Social Choice and Welfare

, Volume 48, Issue 2, pp 269–294 | Cite as

Conundrums for nonconsequentialists

Original Paper

Abstract

There are a number of single-profile impossibility theorems in social choice theory and welfare economics that demonstrate the incompatibility of unanimity/dominance criteria with various nonconsequentialist principles given some rationality restrictions on the rankings being considered. This article is concerned with examining what they have in common and how they differ. Groups of results are identified that have similar formal structures and are established using similar proof strategies.

References

  1. Blackorby C, Donaldson D, Weymark JA (1990) A welfarist proof of Arrow’s theorem. Recherches Economiques de Louvain 56:259–286Google Scholar
  2. Blackorby C, Bossert W, Donaldson D (2005) Multi-profile welfarism: a generalization. Soc Choice Welf 24:253–267CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Bossert W, Weymark JA (2004) Utility in social choice. In: Barberà S, Hammond PJ, Seidl C (eds) Handbook of utility theory. Volume 2: extensions. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Boston, pp 1099–1177Google Scholar
  4. Broome J (1991) Weighing goods: equality, uncertainty and time. Basil Blackwell, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  5. Brown C (2011) Consequentialize this. Ethics 121:749–771CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Brun BC, Tungodden B (2004) Non-welfaristic theories of justice: is “the intersection approach” a solution to the indexing problem. Soc Choice Welf 22:49–60CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Campbell DE, Kelly JS (2002) Impossibility theorems in the Arrovian framework. In: Arrow KJ, Sen AK, Suzumura K (eds) Handbook of social choice and welfare, vol 1. North-Holland, Amsterdam, pp 35–94CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Chang HF (2000) A liberal theory of social welfare: fairness, utility, and the Pareto principle. Yale Law J 110:173–235CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Decancq K, Fleurbaey M, Schokkaert E (2015) Happiness, equivalent incomes and respect for individual preferences. Economica 82:1082–1156CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Donaldson D, Weymark JA (1998) A quasiordering is the intersection of orderings. J Econ Theory 78:382–387CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Fleurbaey M (2006) Social welfare, priority to the worst-off and the dimensions of individual well-being. In: Farina F, Savaglio E (eds) Inequality and economic integration. Routledge, London, pp 225–268Google Scholar
  12. Fleurbaey M (2007) Social choice and the indexing dilemma. Soc Choice Welf 29:633–648CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Fleurbaey M (2011) Willingness-to-pay and the equivalence approach. Revue d’Économie Politique 121:35–58CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Fleurbaey M, Maniquet F (2011) A theory of fairness and social welfare. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Fleurbaey M, Schokkaert E (2013) Behavioral welfare economics and redistribution. Am Econ J Microecon 5:180–205CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Fleurbaey M, Trannoy A (2003) The impossibility of a Paretian egalitarian. Soc Choice Welf 21:243–263CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Fleurbaey M, Tungodden B, Chang HF (2003) Any non-welfarist method of policy assessment violates the Pareto principle: a comment. J Polit Econ 111:1382–1385CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Gibbard A (1979) Disparate goods and Rawls’ difference principle: a social choice theoretic treatment. Theory Decis 11:267–288CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Hare C (2007) Rationality and the distant needy. Philos Public Aff 35:161–178CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Harsanyi JC (1977) Rational behavior and bargaining equilibrium in games and social situations. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Kaplow L, Shavell S (2001) Any non-welfarist method of policy assessment violates the Pareto principle. J Polit Econ 109:281–286CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Kaplow L, Shavell S (2002) Fairness versus welfare. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MAGoogle Scholar
  23. Pattanaik PK, Xu Y (2007) Minimal relativism, dominance, and standard of living comparisons based on functionings. Oxford Econ Papers 59:354–374CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Pattanaik PK, Xu Y (2012) On dominance and context-dependence in decisions involving multiple attributes. Econ Philos 28:117–132CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Rawls J (1971) A theory of justice. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MAGoogle Scholar
  26. Scheffler S (2001) Boundaries and allegiances. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  27. Sen AK (1970a) Collective choice and social welfare. Holden-Day, San FranciscoGoogle Scholar
  28. Sen AK (1970b) The impossibility of a Paretian liberal. J Polit Econ 78:152–157CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Sen AK (1977) On weights and measures: informational constraints in social welfare analysis. Econometrica 45:1539–1572CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Sen AK (1979) Personal utilities and public judgements: or what’s wrong with welfare economics? Econ J 89:537–558CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Sen AK (1985) Commodities and capabilities. North-Holland, AmsterdamGoogle Scholar
  32. Sen AK (1990) Welfare, freedom and social choice: a reply. Recherches Economiques de Louvain 56:451–485Google Scholar
  33. Sen AK (1992) Inequality reexamined. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MAGoogle Scholar
  34. Suppes P (1966) Some formal models of grading principles. Synthese 6:284–306CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Suzumura K (2001) Pareto principles from inch to ell. Econ Lett 70:95–98CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Suzumura K (2011) Welfarism, individual rights, and procedural fairness. In: Arrow KJ, Sen AK, Suzumura K (eds) Handbook of social choice and welfare, vol 2. North-Holland, Amsterdam, pp 605–685CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Weymark JA (2014) Must one be an ogre to rationally prefer aiding the nearby to the distant needy? Philos Public Aff 42:230–252CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2017

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Departments of Economics and PhilosophyVanderbilt UniversityNashvilleUSA

Personalised recommendations