\text{Det }}J_{{\left( {x^{*} ,y^{*} } \right)}} \ge 0\), which completes the Proof of Proposition 1.□
Proof of Proposition 2
From the results in Proposition 1, it is straightforward to derive the following set of results. First, the existence conditions of the four monostable regimes are as follows:
-
1.
The stationary point \(\left( {0,0} \right)\) is the unique attractor iff \(e > \max \left\{ {\rho ,1 - \rho } \right\}\) and \(\alpha > \max \left\{ {\frac{h}{1 - \rho },\frac{h + c}{e}} \right\}\).
-
2.
The stationary point \(\left( {1,1} \right)\) is the unique attractor iff \(e < \min \left\{ {\rho ,1 - \rho } \right\}\) and \(\alpha < \min \left\{ {\frac{h}{1 - \rho },\frac{h + c}{e}} \right\}\).
-
3.
The stationary point \(\left( {1,0} \right)\) is the unique attractor iff \(e < \min \left\{ {\rho ,1 - \rho } \right\}\) and \(\alpha > \max \left\{ {\frac{h}{1 - \rho },\frac{h + c}{e}} \right\}\).
-
4.
The stationary point \(\left( {0,1} \right)\) is the unique attractor iff \(e > \max \left\{ {\rho ,1 - \rho } \right\}\) and \(\alpha < \min \left\{ {\frac{h}{1 - \rho },\frac{h + c}{e}} \right\}\)
Second, the existence conditions of the two bistable regimes are as follows:
-
1.
The stationary points \(\left( {0,0} \right)\) and \(\left( {1,1} \right)\) simultaneously attract iff conditions (1) and (9) are simultaneously satisfied.
-
2.
The stationary points \(\left( {1,0} \right)\) and \(\left( {0,1} \right)\) simultaneously attract iff simultaneously attract iff conditions (7) and (8) are simultaneously satisfied.
Third, the existence conditions of the two cyclical regimes are as follows:
-
1.
The system exhibits cyclical behavior with counterclockwise oscillations around \(\left( {x^{*} ,y^{*} } \right)\) iff conditions (7) and (9) are simultaneously satisfied.
-
2.
The system exhibits cyclical behavior with clockwise oscillations around \(\left( {x^{*} ,y^{*} } \right)\) iff conditions (1) and (8) are simultaneously satisfied.
Observe that when the game is an Active Samaritan’s Dilemma, the monostable regime featuring \(\left( {0,0} \right)\) as the only attractor results; when the game is a Passive Samaritan’s Dilemma, the bistable regime featuring \(\left( {0,0} \right)\) and \(\left( {1,1} \right)\) as attractors result.□
Rights and permissions
Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.
About this article
Cite this article
Dughera, S., Marciano, A. Inside Buchanan's Samaritan's Dilemma: altruism, strategic courage and ethics of responsibility. Econ Gov 24, 207–233 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10101-023-00292-7
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10101-023-00292-7