Skip to main content
Log in

Inside Buchanan's Samaritan's Dilemma: altruism, strategic courage and ethics of responsibility

Economics of Governance Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Cite this article

A Correction to this article was published on 30 March 2023

This article has been updated

Abstract

The Samaritan’s Dilemma has largely been investigated, frequently by assuming that Samaritans help recipients out of altruism. Yet, Buchanan did not make any behavioral assumption regarding the Samaritan’s motives. In this paper, we explicitly introduce this assumption in Buchanan’s original model and analyze how it changes the nature of the game. We show that altruism alone does not explain the Dilemma. A parameter that captures the disutility the Samaritan feels when helping someone who does not reciprocate her benevolence must be introduced to make sense of the different version of Buchanan’s Samaritan’s Dilemma. We also show that the Samaritan’s Dilemma is an evolutionary stable outcome, which confirms Buchanan’s intuitions. Finally, a third important point put forward in the paper is that the more altruistic are the Samaritans, the less likely it is that they will show the kind of strategic courage envisaged by Buchanan, which is one of the most important traits Samaritans should display to avoid being trapped in a Dilemma.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Change history

Notes

  1. See for instance, Thompson (1980), Veall (1986), Charlton (1987), Kotlikoff (1987), Lindbeck and Weibull (1988), Hansson and Stuart (1989), Wagner (1989), Bruce and Waldman (1990, 1991), Coate (1995), Easterly (2003), Lagerlof (2004), Poulsen and Svendsen (2005), Blouin and Pallage (2008), Leeson (2008), Burns (2009), John and Storr (2009) and Skarbek (2016).

  2. Throughout his 1975 text, Buchanan (1975a: 75) identifies as “pragmatic” those behaviors that are implemented without any form of strategic thinking, that arise automatically (even unconsciously) in response to certain type of situations. Interestingly, he saw this type of behavioral automatisms as one of the main causes behind the existence of the Dilemma.

  3. In line with Buchanan’s (1975a: 71) original matrixes, the numbers in Tables 1, 2, 3 and 4 are “utility indicators […] arranged in ordinal sequence”.

  4. See Fontaine (2007) for a detailed historical account of Buchanan’s role and the place “The Samaritan’s Dilemma” in the history of economic analyses of altruism. Fontaine convincingly argues, and provides evidence, that Buchanan was interested in altruism and philanthropy. Yet, when he wrote his article, Buchanan was concerned by other issues that had not much to do with altruism (see Fleury and Marciano 2018).

  5. To be more precise, we show that this form of altruism is not sufficient to make sense of both forms of Buchanan’s Samaritan’s Dilemma. With other forms of altruism, it is possible to show that altruism generates a Samaritan’s Dilemma (see Marciano 2022). This does not however invalidate our result: if the Samaritan’s Dilemma was the consequence of altruism, then it should exist with any form of altruistic concern.

  6. In particular, the game is a Passive Samaritan’s Dilemma as long as \(2\alpha > 4\alpha - h - c > 3\alpha - h > \alpha\); and an Active Samaritan’s Dilemma as long as \(3\alpha - h > 4\alpha - h - c > 2\alpha > \alpha\). Clearly, there are multiple set of parameters satisfying these conditions.

  7. Of course, one can think of many real-life situations where helpers may condition their assistance on the recipients’ future behavior, as well as others where the recipients’ intentions can be signalled or inferred during the matching procedure. In addition, allowing for repeated interactions would ultimately change the model’s predictions. While each of these scenarios is by no means irrelevant and generate a number of problems that can be addressed through other game-theoretic techniques, our focus here is on the multitude of everyday contingencies that fits with the above assumptions—e.g., see the examples of the passer-by giving a coin to a panhandler or helping a driver change a flat tire in the Introduction.

  8. The last assumption, \(\rho \left( {0,0} \right) = \rho \left( {1,1} \right) = \rho \in \left( {0,1} \right)\) is made to avoid notational clutter. While all our results would be slightly different in quantitative terms by allowing for the possibility that \(\rho \left( {0,0} \right) \ne \rho \left( {1,1} \right)\), none would be altered qualitatively.

  9. Meaning that all trajectories starting from any initial pair \(\left( {x_{0} ,y_{0} } \right) = \left( {1,\hat{y}} \right)\), \(\left( {x_{0} ,y_{0} } \right) = \left( {0,\hat{y}} \right)\), \(\left( {x_{0} ,y_{0} } \right) = \left( {\hat{x},0} \right)\) and \(\left( {x_{0} ,y_{0} } \right) = \left( {\hat{x},1} \right)\) will lie on the side with \(x = 1\), \(x = 0\), \(y = 0\) and \(y = 1\) respectively, where \(0 \le \hat{x} \le 1\) and \(0 \le \hat{y} \le 1\).

  10. When there are no-own population effects, the players’ choices do not depend on the behavior of the other members of their population. In our framework, this can be seen from the fact that \(\frac{{\partial \left[ {U\left( 1 \right) - U\left( 0 \right)} \right]}}{\partial x} = 0\) and \(\frac{{\partial \left[ {V\left( 1 \right) - V\left( 0 \right)} \right]}}{\partial y} = 0\).

  11. Moreover, Buchanan makes an additional remark concerning the influence of group size on individual behavior. In small groups, individuals anticipate that their behavior will affect what others do, so they adopt an ethical rule of conduct—they cooperate. In large groups, they believe that what they do will have no consequence and therefore behave egoistically—they do not cooperate.

  12. The situation is surely not new in game theory, and resembles a classic “Battle of the Sexes” where neither of the two Nash equilibria simultaneously maximizes the payoff of the two players.

  13. Interestingly, this strategic property of the Samaritan’s Dilemma is never mentioned by Buchanan in his original contribution, probably, because it sounded like a sort of contradiction to the very point he was trying to make about the need for recipients to make some effort and work.

  14. In The Limits of Liberty (1975b), written at about the same period “The Samaritan’s Dilemma” was published, Buchanan used the same game to defend a social contract and a contractualist view of institutions.

  15. We thank a reviewer for having insisted on the importance of such situations and having suggested us that recipients too could display courage or adhere to an ethic of responsibility that leads them to work more when helped, instead of not working more when helped. Modeling the situation would nonetheless lead us too far away from the objective of the paper.

References

  • Axelrod R (1980) More effective choice in the prisoner's dilemma. J Conflict Resolut 24(3):379–403

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Axelrod R (1984) The evolution of cooperation. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Becker GS (1974) A theory of social interactions. J Polit Econ 82:1063–1093

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bergstrom T (1989) A fresh look at the rotten kid theorem–and other household mysteries. J Polit Econ 97(5):1138–1159

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blouin M, Pallage S (2008) Humanitarian relief and civil conflict. J Confl Resolut 52(4):548–565

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boettke PJ, Martin A (2010) Exchange, production, and Samaritan dilemmas. Mimeo. http://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/33199/

  • Boone P (1996) Politics and the effectiveness of foreign aid. Eur Econ Rev 40:289–329

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bovard J (1983) Feeding Everybody: How federal food programs grew and grew. Policy Rev 26(Fall):42–51

  • Browne MJ, Hoyt RE (2000) The demand for flood insurance: empirical evidence. J Risk Uncertainty 20(3):291–306

  • Bruce N, Waldman M (1990) The rotten-kid theorem meets the Samaritan’s Dilemma. Q J Econ 105(1):155–165

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bruce N, Waldman M (1991) Transfers in kind: why they can be efficient and nonpaternalistic. Am Econ Rev 81(5):1345–1351

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan JM (1965) Ethical rules, expected values, large numbers. Ethics 76(1):1–13

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan JM (1968a) The demand and supply of public goods. Liberty Fund, Carmel

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan JM (1968b) A behavioral theory of pollution. Econ Inq 6(5):347–358

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan JM (1975a) The Samaritan’s Dilemma. In: Phelps ES (ed) Altruism, morality and economic theory. Sage Foundation, New York, pp 71–85

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan JM (1975b) The limits of liberty between Anarchy and Leviathan. University of Chicago, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan JM (1978) Markets, states, and the extent of morals. Am Econ Rev 68(2):364–368

    Google Scholar 

  • Burns BR (2009) Solving Samaritan's Dilemmas in irrigation investment. mimeo

  • Burnside C, Dollar D (2000) Aid, policies, and growth. Am Econ Rev 90(4):847–868

  • Charlton MW (1987) The food aid conundrum and Canadian aid strategy: the issue of donor control. Int J 42(3):473–508

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coate S (1995) Altruism, the Samaritan’s Dilemma, and government transfer policy. Am Econ Rev 85(1):46–57

    Google Scholar 

  • Corbett S, Fikkert B (2009) When helping hurts: how to alleviate poverty without hurting the poor...and yourself. Moody Publishers, Chicago

  • Coyne CJ (2008) After war: the political economy of exporting democracy. Stanford University Press, Stanford

    Google Scholar 

  • Easterly W (2003) Can foreign aid buy growth? J Econ Perspect 17(3):23–48

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fleury JB, Marciano A (2018) The making of a constitutionalist: James Buchanan on education. Hist Polit Econ 50(3):511–548

  • Fontaine P (2007) From philanthropy to altruism: incorporating unselfish behavior into economics, 1961–1975. Hist Polit Econ 39(1):1–46

  • Futagami R, Kamada K, Sato T (2004) Government transfers and the Samaritan’s Dilemma in the family. Public Choice 118(1/2):77–86

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibson CC, Andersson K, Ostrom E, Shivakumar S (2005) The Samaritan’s Dilemma. The political economy of development aid. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goodman NP, Herzberg RQ (2020) Gifts as governance: church welfare and the Samaritan’s Dilemma. J Inst Econ 16:703–714

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansson I, Stuart C (1989) Social security as trade among living generations. Am Econ Rev 79(5):1182–1195

  • Hirshleifer J (1977) Shakespeare versus Becker on altruism: the Importance of having the last word. J Econ Lit 15(2):500–502

  • John A, Storr VH (2009) Can the west help the rest? A review essay of Sachs’ the end of poverty and easterly’s the white man’s burden. J Priv Enterp 25(1):125–140

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonker LB, Taylor PD (1978) Evolutionarily stable strategies and game dynamics. Math Biosci 40:145–156

  • Kotlikoff LJ (1987) Justifying public provision of social security. J Policy Anal Manage 6(4):674–689

  • Lagerlof J (2004) Efficiency-enhancing signalling in the Samaritan’s dilemma. Econ J 114(492):55–68

  • Lee DR (1987) The tradeoff between equality and efficiency: short-run politics and long-run realities. Public Choice 53(2):149–165

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leeson PT (2008) Escaping poverty: foreign aid, private property, and economic development. J Priv Enterp 23(2):39–64

    Google Scholar 

  • Lindbeck A, Weibull JW (1988) Altruism and time inconsistency: the economics of fait accompli. J Polit Econ 96(6):1165–1182

  • Marciano A (2022) Sado-masochism in Buchanan’s Samaritan’s Dilemma: a constitutional perspective. Homo Œconomicus. https://doi.org/10.1007/s41412-022-00126-7

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pasour EC Jr (1991) The Samaritan's Dilemma and the welfare state. Policy, summer, pp 55–57

  • Phelps E (ed) (1975) Altruism, morality, and economic theory. Russel Sage Foundation

  • Poulsen AU, Svendsen GT (2005) Social capital and endogenous preferences. Public Choice 123(1/2):171–196

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rajan RG, Subramanian A (2005) Aid and growth: What does the cross-country evidence really show? NBER working paper w11513. https://doi.org/10.3386/w11513, http://www.nber.org/papers/w11513

  • Raschky PA, Weck-Hannemann H (2007) Charity hazard - a real hazard to natural disaster insurance? Environ Hazards 7(4):321–329

  • Schmidtchen D (1999) To help or not to help: the Samaritan’s dilemma revisited, CSLE Discussion Paper No. 99-09. Universität des Saarlandes, Center for the Study of Law and Economics (CSLE), Saarbrücken

  • Schmidtz D (2000) Islands in a sea of obligation: limits of the duty to rescue. Law Philos 19:683–705

    Google Scholar 

  • Skarbek EC (2016) Aid, ethics, and the Samaritan’s Dilemma: strategic courage in constitutional entrepreneurship. J Inst Econ 12(2):371–393

    Google Scholar 

  • Stone D (2008) The Samaritan’s Dilemma: should government help your neighbor? Nation Books

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson EA (1980) Charity and nonprofit organizations. In: Clarkson K, Martin D (eds) Economics of Non proprietary Organizations. JAI Press, Inc., Greenwich, CT, pp 125–138

  • Tullock G (1977) Economics and sociobiology: a comment. J Econ Lit 15(2):502–506

  • Veall MR (1986) Public pensions as optimal social contracts. J Public Econ 31(2):237–251

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner RE (1989) To promote the general welfare. Pacific Research Institute, San Francisco

  • Wagner RE (2005) Redistribution, poor relief, and the welfare state. In: Backhaus J, Wagner RE (eds) Handbook of public finance. Springer, Berlin, pp 385–405

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson C (2010) Exploring the failure of foreign aid: the role of incentives and information. Rev Austrian Econ 23:17–33

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alain Marciano.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

The original online version of this article was revised: Due to a production error, the affiliation details for the author Alain Marciano were incorrect. Now, it has been corrected.

Previous versions of the paper were presented at the Adam Smith Seminar (Center of Conflict of Resolution, Munich, 29 March 2021), CEPN (Predatory state, conflict and resistance, 18 June 2021), Annual conference of the Association Française d'Économie du Droit (14–15 October 2021), Nice-Nancy-Montpellier online workshop (2 December 2021), and at the Séminaire d’Économie Théorique et Appliquée (THEMA, Cergy Université, 25 octobre 2022). We thank all the participants for their comments. In particular, Benoît Le Maux, Antoine Pietri, and Mehrdad Vahabi.

Appendix 1

Appendix 1

Proof of Lemma 2

The \(\left( {x^{*} ,y^{*} } \right)\) equilibrium exists when \(x^{*}\) and \(y^{*}\) both \(\in \left( {0,1} \right)\). This, in turn, requires that two of the following conditions are simultaneously satisfied:

$$2\rho - 1 > \rho - \left( {1 - e} \right) > 0$$
(4′)
$$2\rho - 1 < \rho - \left( {1 - e} \right) < 0$$
(5′)
$$\left( {2\rho - 1} \right)\alpha - c > \rho \alpha - h - c > 0$$
(6′)
$$\left( {2\rho - 1} \right)\alpha - c < \rho \alpha - h - c < 0$$
(7′)

Rearranging condition (4′) yields condition (1); rearranging conditions (6′) and (7′) yields, respectively, conditions (8) and (9). The concluding statement in Lemma 1 follows from the fact that conditions (1) and (9) are simultaneously satisfied when the game is a Passive Samaritan’s dilemma, since both are implied by condition (3), while the parametrization defined in condition (1) is inconsistent with any of the possible combinations across conditions (4′)–(7′), so that \(\left( {x^{*} ,y^{*} } \right)\) never exists when the game is an Active Samaritan’s dilemma.□

Proof of Proposition 1

The Jacobian matrix of the system is given by:

$$J = \left( {\begin{array}{*{20}c} {{\text{d}}\dot{x}/{\text{d}}x} & {{\text{d}}\dot{x}/{\text{d}}y} \\ {{\text{d}}\dot{y}/{\text{d}}y} & {{\text{d}}\dot{y}/{\text{d}}y} \\ \end{array} } \right) = \left( {\begin{array}{*{20}c} {\left( {1 - 2x} \right)\left[ {U\left( 1 \right) - U\left( 0 \right)} \right]} & {x\left( {1 - x} \right)\left( {2\rho - 1} \right)} \\ {y\left( {1 - y} \right)\left[ {\left( {2\rho - 1} \right)\alpha - c} \right]} & {\left( {1 - 2y} \right)\left[ {V\left( 1 \right) - V\left( 0 \right)} \right]} \\ \end{array} } \right)$$

As it is well-known, a stationary point is attractive if both the eigenvalues of the Jacobian matrix evaluated at that equilibrium have negative real parts. In addition, when either of the partial derivative \({\text{d}}\dot{x}/{\text{d}}y\) and/or \({\text{d}}\dot{y}/{\text{d}}x\) is = 0—which happens whenever \(x = 0\) or \(x = 1\) and/or \(y = 0\) or \(y = 1\)—the eigenvalues exactly correspond to the partial derivatives \({\text{d}}\dot{x}/{\text{d}}x\) and \({\text{d}}\dot{y}/{\text{d}}y\). With these facts in mind, the topological properties of the four vertices \(\left( {0, 0} \right)\), \(\left( {0, 1} \right)\), \(\left( {1, 0} \right)\) and \(\left( {1, 1} \right)\) can be straightforwardly checked by evaluating the sign of \({\text{d}}\dot{x}/{\text{d}}x\) and \({\text{d}}\dot{y}/{\text{d}}y\) at each of the four vertices, since the partial derivatives \({\text{d}}\dot{x}/{\text{d}}y\) and \({\text{d}}\dot{y}/{\text{d}}x\) are always = 0 at each of these points.

At \(\left( {0,0} \right)\) we have that:

$${\text{d}}\dot{x}/{\text{d}}x = 1 - e - \rho$$
$${\text{d}}\dot{y}/{\text{d}}y = h + c - \rho \alpha$$

Hence, we have three cases:

  1. 1.

    if \(1 - e - \rho < 0\) and \(h + c - \rho \alpha < 0\), \(\left( {0,0} \right)\) is a sink (asymptotically stable).

  2. 2.

    If \(1 - e - \rho > 0\) and \(h + c - \rho \alpha > 0\), \(\left( {0,0} \right)\) is source (asymptotically unstable).

  3. 3.

    If \(1 - e - \rho < 0\) and \(h + c - \rho \alpha > 0\), or \(1 - e - \rho > 0\) and \(h + c - \rho \alpha < 0\), \(\left( {0,0} \right)\) is a saddle (asymptotically unstable).

Given Lemma 1, when the game is either an Active or a Passive Samaritan’s Dilemma, \(\left( {0,0} \right)\) is always a sink.

At \(\left( {1,1} \right)\) we have that:

$$\begin{aligned} {\text{d}}\dot{x}/{\text{d}}x & = e - \rho \\ {\text{d}}\dot{y}/{\text{d}}y & = \alpha \left( {1 - \rho } \right) - h \\ \end{aligned}$$

Hence, we have three cases:

  1. 1.

    if \(e - \rho < 0\) and \(\alpha \left( {1 - \rho } \right) - h < 0\), \(\left( {1,1} \right)\) is a sink (asymptotically stable).

  2. 2.

    If \(e - \rho > 0\) and \(\alpha \left( {1 - \rho } \right) - h > 0\), \(\left( {1,1} \right)\) is source (asymptotically unstable).

  3. 3.

    If \(e - \rho < 0\) and \(\alpha \left( {1 - \rho } \right) - h > 0\) or \(e - \rho > 0\) and \(\alpha \left( {1 - \rho } \right) - h < 0\), \(\left( {1,1} \right)\) is a saddle (asymptotically unstable).

Given Lemma 1, when the game is an Active Samaritan’s Dilemma, \(\left( {1,1} \right)\) is always a saddle; when the game is a Passive Samaritan’s Dilemma, \(\left( {1,1} \right)\) is always a sink.

At \(\left( {1,0} \right)\) we have that

$$\begin{aligned} {\text{d}}\dot{x}/{\text{d}}x & = \rho + e - 1 \\ {\text{d}}\dot{y}/{\text{d}}y & = h - \left( {1 - \rho } \right)\alpha \\ \end{aligned}$$

Hence, we have three cases:

  1. 1.

    if \(\rho + e - 1 < 0\) and \(h - \left( {1 - \rho } \right)\alpha < 0\), \(\left( {1,0} \right)\) is a sink (asymptotically stable).

  2. 2.

    If \(\rho + e - 1 > 0\) and \(h - \left( {1 - \rho } \right)\alpha > 0\), \(\left( {1,0} \right)\) is source (asymptotically unstable).

  3. 3.

    If \(\rho + e - 1 < 0\) and \(h - \left( {1 - \rho } \right)\alpha > 0\), or \(\rho + e - 1 > 0\) and \(h - \left( {1 - \rho } \right)\alpha < 0\), \(\left( {0,1} \right)\) is a saddle (asymptotically unstable).

Given Lemma 1, when the game is an Active Samaritan’s Dilemma, \(\left( {1,0} \right)\) is always a saddle; when the game is a Passive Samaritan’s Dilemma, \(\left( {1,0} \right)\) is always a source.

At \(\left( {0,1} \right)\) we have that

$$\begin{aligned} {\text{d}}\dot{x}/{\text{d}}x & = \rho - e \\ {\text{d}}\dot{y}/{\text{d}}y & = \rho \alpha - h - c \\ \end{aligned}$$

Hence, we have three cases:

  1. 1.

    if \(\rho - e < 0\) and \(\rho \alpha - h - c < 0\), \(\left( {0,1} \right)\) is a sink (asymptotically stable).

  2. 2.

    If \(\rho - e > 0\) and \(\rho \alpha - h - c > 0\), \(\left( {0,1} \right)\) is source (asymptotically unstable).

  3. 3.

    If \(\rho - e < 0\) and \(\rho \alpha - h - c > 0\), or \(\rho - e > 0\) and \(\rho \alpha - h - c < 0\), \(\left( {0,1} \right)\) is a saddle (asymptotically unstable).

Given Lemma 1, when the game is an Active Samaritan’s Dilemma, \(\left( {0,1} \right)\) is always a saddle; when the game is a Passive Samaritan’s Dilemma, \(\left( {0,1} \right)\) is always a source.

To prove the stability properties of the \(\left( {x^{*} ,y^{*} } \right)\) equilibrium, we study its Trace and Determinant and see that:

$${\text{TR}}\,J_{{(x^{*} ,y^{*} )}} = 0\,{\text{and}}\,{\text{Det}}\,J_{{(x^{*} ,y^{*} )}} = - x^{*} (1 - x^{*} )y(1 - y^{*} )[(2\rho - 1)\alpha - c](2\rho - 1)$$

From Lemma 1, we already know that \(\left( {2\rho - 1} \right)\alpha - c > 0\) and \(2\rho - 1 > 0\) are simultaneously satisfied when condition (3) is satisfied. In this case, \({\text{Det }}J_{{\left( {x^{*} ,y^{*} } \right)}} < 0\), which proves that \(\left( {x^{*} ,y^{*} } \right)\) is a saddle when the game is a Passive Samaritan’s dilemma. In addition, there exists parametrizations for which \({\text{Det }}J_{{\left( {x^{*} ,y^{*} } \right)}} \ge 0\), which completes the Proof of Proposition 1.□

Proof of Proposition 2

From the results in Proposition 1, it is straightforward to derive the following set of results. First, the existence conditions of the four monostable regimes are as follows:

  1. 1.

    The stationary point \(\left( {0,0} \right)\) is the unique attractor iff \(e > \max \left\{ {\rho ,1 - \rho } \right\}\) and \(\alpha > \max \left\{ {\frac{h}{1 - \rho },\frac{h + c}{e}} \right\}\).

  2. 2.

    The stationary point \(\left( {1,1} \right)\) is the unique attractor iff \(e < \min \left\{ {\rho ,1 - \rho } \right\}\) and \(\alpha < \min \left\{ {\frac{h}{1 - \rho },\frac{h + c}{e}} \right\}\).

  3. 3.

    The stationary point \(\left( {1,0} \right)\) is the unique attractor iff \(e < \min \left\{ {\rho ,1 - \rho } \right\}\) and \(\alpha > \max \left\{ {\frac{h}{1 - \rho },\frac{h + c}{e}} \right\}\).

  4. 4.

    The stationary point \(\left( {0,1} \right)\) is the unique attractor iff \(e > \max \left\{ {\rho ,1 - \rho } \right\}\) and \(\alpha < \min \left\{ {\frac{h}{1 - \rho },\frac{h + c}{e}} \right\}\)

Second, the existence conditions of the two bistable regimes are as follows:

  1. 1.

    The stationary points \(\left( {0,0} \right)\) and \(\left( {1,1} \right)\) simultaneously attract iff conditions (1) and (9) are simultaneously satisfied.

  2. 2.

    The stationary points \(\left( {1,0} \right)\) and \(\left( {0,1} \right)\) simultaneously attract iff simultaneously attract iff conditions (7) and (8) are simultaneously satisfied.

Third, the existence conditions of the two cyclical regimes are as follows:

  1. 1.

    The system exhibits cyclical behavior with counterclockwise oscillations around \(\left( {x^{*} ,y^{*} } \right)\) iff conditions (7) and (9) are simultaneously satisfied.

  2. 2.

    The system exhibits cyclical behavior with clockwise oscillations around \(\left( {x^{*} ,y^{*} } \right)\) iff conditions (1) and (8) are simultaneously satisfied.

Observe that when the game is an Active Samaritan’s Dilemma, the monostable regime featuring \(\left( {0,0} \right)\) as the only attractor results; when the game is a Passive Samaritan’s Dilemma, the bistable regime featuring \(\left( {0,0} \right)\) and \(\left( {1,1} \right)\) as attractors result.□

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and Permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Dughera, S., Marciano, A. Inside Buchanan's Samaritan's Dilemma: altruism, strategic courage and ethics of responsibility. Econ Gov 24, 207–233 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10101-023-00292-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10101-023-00292-7

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation