Skip to main content
Log in

General Luce model

  • Research Article
  • Published:
Economic Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We extend the Luce model of discrete choice theory to satisfactorily handle zero-probability choices. The Luce mode struggles to explain choices that are not made. The model requires that if an alternative y is never chosen when x is available, then there is no set of alternatives from which y is chosen with positive probability. In our model, if an alternative y is never chosen when x is available, then we infer that y is dominated by x. While dominated by x, y may still be chosen with positive probability, when grouped with a comparable set of alternatives.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. A recent growing literature extends the Luce model to capture various behavioral phenomena, but typically requires strictly positive choice probabilities.

  2. A common example in the literature on semiorders is the comparison of coffee with different amounts of sugar. One additional grain of sugar produces an indifferent cup of coffee. But after adding enough grains, one obtains a noticeably sweeter cup.

  3. The paper by Fudenberg et al. (2015) allows for deterministic choices, but does not focus on Luce.

  4. A first draft of our paper focused on the threshold Luce mode, which we define below. We thank an anonymous referee and David Ahn for suggesting that we extend the discussion to cover the general Luce model and the two-stage general Luce model. After we wrote the first version of our paper, which did not include our most general model, Ahumada and Ulku (2017) independently developed the present generalization.

  5. Transitivity and irreflexivity imply asymmetry.

  6. The function c also satisfies the following property. If \(B \subset A\) and \(c(A) \subset B\), then \(c(B)=c(A)\). This property appears in several studies, such as Aizerman and Malishevski (1981).

  7. \(n=2\) is allowed.

  8. Luce IIA implies that for any i, \(p(x_i,A_i)/p(x_{i+1},A_i)= p(x_i, \cup _{j=1}^{n-1}A_j)/p(x_{i+1},\cup _{j=1}^{n-1}A_j)\). So the right hand side becomes \(p(x_1,\cup _{j=1}^{n-1}A_j)/p(x_{n},\cup _{j=1}^{n-1}A_j)\), which is \(p(x_1,A_n)/p(x_n,A_n)\) by Luce IIA again.

  9. To see this consider \(x, y, z \in X\) such that \(x \simeq y\), \(x \simeq z\), and \(z\gg y\) but \(u(z)< u(y)\). Then \(p(x,\{x, y\})= u(x)/(u(x)+u(y))< u(x)/(u(x)+u(z))=p(x,\{x,y,z\})\).

  10. Suppose that \(z_{i} \gg z_{i+1}\) for some i. Then \(d((z_i)_{i=1}^s)\) becomes \(+\infty \), even though \(z_{j+1} \ge z_j\) for some \(j\ne i\). This is not useful to compare the values of intensity. So, by (iii), we restrict when \(z_{i} \gg z_{i+1}\) is allowed: it is allowed only when \(z_{i} \ge z_{i+1}\) for all i.

  11. We appreciate a referee who pointed out the relationship.

  12. See Definition 12 of Sen (1971) to see the relationship between the normality of a choice function and a threshold Luce function.

  13. Otherwise, we have \(x_j\equiv z \gg y \equiv x_{j+1}\), which shows \(u(z)/u(y) \equiv u(x_j)/u(x_{j+1})>1+\alpha \), which is a contradiction.

References

  • Ahumada, A., Ulku, L.: Luce rule with limited consideration. Math. Soc. Sci. 93, 52–56 (2017)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aizerman, M., Malishevski, A.: General theory of best variants choice: some aspects. IEEE Trans. Autom. Control 26, 1030–1040 (1981)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, H., Marschak, J.: Random orderings and stochastic theories of responses. In: Olkin, I., Ghurye, S.G., Hoeffding, W., Hotelling, H., Madow, W.G. (eds.) Contributions to Probability and Statistics, vol. 2, pp. 97–132. Stanford University Press, Palo Alto (1960)

  • Brady, R.L., Rehbeck, J.: Menu-dependent stochastic feasibility. Econometrica 84, 1203–1223 (2016)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cerreia-Vioglio, S., Maccheroni, F., Marinacci, M., Rustichini: Law of Demand and Forced Choice. Tech. rep (2016)

  • Cerreia-Vioglio, S., Maccheroni, F., Marinacci, M., Rustichini, A.: Multinomial Logit Processes and Preference Discovery: Inside and Outside the Black Box. Mimeo, U. Bocconi, New York (2017)

    Google Scholar 

  • Echenique, F., Saito, K., Tserenjigmid, G.: The perception-adjusted Luce model. Math. Soc. Sci. 93, 67–76 (2018)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn, P.C.: Binary choice probabilities: on the varieties of stochastic transitivity. J. Math. Psychol. 10, 327–352 (1973)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Flores, A., Berbeglia, G., Van Hentenryck, P.: Assortment Optimization Under the General Luce Model. Tech. rep (2017)

  • Fudenberg, D., Strzalecki, T.: Dynamic logit with choice aversion. Econometrica 83, 651–691 (2015)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fudenberg, D., Iijima, R., Strzalecki, T.: Stochastic choice and revealed perturbed utility. Econometrica 83, 2371–2409 (2015)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gul, F., Natenzon, P., Pesendorfer, W.: Random choice as behavioral optimization. Econometrica 82, 1873–1912 (2014)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horan, S.: Random Consideration and Choice. Tech. rep., mimeo, Université du Québeca Montréal (2014)

  • Jamison, D.T., Lawrence, L.J.: Semiorders and the theory of choice. Econometrica 41, 901–912 (1973)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luce, R.D.: Semiorders and a theory of utility discrimination. Econometrica 24, 178–191 (1956)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luce, R .D.: Individual Choice Behavior a Theoretical Analysis. Wiley, New York (1959)

    Google Scholar 

  • Manzini, P., Mariotti, M.: Stochastic choice and consideration sets. Econometrica 82, 1153–1176 (2014)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Masatlioglu, Y., Nakajima, D., Ozbay, E.Y.: Revealed attention. Am. Econ. Rev. 102, 2183–2205 (2012)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A.K.: Choice functions and revealed preference. Rev. Econ. Stud. 38, 307–317 (1971)

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kota Saito.

Additional information

Echenique thanks the National Science Foundation for its support through the Grants SES 1558757 and CNS-1518941. Saito thanks the National Science Foundation for its support through the Grant SES 1558757.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Echenique, F., Saito, K. General Luce model. Econ Theory 68, 811–826 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-018-1145-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-018-1145-5

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation