Advertisement

Social Choice and Welfare

, Volume 43, Issue 3, pp 731–746 | Cite as

Paternalism with hindsight: do protégés react consequentialistically to paternalism?

  • Mitesh Kataria
  • M. Vittoria LevatiEmail author
  • Matthias Uhl
Article

Abstract

We investigate experimentally whether the protégés’ reaction to paternalism depends on the consequences of the paternalistic action to their well-being. Thus, our research is concerned with the perception of paternalism by those who are directly affected by it, rather than with the justifiability of paternalism from an ethical perspective. We find that the protégés punish a paternalist restricting their freedom of choice. Yet, this negative reaction is not based on principled grounds because, with the wisdom of hindsight, the protégés punish the paternalist only if the restriction makes them worse off. Conversely, if the restriction makes them better off, the protégés on average do not punish and, sometimes, they even reward the paternalist. This suggests that the protégés take predominantly a consequentialist stand on paternalism. In addition, a regression analysis reveals that our main finding is not altered when we control for the intentions (malevolent vs. benevolent) that the protégés attribute to the paternalist.

Keywords

Inequality Aversion Strategy Method Paternalistic Intervention Experimental Currency Unit Poker Machine 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Notes

Acknowledgments

We thank the managing editor Marc Fleurbaey, the editor in charge, and two anonymous referees for their constructive comments. We also thank Dominique Cappelletti, Alon Harel, Elina Lampi, Matteo Ploner, and Birendra Rai for helpful suggestions. The authors bear the responsibility for any errors and omissions.

Supplementary material

355_2014_800_MOESM1_ESM.tex (7 kb)
Supplementary material 1 (tex 6 KB)

References

  1. Ahlert M, Crüger A (2004) Freedom to veto. Soc Choice Welf 22(1):7–16CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Amiel Y, Cowell FA, Polovin A (2001) Risk perceptions, income transformations and inequality. Eur Econ Rev 45(4):964–976CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Bolton GE, Ockenfels A (2000) ERC: a theory of equity, reciprocity, and competition. Am Econ Rev 90(1):166–193CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Bolton GE, Ockenfels A (2010) Betrayal aversion: evidence from Brazil, China, Oman, Switzerland, Turkey, and the United States: comment. Am Econ Rev 100(1):628–633CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Brandts J, Charness G (2011) The strategy versus the direct-response method: a first survey of experimental comparisons. Exp Econ 14:375–398CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Camerer C, Issacharoff S, Loewenstein G, O’Donoghue T, Rabin M (2003) Regulation for conservatives: behavioral economics and the case for “asymmetric paternalism”. Univ PA Law Rev 151(3):1211–1254CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Carlsson F, Daruvala D, Johansson-Stenman O (2005) Are people inequality-averse, or just risk-averse? Economica 72(287):375–396CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Dohmen T, Falk A, Huffman D, Sunde U, Schupp J, Wagner GG (2011) Individual risk attitudes: measurement, determinants, and behavioral consequences. J Eur Econ Assoc 9(3):522–550CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Dworkin G (2010) Paternalism. In: Zalta E N (ed) The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Available at http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2010/entries/paternalism/. Accessed 12 Jan 2014
  10. Fehr E, Schmidt KM (1999) A theory of fairness, competition and cooperation. Q J Econ 114:817–868CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Fischbacher U (2007) Zurich toolbox for readymade economic experiments. Exp Econ 10(2):171–178CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Gneezy U, Potters J (1997) An experiment on risk taking and evaluation periods. Q J Econ 112(2):631–645CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Greiner B (2004) An online recruitment system for economic experiments. In: Kremer K, Macho V (eds) Forschung und wissenschaftliches Rechnen 2003. Ges. für Wiss. Datenverarbeitung, Göttingen, pp 79–93Google Scholar
  14. Honderich T (1995) The oxford companion to philosophy. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  15. Johansson-Stenman O (2012) Are most people consequentialists? Econ Lett 115(2):225–228CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Kroll Y, Davidovitz L (2003) Inequality aversion versus risk aversion. Economica 70(277):19–29CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Schelling TC (1984) Self-command in practice, in policy, and in a theory of rational choice. Am Econ Rev Pap Proc 74(2):1–11Google Scholar
  18. Sen A (1987) On ethics and economics. Basil Blackwell, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  19. Sen A (1988) Freedom of choice: concept and content. Eur Econ Rev 32:269–294CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Sen A (1991) Welfare, preference and freedom. J Econom 50(2):15–29CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Thaler RH, Sunstein CR (2003) Behavioral economics, public policy, and paternalism: libertarian paternalism. Am Econ Rev 93(2):175–179CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Thaler RH, Sunstein CR (2008) Nudge: improving decisions about health, wealth, and happiness. Yale University Press, New HavenGoogle Scholar
  23. Thomas M, Buckmaster L (2010) Paternalism in social policy — when is it justifiable?. Parliament of Australia, Department of Parliamentary Services, Research Paper No 8Google Scholar
  24. Verme P (2009) Happiness, freedom and control. J Econ Behav Organ 71(2):146–161CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Zizzo DJ (2010) Experimenter demand effects in economic experiments. Exp Econ 13(1):75–98CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2014

Authors and Affiliations

  • Mitesh Kataria
    • 1
  • M. Vittoria Levati
    • 1
    • 2
    Email author
  • Matthias Uhl
    • 3
  1. 1.Max Planck Institute of EconomicsJenaGermany
  2. 2.Department of EconomicsUniversity of VeronaVeronaItaly
  3. 3.Technical University of MunichMunichGermany

Personalised recommendations