Skip to main content
Log in

Neutral freedom and freedom as control

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Social Choice and Welfare Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I present a model of freedom as control. Control is measured by the preferences of a decision-maker, or judge, who values flexibility and is neutral towards outcomes ex ante. Formally, I explore the consequences of adding a neutrality axiom to the Dekel et al. (Econometrica 69(4):891–934, 2001) axioms for preference for flexibility. I characterize the consensus of all neutral judges about which choice situations embody more freedom. The theory extends the freedom ranking literature to situations where agents have imperfect control, as modeled by choices among lotteries. In a voting context, the consensus of neutral judges coincides with Banzhaf power.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. To say that we should be neutral about the value of alternatives is not to say that no value judgments are involved. See Sect. 3.3. Neutrality is conditioned on certain normative presuppositions.

  2. In his work on measuring freedom, Carter (1999) emphasizes the distinction between the value of specific freedoms and value of overall freedom, and proposes a measure of overall freedom that abstracts from the values of specific freedoms.

  3. Sen (1985, 1991) also discussed the relation of freedom to flexibility.

  4. This is an exaggeration.

  5. The version of the axioms I present here are slightly different than that presented in Dekel et al. (2001). The monotonicity axiom is the same as in Dekel et al. (2001), but the continuity and independence axioms differ. The independence axiom of Dekel et al. (2001) differs in that (1) it is formulated with respect to strict preference and (2) it contains only the \(\Rightarrow\) direction of Axiom 4 below. In conjunction, the axioms presented here characterize the same preferences as the axioms in Dekel et al. (2001). The reason for the difference is that my main result, Theorem 1, appeals to a representation theorem for preference for flexibility with incomplete preferences due to Kochov (2007) and Galaabaatar (2010), and so I use the versions of independence and monotonicity used in those papers. The differences only matter when preferences are incomplete.

  6. The formulation of the axiom is different than in Dekel et al. (2001). See footnote 6.

  7. The theorem continues to hold despite the slightly different formulation of the axioms. See footnote 6.

  8. The representation (3) is not unique—multiple probability measures p correspond to the same preferences \(\preccurlyeq\). Dekel et al. (2001) restrict attention to a subset of utility functions U satisfying certain normalizations and thereby attain a unique representation. Uniqueness is not important for my purposes.

  9. This example previously appeared in Sher (2018a).

  10. I mention this last fact just to emphasize that in Scenarios A and B below, if the agent goes to prison, it will be the same prison in both scenarios.

  11. In this example we identify the options c and s with the degenerate lotteries that put probability one on each of these two options.

  12. It is not entirely obvious because one might say that both menus allow no freedom, and so are equivalent in that sense. A counterargument would be that bliss is much more choiceworthy than suffering; there are many more situations in which an agent would or should choose bliss rather than suffering if given the choice. Moreover, even if one accepts that the singleton menus \(\left\{ \textit{suffering}\right\}\) and \(\left\{ \textit{bliss}\right\}\) are equivalent in terms of freedom in that they allow no freedom, one might not accept the stronger implication of neutrality that it is equivalent in terms of freedom to interchange suffering and bliss in every menu. In arguing against the cardinality order of Pattanaik and Xu (1990), Sen (1990) argues similarly that the choiceworthiness of alternatives is relevant to the freedom allowed by a menu.

  13. Sher (2015) is an earlier working paper version of the current paper. The weakenings of the neutrality axiom can be found in Sect. 6 of that version. The paper can be found at https://drive.google.com/file/d/18ORLZcVTlKnGHYynSNLvGkkfYmoRJkGQ/view?usp=sharing.

  14. Nehring and Puppe (2008) also applies the attribute approach to freedom of choice.

  15. Sher (2018a) does not explicitly consider applying neutrality within each category of freedom; the paper focuses rather on assigning different values to different freedoms (either in the same or in different categories). The approach would however be consistent with applying neutrality within categories.

  16. For example, consider the 27 possible ways of assigning the utilities \(-1,0,\) and 2 to the different candidates allowing that different candidates may be assigned the same utility. If each of these 27 assignments is viewed as equiprobable, that would amount to a different situation of symmetric uncertainty.

  17. For the formal definition of what it means to take a weighted average of menus, see (2) in Sect. 2.2, and the discussion surrounding (2).

  18. Let us consider two particular neutral judges who disagree about these two menus. When neutral judge 1’s specific preferences are realized, judge 1 assigns utility 1 to one alternative and utility 0 to the other two alternatives. For each of the three alternatives, there is a \(\frac{1}{3}\) probability that judge 1 will assign utility 1 to that alterntative. When neutral judge 2’s specific preferences are realized, judge 2 assigns utility 0 to one alternative and utility 1 to the other two alternatives. For each of the three alternatives, there is a \(\frac{1}{3}\) probability that neutral judge 2 will assign utility 0 to that alternative. Judge 1 attains an expected utility of \(\frac{2}{3}\) from having access to \(M_1\) and an expected utility of \(\frac{7}{9}\) from having access to \(M_2\). So judge 1 prefers \(M_2\). Judge 2 attains an expected utility of 1 from having access to \(M_1\) and an expected utility of \(\frac{8}{9}\) from having access to \(M_2\). So judge 2 prefers \(M_1\). Judge 1 and judge 2 disagree.

  19. See in particular Sect. 3.2 and Corollary 1.

  20. The repetitions occur because each of the two lotteries contain only two distinct probabilities—in this case 0 and 1. If one of the two lotteries contained three distinct probabilities, as in the menu \(M=\left\{ \left( 1,0,0\right) ,\left( \frac{1}{2},\frac{1}{3},\frac{1}{6}\right) \right\}\), there would be no repetitions.

  21. Some red points on the right hand side can be arrived at in multiple ways. This is a general feature which is not particular to the menu in this example because for any menu M and all \(\ell \in M\), \(\frac{1}{n!} \sum _{\pi \in \Pi } \ell ^\pi = \left( \frac{1}{n},\frac{1}{n},\ldots ,\frac{1}{n}\right)\).

  22. It follows that if one rejects some comparison made by the symmetry order, one must reject one of the axioms characterizing freedom.

  23. The symmetry order is referred to as the grading order in Sher (2015).

  24. The cardinality order ranks one deterministic menu above another if and only if the former contains more elements.

  25. A preorder \(\preccurlyeq\) is a reflexive and transitive relation.

  26. A preorder \(\preccurlyeq _0\) is coarser than a preorder \(\preccurlyeq _1\) if for all \(M,M' \in {\mathscr {M}}, M' \preccurlyeq _0 M \Rightarrow M' \preccurlyeq _1 M\).

  27. For example, if \(M_2\) contains two lotteries and \(M_3\) contains three lotteries, but the convex hull of \(M_3\) is a proper subset of the convex hull of \(M_2\), then \(M_2\) allows more freedom than \(M_3\) according to the symmetry order.

  28. \(z \le z'\) means that for all i, \(z_i \le z'_i\).

  29. In the case that the voting mechanism is deterministic (i.e., \(\alpha (z) \in \{0,1\}, \forall z\)) , it is obvious that (9) represents the probability of being pivotal. In the Appendix, I explain why we can also regard (9) as the probability of being pivotal in stochastic mechanisms.

  30. In Sher (2018a), I present a general framework for evaluating freedom in games.

  31. In this paper, I have assumed that a menu is a closed set of lotteries over alternatives. In (12), I allow all subsets of \(\left[ 0,1\right]\). If I had here restricted to closed subsets of \(\left[ 0,1\right]\), the \(\sup\) in (12) could be replaced by \(\max\).

  32. The critical thing here is not the menus contain two lotteries, but rather that the lotteries in the menus are over two outcomes.

  33. Strictly speaking the condition is that all expected utility maximizers prefer P to Q given any prior beliefs.

  34. Since the preordered flexibility axioms imply that a menu is indifferent to its convex hull, nothing substantive would change if we substituted the set of randomized strategies for the set of pure strategies \(\Sigma\) used in the above construction.

  35. See Sect. 6.

  36. Specifically, only the \(\Leftarrow\) direction employs the separating hyperplane theorem. If \(S\left( M\right) \not \subseteq S\left( M'\right)\), then there exists \(\ell \in S\left( M\right) {\setminus } S\left( M'\right)\), and then the strong separating hyperplane theorem implies that \(\ell\) and \(G(M')\) can be strongly separated.

  37. It is straightforward to confirm that when \(p^\pi\) is defined in this way, then \(p^\pi\) indeed belongs to \(\Delta ^*\left( U\right)\).

References

  • Arrow KJ (1995) A note on freedom and flexibility. Choice, welfare and development: a festschrift in honour of Amartya K. Sen, 7–15

  • Banzhaf JF (1964) Weighted voting doesn’t work: a mathematical analysis. Rutgers Law Rev 19:317–343

    Google Scholar 

  • Banzhaf JF (1968) One man, 3.312 votes: a mathematical analysis of the electoral college. Villanova Law Rev 13:304–332

    Google Scholar 

  • Barbera S, Bossert W, Pattanaik PK (2004) Ranking sets of objects. In: Barbera S, Hammond P, Seidl C (eds) Handbook of utility theory, vol 2. Springer, Berlin, pp 893–977

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Blackwell D (1951) Comparison of experiments. In: Neyman J (ed) Proceedings of the second Berkeley symposium on mathematical statistics and probability. University of California Press, California, pp 93–102

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackwell D (1953) Equivalent comparisons of experiments. Ann Math Stat 24:265–272

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carter I (1999) A measure of freedom. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dekel E, Lipman BL, Rustichini A (2001) Representing preferences with a unique subjective state space. Econometrica 69(4):891–934

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dubey P, Shapley LS (1979) Mathematical properties of the Banzhaf power index. Math Oper Res 4(2):99–131

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Felsenthal D, Machover M (1998) The measurement of voting power. Edward Elgar, UK

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Galaabaatar T (2010) Menu choice without completeness. Unpublished manuscript

  • Jones P, Sugden R (1982) Evaluating choice. Int Rev Law Econ 2(1):47–65

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kochov A (2007) Subjective states without the completeness axiom. Unpublished Manuscript, University of Rochester

  • Kreps DM (1979) A representation theorem for “preference for flexibility”. Econometrica 47:565–577

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nehring K (1999) Preference for flexibility in a Savage framework. Econometrica 67(1):101–119

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nehring K, Puppe C (2002) A theory of diversity. Econometrica 70(3):1155–1198

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nehring K, Puppe C (2008) Diversity and the metric of opportunity. Working paper

  • Pattanaik PK, Xu Y (1990) On ranking opportunity sets in terms of freedom of choice. Recherches Économiques de Louvain/Louvain Econ Rev 56(3–4):383–390

    Google Scholar 

  • Pattanaik PK, Xu Y (1998) On preference and freedom. Theor Decis 44(2):173–198

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen A (1985) Commodities and capabilities. North-Holland

  • Sen A (1990) Welfare, freedom and social choice: a reply. Recherches Économiques de Louvain/Louvain Econ Rev 56(3–4):451–485

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen A (1991) Welfare, preference and freedom. J Econ 50(1):15–29

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen A (1993) Markets and freedoms: achievements and limitations of the market mechanism in promoting individual freedoms. Oxford Economic Papers, pp 519–541

  • Sher I (2015) Neutral freedom and freedom as control. Unpublished Manuscript. https://drive.google.com/file/d/18ORLZcVTlKnGHYynSNLvGkkfYmoRJkGQ/view?usp=sharing

  • Sher I (2018a) Evaluating allocations of freedom. Econ J 128(612):F65–F94

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sher I (2018b) Freedom and voting power. Available at SSRN https://ssrn.com/abstract=3219554

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Itai Sher.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Appendix: Proofs and technical comments

Appendix: Proofs and technical comments

1.1 Proof of Proposition 2

Let \(\Delta ^*_{\text{ sym }}\left( U\right)\) be the set of symmetric probability measures in \(\Delta ^*\left( U\right)\).

Lemma A.1

Suppose that \(\preccurlyeq\) has a representation of the form (5) with some \(p \in \Delta ^*\left( U\right)\). Then \(\preccurlyeq\) has a representation of the form (5) with some \(p \in \Delta ^*_{\text{ sym }}\left( U\right)\) if and only if \(\preccurlyeq\) satisfies neutrality.

Proof

For any \(p \in \Delta ^*\left( U\right)\) and \(\pi \in \Pi\), define \(p^{\pi } \in \Delta ^*(U)\) by:

$$\begin{aligned} p^\pi \left( S\right) := p\left( S^\pi \right) , \;\;\; \forall \text{ measurable } S. \end{aligned}$$

Choose any \(M \in {\mathscr {M}}\) and \(\pi \in \Pi\). The neutrality axiom holds if and only if

$$\begin{aligned} \int \max _{\ell \in M} \left( u \cdot \ell \right) p\left( du\right)&= \int \max _{\ell \in M^\pi } \left( u \cdot \ell \right) p\left( du\right) , \;\;\; \forall \pi \in \Pi , \;\forall M \in {\mathscr {M}}. \end{aligned}$$
(A.1)

Next observe that

$$\begin{aligned} \begin{aligned} \int \max _{\ell \in M^\pi } \left( u \cdot \ell \right) p\left( du\right)&= \int \max _{\ell \in M} \left( u \cdot \ell ^\pi \right) p\left( du\right) = \int \max _{\ell \in M} \left( u^{\pi ^{-1}} \cdot \ell \right) p\left( du\right) \\&= \int \max _{\ell \in M} \left( u \cdot \ell \right) p^\pi \left( du\right) . \end{aligned} \end{aligned}$$
(A.2)

In other words, if we consider an agent who values flexibility and faces menu M, permuting the menu M according to \(\pi\) leads to the same ex ante expected utility as permuting the agent’s current uncertainty p over her fututre utility at the time of choice according to \(\pi\).

It follows that (A.1) is equivalent to

$$\begin{aligned} \int \max _{\ell \in M} \left( u \cdot \ell \right) p\left( du\right)&= \int \max _{\ell \in M} \left( u \cdot \ell \right) p^\pi \left( du\right) , \;\;\; \forall \pi \in \Pi , \;\forall M \in {\mathscr {M}}. \end{aligned}$$
(A.3)

Define \({\bar{p}} = \frac{1}{n!} \sum _{\pi \in \Pi } p^\pi\). (A.3) implies that

$$\begin{aligned} \int \max _{\ell \in M} \left( u \cdot \ell \right) p\left( du\right) = \frac{1}{n!} \sum _{\pi \in \Pi }\int \max _{\ell \in M} \left( u \cdot \ell \right) p^\pi \left( du\right) = \int \max _{\ell \in M} \left( u \cdot \ell \right) {\bar{p}}\left( du\right) . \end{aligned}$$
(A.4)

Observe that if \(p \in \Delta ^*\left( U\right)\), then \({\bar{p}} \in \Delta ^*_{\text{ sym }}\left( U\right)\). So we have established that (A.3) implies that

$$\begin{aligned} \exists p' \in \Delta^* _{\text{ sym }}\left( U\right) , \forall M \in {\mathscr {M}}, \;\;\; \int \max _{\ell \in M} \left( u \cdot \ell \right) p\left( du\right) = \int \max _{\ell \in M} \left( u \cdot \ell \right) p'\left( du\right) . \end{aligned}$$
(A.5)

On the other hand assume (A.5) holds; then (A.3) holds with \(p'\) taking the role of p. It follows that if \(\int \max _{\ell \in M} \left( u \cdot \ell \right) p\left( du\right)\) represents \(\preccurlyeq\), then neutrality is equivalent to (A.5), which establishes the lemma. \(\square\)

Suppose that \(\preccurlyeq\) satisfies the weak order, continuity, monotonicity, independence, and neutrality axioms. Then Proposition 1 and Lemma A.1 imply that \(\preccurlyeq\) has the desired representation. Conversely, assume that \(\preccurlyeq\) has a representation of the form (5) with some \(p^* \in \Delta ^*_{\text{ sym }}\left( U\right)\). Then Proposition 1 and Lemma A.1 imply that \(\preccurlyeq\) satisfies all of the axioms. \(\square\)

1.2 Proof of Theorem 1

Lemma A.2

For all \(M, M' \in {\mathscr {M}}\), \(M \preccurlyeq ^* M'\) if and only if:

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{1}{n!} \sum _{\pi \in \Pi } \max _{\ell \in M} (u^\pi \cdot \ell ) \le \frac{1}{n!} \sum _{\pi \in \Pi } \max _{\ell \in M'} (u^\pi \cdot \ell ),\;\;\forall u \in {\mathbb {R}}^n. \end{aligned}$$
(A.6)

Proof

First observe that for all \(M \in {\mathscr {M}}\),

$$\begin{aligned} \begin{aligned} \max _{\ell \in S\left( M\right) } u \cdot \ell&= \max _{\left( \ell \left( \pi \right) : \pi \in \Pi \right) \in \times _{\pi \in \Pi } \text{ co }\left( M^\pi \right) } u \cdot \left[ \frac{1}{n!}\sum _{\pi \in \Pi } \ell \left( \pi \right) \right] \\&= \max _{\left( \ell \left( \pi \right) : \pi \in \Pi \right) \in \times _{\pi \in \Pi } \text{ co }\left( M^\pi \right) } \left[ \frac{1}{n!}\sum _{\pi \in \Pi } u \cdot \ell (\pi )\right] = \frac{1}{n!} \sum _{\pi \in \Pi } \max _{\ell \in \text{ co }\left( M\right) } \left( u \cdot \ell ^\pi \right) \\&= \frac{1}{n!} \sum _{\pi \in \Pi } \max _{\ell \in \text{ co }\left( M\right) } \left( u^{\pi ^{-1}} \cdot \ell \right) = \frac{1}{n!} \sum _{\pi \in \Pi } \max _{\ell \in \text{ co }(M)} \left( u^\pi \cdot \ell \right) . \end{aligned} \end{aligned}$$
(A.7)

So

$$\begin{aligned} M \preccurlyeq ^* M' \Leftrightarrow S\left( M\right) \subseteq S\left( M'\right) \Leftrightarrow \left( \max _{\ell \in S\left( M\right) } u \cdot \ell \le \max _{\ell \in S\left( M'\right) } u \cdot \ell , \;\; \forall u \in {\mathbb {R}}^n \right) \Leftrightarrow {(A.6)}, \end{aligned}$$

where the second equivalence follows from the fact that \(S\left( M'\right)\) is closed and convex and the strong separating hyperplane theorem,Footnote 36 and the last equivalence follows from (A.7). \(\square\)

Recall that \(\Delta ^*_{\text{ sym }}\left( U\right)\) is the set of all symmetric probability measures in \(\Delta ^*\left( U\right)\). Proposition 2 implies that to show that that \(\preccurlyeq ^*\) coincides with consensus of neutral judges, it is sufficient to show that:

$$\begin{aligned}&M \preccurlyeq ^* M' \Leftrightarrow \left[ \int \max _{\ell \in M} \left( u \cdot \ell \right) p \left( du\right) \le \int \max _{\ell \in M'} \left( u \cdot \ell \right) p \left( du\right) , \forall p \in \Delta ^*_{\text{ sym }}\left( U\right) \right] , \;\;\;\\&\quad \forall M, M' \in {\mathscr {M}}. \end{aligned}$$

Lemma A.2 now implies that to complete the proof, it is sufficient to show that (A.6) is equivalent to

$$\begin{aligned} \int \max _{\ell \in M} \left( u \cdot \ell \right) p (du) \le \int \max _{\ell \in M'} \left( u \cdot \ell \right) p \left( du\right) , \;\;\;\forall p \in \Delta ^*_{\text{ sym }}\left( U\right) . \end{aligned}$$

For any \(p \in \Delta ^*\left( U\right)\) and \(\pi \in \Pi\), define \(p^\pi \in \Delta ^*\left( U\right)\) by \(p^\pi \left( E\right) := p\left( E^\pi \right)\) for all measurable \(E \subseteq U\).Footnote 37 Let \(p\in \Delta ^*_{\text{ sym }}\left( U\right)\). Then for all measurable \(E \subseteq U\), \(p\left( E\right) = p\left( E^\pi \right) = p^\pi \left( E\right)\) for all \(\pi \in \Pi\). So \(p = p^\pi\) for all \(\pi \in \Pi\). So:

$$\begin{aligned}&\forall p \in \Delta ^*_{\text{ sym }}\left( U\right) , \int \max _{\ell \in M} \left( u \cdot \ell \right) p\left( du\right) \\&\quad = \frac{1}{n!} \times n! \int \max _{\ell \in M} \left( u \cdot \ell \right) p\left( du\right) =\frac{1}{n!} \sum _{\pi \in \Pi } \int \max _{\ell \in M} \left( u \cdot \ell \right) p^{\pi ^{-1}} \left( du\right) \\&\quad = \frac{1}{n!} \sum _{\pi \in \Pi } \int \max _{\ell \in M} \left( u^\pi \cdot \ell \right) p\left( du\right) = \int \frac{1}{n!} \sum _{\pi \in \Pi } \max _{\ell \in M} \left( u^\pi \cdot \ell \right) p\left( du\right) . \end{aligned}$$

It is now easy to see that the desired equivalence holds. \(\square\)

1.3 Proof of Proposition 3

Kochov (2007) and Galaabaatar (2010) establish the following proposition.

Proposition A.1

Let \(\preccurlyeq\) be a relation on \({\mathscr {M}}\). \(\preccurlyeq\) is a preorder satisfying continuity, monotonicity, and independence if and only if there exists \(P \subseteq \Delta ^*\left( U\right)\) such that for all \(M, N \in {\mathscr {M}},\)

$$\begin{aligned} M \preccurlyeq N \Leftrightarrow \left[ \int _U \max _{\ell \in M} (u \cdot \ell ) p (du)\le \int _U \max _{\ell \in N} (u \cdot \ell ) p (du), \;\;\forall p \in P \right] . \end{aligned}$$
(A.8)

Theorem 1, Proposition 2 and Proposition A.1 imply that the symmetry order is a preorder that satisfies continuity, independence, monotonicity, and neutrality. It is also straightforward to establish that the symmetry order satisfies these axioms via a direct proof. It is easy to see that the symmetry order is not complete.

Next consider any preorder satisfying continuity, independence, monotonicity and neutrality. Proposition A.1 implies that there exists \(P \subseteq \Delta ^*\left( U\right)\) such that \(\preccurlyeq\) satisfies (A.9). The neutrality axiom then implies that

$$\begin{aligned} \int _U \max _{\ell \in M} (u \cdot \ell ) p (du)= \int _U \max _{\ell \in M^\pi } (u \cdot \ell ) p (du),\;\;\; \forall p \in P, \; \forall M \in {\mathscr {M}}, \forall \pi \in \Pi . \end{aligned}$$

Recall that \(\Delta ^*_{\text{ sym }}\left( U\right)\) is the set of all symmetric probability measures in \(\Delta \left( U\right)\). An argument similar to the proof of Lemma A.1 now implies that for all \(p \in P\), there exists \(p' \in \Delta _{\text{ sym }}\left( U\right)\) such that

$$\begin{aligned} \int _U \max _{\ell \in M} (u \cdot \ell ) p (du)= \int _U \max _{\ell \in M} (u \cdot \ell ) p' (du),\quad \forall M \in {\mathscr {M}}. \end{aligned}$$

It follows that there exists \(P' \subseteq \Delta _{\text{ sym }}\left( U\right)\) such that for all \(M, N \in {\mathscr {M}}\),

$$\begin{aligned} M \preccurlyeq N \Leftrightarrow \left[ \int _U \max _{\ell \in M} (u \cdot \ell ) p (du)\le \int _U \max _{\ell \in N} (u \cdot \ell ) p (du), \forall p \in P' \right] . \end{aligned}$$
(A.9)

That the symmetry order is the coarsest preorder satisfying continuity, monotonicity, independence, and neutrality now follows from Theorem 1. \(\square\)

1.4 Proof of Proposition 4

For every lottery \(\ell\), \(S\left( \left\{ \ell \right\} \right) =\left\{ \left( \frac{1}{n},\frac{1}{n},\ldots ,\frac{1}{n}\right) \right\}\). On the other hand, for all M, \(\left( \frac{1}{n},\frac{1}{n},\ldots ,\frac{1}{n}\right) \in S\left( M\right)\) and if M contains more than one lottery, then \(S\left( M\right)\) contains more than one lottery. So \(S\left( \left\{ \ell \right\} \right) \subseteq S\left( M\right)\) with a strict inclusion if M contains more than one lottery. The result now follows from (8), the definition of the symmetry order. \(\square\)

1.5 Interpretation of (9)

Here I explain why (9) does indeed give the probability that voter i is pivotal. In a stochastic voting mechanism \(\alpha\), the outcome of the election is determined by the profile of votes and a random element. To more explicitly formalize the random element, define an extended voting mechanism to be a function \(\alpha ': \{0,1\}^k \times [0,1] \rightarrow \{0,1\}\). Compared to a stochastic voting mechanism \(\alpha\), an extended voting mechanism \(\alpha '\) has one more argument, which is a real number \(r \in [0,1]\). Interpret r as a random draw chosen with uniform probability independent of voter preferences. The output of extended voting mechanism \(\alpha '\) is an integer, meaning that as a function of the inputs, one candidate definitely wins, so that the stochastic element is completely captured by the realization of r. For any stochastic voting mechanism \(\alpha\), define the corresponding extended voting mechanism \(\alpha '\) by: \(\alpha '(z,r)= 1\) if \(r \le \alpha (z)\), and \(\alpha '(z,r)= 0\) otherwise. Then, in \(\alpha '\), the probability that candidate 1 wins conditional on vote profile z is \(\alpha (z)\). Also since \(\alpha\) is monotone in the vote profile, so is \(\alpha '\): \(\forall , z, z' \in \{0,1\}^k, \forall r \in [0,1], z \le z' \Rightarrow \alpha '(z,r) \le \alpha '(z',r)\). As \(\alpha\) and \(\alpha '\) are essentially identical, and differ only in that the random element of \(\alpha\) has been imported as an argument of \(\alpha '\), to understand what it means to be pivotal in \(\alpha\), one can look to what it means to be pivotal in \(\alpha '\). In particular, i is pivotal in \(\alpha '\) whenever \((z_{-i},r)\) is such that \(\alpha '((0,z_{-i}),r) =0\) and \(\alpha '((1,z_{-i}),r)=1\). (Since \(\alpha '\) is monotone, it is not possible that when a voter changes her vote from 0 to 1, the outcome will change from 1 to 0.) In other words, i is pivotal whenever whichever candidate that i votes for wins. Define random variable \(v_i\) on \(\{0,1\}^{k-1} \times [0,1]\) by \(v_i(z_{-i},r) = \alpha '((1,z_{-i}),r)-\alpha '((0,z_{-i}),r)\). \(v_i=1\) if and only if i is pivotal, and \(v_i = 0\) otherwise. So the expected value of \(v_i\) is the probability that i is pivotal. The expected value of \(v_i\) is \(\sum _{z_{-i} \in \{0,1\}^{k-1} }\left( \int _0^1 \left[ \alpha '((1,z_{-i}),r)-\alpha '((0,z_{-i}),r)\right] dr\right) \mu (z_{-i}) = \sum _{z_{-i} \in \{0,1\}^{k-1}} \left( \int _0^1 \alpha '((1,z_{-i}),r)dr-\int _0^1 \alpha '((0,z_{-i}),r)dr\right) \mu (z_{-i})\), which is equal to the right-hand side of (9).

1.6 Proof or Proposition 5

Fix a voter i. For \(j,k \in \{0,1\}\), let \(\ell ^k_j\) and \(\ell '^k_j\) be, respectively, the probabilities that lotteries \(\ell ^k_i(\alpha ,\mu )\) and \(\ell ^k_i(\alpha ',\mu ')\) assign to candidate j. Let \(\delta _j\) be the lottery that assigns probability 1 on candidate j.

We have:

$$\begin{aligned} \begin{aligned} M_i(\alpha ,\mu )&= \{ \ell ^0_0 \delta _0 + \ell ^0_1 \delta _1, \ell ^1_0 \delta _0 + \ell ^1_1 \delta _1\} \\&= \ell ^1_0 \{\delta _0\}+\ell ^0_1 \{ \delta _1 \} + ( \ell ^1_1-\ell ^0_1 ) \{ \delta _0,\delta _1 \} \\&\sim ^* (\ell ^1_0 + \ell ^0_1)\{\delta _0\} + ( \ell ^1_1-\ell ^0_1 ) \{ \delta _0,\delta _1 \}. \end{aligned} \end{aligned}$$
(A.10)

For the second equality, note that monotonicity of \(\alpha\) implies that \(\ell ^1_1 -\ell ^0_1 \ge 0\). The indifference follows from the fact that all singleton menus are indifferent according to the symmetry order (Proposition 4) and the independence axiom. Similarly,

$$\begin{aligned} M_i(\alpha ',\mu ') \sim ^* (\ell '^1_0 + \ell '^0_1) \{\delta _0\} + ( \ell '^1_1-\ell '^0_1 ) \{ \delta _0,\delta _1 \}. \end{aligned}$$
(A.11)

Definitions imply that \(B_i(\alpha ,\mu ) = \ell ^1_1-\ell ^0_1\) and \(B_i(\alpha ',\mu ')= \ell '^1_1-\ell '^0_1\). So

$$\begin{aligned} B_i(\alpha ,\mu ) \le B_i(\alpha ',\mu ') \Leftrightarrow \;&\ell ^1_1-\ell ^0_1 \le \ell '^1_1-\ell '^0_1\\ \Leftrightarrow \;&(\ell ^1_0 + \ell ^0_1)\{ \delta _0\} + ( \ell ^1_1-\ell ^0_1 ) \{ \delta _0,\delta _1 \} \\&\preccurlyeq ^* (\ell '^1_0 + \ell '^0_1) \{\delta _0\} + ( \ell '^1_1-\ell '^0_1 ) \{ \delta _0,\delta _1 \}.\\ \Leftrightarrow \;&M_i(\alpha ,\mu ) \preccurlyeq ^* M_i(\alpha ',\mu '), \end{aligned}$$

where the second equivalence follows from the independence axiom and the fact that singleton menus are strictly dispreferred to all menus M such that M is not a singleton (Proposition 4), and the last equivalence follows from (A.10A.11). \(\square\)

1.7 Proof of Proposition 7

Suppose that matrix \(P=(p_{st}: s \in S, t \in T)\) is more informative than \(Q =(q_{st}: s \in S, t \in T)\). Let \(R=(r_{vt}: v \in T, t \in T)\) be the stochastic matrix such that \(Q=PR\). Choose \(\gamma ^*=\gamma (Q,\eta ,\sigma ^*) \in M(Q,\eta )\), where \(\sigma ^*\) is an arbitrary strategy in \(\Sigma\). For each \(\sigma \in \Sigma\), define \(\gamma ^\sigma = \gamma (P,\eta ,\sigma )\). For each \((s,d) \in S \times D\), \(\gamma ^*(s,d)\) (resp., \(\gamma ^\sigma (s,d)\)) is the probability that \(\gamma ^*\) (resp., \(\gamma ^\sigma\)) puts on (sd). It is sufficient to write \(\gamma ^*\) as a convex combination of lotteries in \(M(P,\eta ) =\{\gamma ^\sigma : \sigma \in \Sigma \}\). This is sufficient because it establishes that \(M(Q,\eta ) \subseteq \text{ co }\left( M(P,\eta )\right)\), which implies that every agent with preference for flexibility prefers \(M(P,\eta )\) to \(M(Q,\eta )\), which, in turn, implies that \(M(Q,\eta ) \preccurlyeq ^* M(P,\eta )\).

For \(d,d' \in D\), define \(\chi (d,d'):=1\) if \(d =d'\) and \(\chi (d,d'):=0\) otherwise. Then for all \((s,d) \in S \times D\)

$$\begin{aligned} \gamma ^*(s,d) = \eta _s \sum _{t \in T} q_{st}\chi (\sigma ^*(t),d)&= \eta _s \sum _{t \in T} \sum _{v \in T} p_{sv} r_{vt}\chi (\sigma ^*(t),d). \end{aligned}$$
(A.12)

Similarly,

$$\begin{aligned} \gamma ^\sigma (s,d) = \eta _s \sum _{v \in T} p_{sv} \chi (\sigma (v),d). \end{aligned}$$
(A.13)

For any \(v \in T\) and \(d \in D\), define:

$$\begin{aligned} \tau (v,d) = \sum _{t \in T} r_{vt} \chi (\sigma ^*(t),d). \end{aligned}$$
(A.14)

It is easy to see that \(\tau (v,d) \ge 0\) for all \(v \in T\) and \(d \in D\), and the for for all \(v \in T\), \(\sum _{d \in D} \tau (v,d) =1.\) For any \(\sigma \in \Sigma\), define: \(\lambda _{\sigma } = \prod _{t \in T} \tau (t,\sigma (t))\). It follows that

$$\begin{aligned} 1= \prod _{t \in T} \sum _{d \in D} \tau (t,d) = \sum _{\sigma \in \Sigma } \prod _{t \in T} \tau (t,\sigma (t)) =\sum _{\sigma \in \Sigma } \lambda _\sigma . \end{aligned}$$

Similarly:

$$\begin{aligned} \begin{aligned} \tau (v,d)&= \tau (v,d) \prod _{t \in T {\setminus } v} \sum _{d' \in D} \tau (t,d') = \sum _{\{\sigma \in \Sigma : \sigma (v) =d\}} \prod _{t \in T} \tau (t,\sigma (t)) \\&= \sum _{\{\sigma \in \Sigma : \sigma (v)=d \}} \lambda _\sigma = \sum _{\sigma \in \Sigma } \lambda _\sigma \chi (\sigma (v),d). \end{aligned} \end{aligned}$$
(A.15)

Putting it all together, we have:

$$\begin{aligned} \gamma ^*(s,d)&= \eta _s \sum _{t \in T} \sum _{v \in T} p_{sv} r_{vt}\chi (\sigma ^*(t),d) = \eta _s \sum _{v \in T} p_{sv}\sum _{t \in T} r_{vt}\chi (\sigma ^*(t),d)\\&= \eta _s \sum _{v \in T} p_{sv} \tau (v,d) = \eta _s \sum _{v \in T} p_{sv} \left[ \sum _{\sigma \in \Sigma } \lambda _\sigma \chi (\sigma (v),d) \right]\\& = \sum _{\sigma \in \Sigma } \lambda _\sigma \left[ \eta _s \sum _{v \in T} p_{sv}\chi (\sigma (v),d) \right] = \sum _{\sigma \in \Sigma } \lambda _\sigma \gamma ^\sigma (s,d), \end{aligned}$$

where the first equality follows from (A.12), the third equality follows from (A.14), the fourth equality follows from (A.15), and the last equality follows from (A.13). This shows that \(\gamma ^*\) can be written as a convex combination of \(\{\gamma ^\sigma : \sigma \in \Sigma \}\), as we wanted to show.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Sher, I. Neutral freedom and freedom as control. Soc Choice Welf 56, 21–56 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-020-01267-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-020-01267-x

Navigation