Skip to main content
Log in

When are committees of Condorcet winners Condorcet winning committees?

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Review of Economic Design Aims and scope Submit manuscript

A Correction to this article was published on 12 October 2021

This article has been updated

Abstract

We consider seat-posted (or designated-seat) committee elections, where disjoint sets of candidates compete for each seat. We assume that each voter has a collection of seat-wise strict rankings of candidates, which are extended to a strict ranking of committees by means of a preference extension. We investigate conditions upon preference extensions for which seat-wise Condorcet candidates, whenever all exist, form the Condorcet winner among committees. We characterize the domain of neutral preference extensions for which the committee of seat-wise winners is the Condorcet winning committee, first assuming the latter exists (Theorem 1) and then relaxing this assumption (Theorem 2). Neutrality means that preference extensions are not sensitive to the names of candidates. Moreover, we show that these two characterizations can be stated regardless of which preference level is considered as a premise.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Change history

Notes

  1. A good real-life example of the difficulties brought by the presence of preferential dependencies is provided in Ratliff (2006). See also Hodge and Schwallier (2006) for a detailed analysis of preferential dependencies in multiple referenda.

  2. The reader may refer to Lang and Xia (2016) for a review of methods that partially overcome the trade-off between expressivity and costs.

  3. A preference over committees is separable if there exists a set of seat-wise rankings such that for any two committees disagreeing on a single seat, the preferred one is comprising the more preferred candidate for that seat.

  4. This result extends previous ones obtained for multiple referenda. In particular, (Özkal-Sanver and Sanver 2006) show that if preferences over committees are separable, every anonymous seat-based procedure is Pareto inefficient. For the same setting, Cuhadaroglu and Lainé (2012) show that the committee formed by seat-wise plurality winners is Pareto-optimal at any profile of (separable) preferences over committees if and only if these preferences emanate from the Hamming distance criterion.

  5. A generalization of the Ostrogorski paradox is analyzed in Laffond and Lainé (2009). Furthermore, Laffond and Lainé (2012) show that the committee of seat-wise plurality winners may also fail at implementing a compromise solution.

  6. If a voter’s ideal committee is A, the Hamming distance between A and another committee B is the number of seats with different appointed candidates.

  7. A detailed argument is provided in Sect. 6.

  8. A CCG is exposed to several paradoxes (see Ratliff 2003; Diss and Mahajne 2020). Studies of voting methods selecting a CCG can be found in Barberà and Coelho (2008), Kamwa and Merlin (2015), Diss and Doghmi (2016), Aziz et al. (2017), Kamwa (2017a, 2017b), Diss et al. (2020) and Bubboloni et al. (2020).

  9. In this context, a preference extension maps every ranking of candidates to a ranking of sets of candidates. Kamwa and Merlin (2018) consider the Leximin and the Leximax preference extensions.

  10. A preliminary step towards the answer is provided in Kamwa and Merlin (2018), who prove that if preferences over committees are separable, a CCG coincides with the CCF if the latter exists.

  11. The reader may refer to Ratliff and Saari (2014), who analyze at-large committee selection methods that address diversity constraints such as gender balance.

  12. Another example of a lexicographic preference extension is given by the choice problem defined above Definition 3. In this example, \(\delta ^{i}\) is q-lexicographic with 1 q 2.

  13. Under neutrality, a preference extension generates a unique committee preference up to a reshuffling of candidates’ names.

  14. This simple remark already appears in Benoît and Kornhauser (1991) and is discussed in Kamwa and Merlin (2018) for at-large committees.

  15. By Lemma 3 a responsive preference extension induces a separable committee preference. The fact that a profile of separable preference generates a separable majority preference and its consequences are emphasized in particular by Kadane (1972), Koehler (1975), Miller (1975), Hollard and Le Breton (1996) and Vidu (2002).

  16. As this relabelling does not interact with the one made above, it does not imply any loss of generality.

  17. We write the projection of \(C_{k}\) to \(\{k^{*},\ldots ,k\}\) as \( C_{k}\mid _{\{k^{*},\dots ,k\}}\)instead of \(C_{k\{k^{*},\dots ,k\}}\) in order to avoid a too heavy notation.

  18. Intuitively, \(q_{\delta }\) defines a priority ordering over seats. Observe that the definition of \(\delta |_{\Omega }\) induces the inverse of this priority order. This expresses the fact that if seat s is given lower priority than seat \(s^{\prime }\), and when starting from the best rank vector \(\overrightarrow{1}\), losing one rank in s should be less harmful than losing one rank in \(s^{\prime }\).

  19. Observe that one cannot have \(s^{*}=S\), since \(\delta \) is responsive.

  20. Note that if \(s^{*}=1\), the designated columns for \(1\le s<s^{*}-1\) in preferences are redundant. And also straightforward changes are required in the notation, e.g., \((\overset{s^{*}-1}{\overbrace{1,...,1}},\overset{ i}{\overbrace{2,...,2}},1,\overset{S-s^{*}-i}{\overbrace{2,...,2}})\) becomes \((\overset{i}{\overbrace{2,...,2}},1,\overset{S-s^{*}-i}{ \overbrace{2,...,2}})\).

  21. Observe that one may have \(\forall {\mathbf {P}}\in {\mathcal {L}}_{{\mathcal {C}}}\), \(\varepsilon ({\mathbf {P}})\in {\mathbb {L}}\). For instance, denote by \(A^{*}( {\mathbf {P}})\) the first-best committee according to \({\mathbf {P}}\), and define \( P_{s}^{i}\) by \(\forall s\in {\mathcal {S}}, \forall a_{s},b_{s}\in {\mathcal {C}} _{s}\), \(a_{s} \varepsilon _{s}({\mathbf {P}}) b_{s} \Leftrightarrow [a_{s},A^{*}({\mathbf {P}})_{-s}] {\mathbf {P}}^{i} [b_{s},A^{*}({\mathbf {P}})_{-s}]\). With words, for any seat s, we elicit voter i ’s preferences for two different candidates \(a_{s}\) and \(b_{s}\) by considering all committees which overlap the first-best committee for all but seat s. If \({\mathbf {P}}\) ranks the committee comprising \(a_{s}\) above the one comprising \(b_{s}\), we say that i prefers \(a_{s}\) to \(b_{s}\). This elicitation method generalizes the one above by allowing to pick different reference committees for different seats. However, for the elicitation maps characterized in our results, some committee preferences are mapped to \( {\triangle }\).

  22. The reader may refer to Gehrlein and Lepelley (2017) for an overview of the main probabilistic approaches.

References

  • Aslan F, Dindar H, Lainé J (2019) Choosing a committee under majority voting. In: Morais D, Carreras A, de Almeida A, Vetschera R (eds) Group decision and negotiation: behavior, models, and support. GDN 2019. Lecture notes in business information processing, vol 351. Springer, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Aziz H, Elkind E, Faliszewski, P, Lackner M, Skowron, P (2017) The Condorcet principle for multiwinner election: from short listing to proportionality. In: Proceedings of the twenty-sixth international joint conference on artificial intelligence (IJCAI-17), pp 84–90

  • Barberà S, Coelho D (2008) How to choose a non-controversial list with k names. Soc Choice Welf 31:79–96

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benoît J-P, Kornhauser LA (1991) Voting simply in the election of assemblies. Starr Center for Applied Economics. Working paper #91-32, New York University, CV

  • Benoît J-P, Kornhauser LA (2010) Only a dictatorship is efficient. Games Econom Behav 70:261–270

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernholz P (1973) Logrolling, arrow-paradox and cyclical majorities. Public Choice 15:87–95

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bezembinder T, van Acker P (1985) The ostrogorski paradox and its relation to nontransitive choice. J Math Sociol 11:131–58

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Black D (1948) On the rationale of group decision-making. J Polit Econ 56:23–34

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bubboloni D, Diss M, Gori M (2020) Extensions of the Simpson voting rule to the committee selection setting. Public Choice 183:151–185

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cuhadaroglu T, Lainé J (2012) Pareto efficiency in multiple referendum. Theor Decis 72:525–536

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daudt H, Rae D (1976) The Ostrogorski paradox: a peculiarity of compound majority decision. Eur J Polit Res 4:391–398

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deb R, Kelsey D (1987) On constructing a generalized Ostrogorski paradox: necessary and sufficient conditions. Math Soc Sci 14:161–174

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diss M, Doghmi A (2016) Multi-winner scoring election methods: Condorcet consistency and paradoxes. Public Choice 169:97–116

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diss M, Mahajne M (2020) Social acceptability of Condorcet committees. Math Soc Sci 105:14–27

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diss M, Kamwa E, Tlidi A (2020) On some k-scoring rules for committee elections: agreement and Condorcet principle. Revue d’Economie Politique 130(5):699–725

  • Elkind E, Faliszewski P, Skowron P, Slinko A (2017) Properties of multiwinner scoring rules. Soc Choice Welf 48:599–632

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn PC (1981) An analysis of simple voting systems for electing committees. SIAM J Appl Math 41:499–502

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gehrlein WV (1985) The Condorcet criterion and committee selection. Math Soc Sci 10:199–209

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gehrlein WV, Lepelley D (2017) Elections, voting rules and paradoxical outcomes. Studies in social choice and welfare. Springer, Berlin

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hodge JK, Schwallier P (2006) How does separability affect the desirability of referendum election outcomes? Theor Decis 61:251–276

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hollard G, Le Breton M (1996) Logrolling and a McGarvey theorem for separable tournaments. Soc Choice Welf 13:451–455

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kadane JB (1972) On division of the question. Public Choice 13:47–54

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kamwa E (2017) On stable rules for selecting committees. J Math Econ 70:36–44

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kamwa E (2017) Stable rules for electing committees and divergence on outcomes. Group Decis Negot 26(3):547–564

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kamwa E, Merlin V (2015) Scoring rules over subsets of alternatives: consistency and paradoxes. J Math Econ 61:130–138

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kamwa E, Merlin V (2018) Coincidence of Condorcet committees. Soc Choice Welf 50:171–189

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaymak B, Sanver MR (2003) Sets of alternatives as Condorcet winners. Soc Choice Welf 20:477–494

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koehler DH (1975) Vote trading and the voting paradox: a proof of logical equivalence. Am Polit Sci Rev 69:954–960

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laffond G, Lainé J (2006) Single-switch preferences and the Ostrogorski paradox. Math Soc Sci 52:49–66

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laffond G, Lainé J (2009) Condorcet choice and the Ostrogorski paradox. Soc Choice Welf 32:317–333

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laffond G, Lainé J (2012) Searching for a compromise in multiple referendum. Group Decis Negot 21:551–569

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lang J, Xia L (2016) Voting on combinatorial domains. In: Brandt F, Conitzer V, Endriss U, Lang J, Procaccia AD (eds) Handbook of computational social choice. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 197–221

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Miller NR (1975) Logrolling and the arrow paradox: a note. Public Choice 21:107–110

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moulin H (1988) Axioms for cooperative decision-making. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Özkal-Sanver I, Sanver MR (2006) Ensuring Pareto optimality by referendum voting. Soc Choice Welf 27:211–219

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ratliff TC (2003) Some startling inconsistencies when electing committees. Soc Choice Welf 21:433–454

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ratliff TC (2006) Selecting committees. Public Choice 126:343–355

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ratliff TC, Saari DG (2014) Complexities of electing diverse committees. Soc Choice Welf 43:55–71

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vidu L (1999) An extension of a theorem on the aggregation of separable preferences. Soc Choice Welf 16:159–167

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vidu L (2002) Majority cycles in a multi-dimensional setting. Econ Theor 20:373–386

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Funding was provided by Istanbul Bilgi University (Grant No. BILGI Research Development Innovation Programme, POlarization viewed from SOcial choice Perspective (POSOP)) National Research Development and Innovation Office (Grant No. TKP2020, National Challenges Program, BME NC TKP2020).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jean Lainé.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Authors are grateful to two reviewers for their valuable comments and suggestions. This research has been partially funded by the BILGI Research Development Innovation Programme, POlarization viewed from SOcial choice Perspective (POSOP), and the “TKP2020, National Challenges Program” of the National Research Development and Innovation Office (BME NC TKP2020).

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Aslan, F., Dindar, H. & Lainé, J. When are committees of Condorcet winners Condorcet winning committees?. Rev Econ Design 26, 417–446 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10058-021-00260-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10058-021-00260-9

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation