Skip to main content
Log in

Sequential innovation, naked exclusion, and upfront lump-sum payments

  • Research Article
  • Published:
Economic Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We present a potentially benign naked exclusion mechanism that can be applied to sequential innovation; a non-patentable original innovation by the incumbent supplier fosters derivative innovation by rivals. In the absence of an appropriate legal framework, the original innovator’s equilibrium exclusivity contracts block subsequent efficient entry even if there is (leader–follower) competition in the contracting phase. However, the legal framework may maximize social welfare by imposing a ban on upfront lump-sum payments in exclusivity contracts (by all suppliers) combined with an outright ban on exclusivity contracts by the derivative innovator. The former ban precludes the exclusion of socially beneficial derivative innovation by causing the incumbent supplier to resort to accommodation, rather than to pure exclusion, strategies. The latter ban complements the former by preventing inefficient or excessive derivative innovation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In a different vein, Innes and Sexton (1994) point out that naked exclusion may prevent inefficient entry. Fumagalli and Motta (2006) note that downstream competition may discourage naked exclusion, while in Simpson and Wickelgren (2007) downstream competition facilitates exclusion. Spector (2011) notes that exclusion is more likely if contracts can only take simple forms. Armstrong and Wright (2007) focus on the role of exclusivity contracts in preventing multihoming in two-sided markets. Stefanadis (2016) examines the impact of the potential entrant’s volatility of innovation on the exclusion strategy of a non-innovating incumbent.

  2. As Bessen and Maskin (2009) note, some of the most innovative industries in the last 40 years, such as semiconductors, computers and software, have historically had weak patent protection. In recent years, however, software patents have grown rapidly (Bessen and Hunt 2007).

  3. The trade-off between non-patentable original and derivative innovation is central in several exclusive dealing antitrust cases. For example, in the well-known Standard Fashion v. Magrane-Houston antitrust case (258 U.S. 346 (1922)), United Fashion, a clothes designer, elicited exclusivity contracts that required department stores to sell only United Fashion’s patterns. After such contracts were in place, United Fashion invested in the development and introduction of new products. United Fashion thus claimed that the purpose of its contracts was the efficient protection of original innovation, while Magrane-Houston disputed this claim (Marvel 1982). Our analysis may enhance our understanding of such cases.

  4. In Bernheim and Whinston (1998) if suppliers compete in contracts, the incumbent may still deter efficient entry, but only when there are effects on non-coincident markets (other than the ones in which exclusivity contracts are employed). Furthermore, competition in contracts may not prevent inefficient exclusion if there is lack of coordination among customers (Fumagalli and Motta 2008), or if contracts can only take very simple forms, e.g., if they cannot incorporate termination penalties and they also automatically deprive a supplier of the opportunity to later leave the market (Spector 2011). We show that (leader–follower) competition in contracts may lead to anticompetitive outcomes even if there are no non-coincident markets, if buyers can coordinate, and if contracts are not too simple.

  5. Furthermore, the effects of upfront lump-sum payments have been discussed by U.S. Senate (1999) and Federal Trade Commission (2003).

  6. In a different vein, De Meza and Selvaggi (2007) discuss relationship-specific investment that does not directly affect parties other than the contract participants.

  7. There is also a large literature that examines the optimal strength of patent laws (e.g., Grossman and Lai 2004; Iwaisako and Futagami 2013; Moser 2013). Our analysis explores a different issue than this line of research since it focuses on non-patentable innovations.

  8. Our results would be identical if derivative innovation took the form of higher quality (i.e., of a product with a reservation value \(r+c-\underline{c}\)), rather than of a lower variable cost \(\underline{c}<c\).

  9. As, for example, Anand and Khanna (2000) empirically show, many licensing contracts are signed prior to the development of the technology to which the contract applies. Such timing, which entails pre-investment contracts, is also in the spirit of Innes and Sexton (1994), Segal and Whinston (2000b) and Fumagalli et al. (2012), among others.

  10. As, for example, Segal and Whinston (2000b) explain, contracts are often incomplete in that future trade is difficult to specify in advance, impeding any contractual precommitment to future prices. Then, “the only possible term in the initial contact, aside from the lump-sum payment, is the exclusivity provision” (Segal and Whinston 2000b, pp. 604–605). In our model contract incompleteness is reinforced by the feature that the contracting stage occurs before the innovation, or the investment, stage, i.e., before the product to which the contract applies is introduced into the market. Given that the quality of such a future product is largely non-contractible, even if precommitment to future prices was possible, precommitment to the product’s “real price,” or to the product’s price relative to its quality, would be largely unfeasible.

  11. It is thus implicitly assumed that a pure exclusivity contract entails an infinite termination penalty.

  12. As Aghion and Bolton (1987) and Segal and Whinston (2000a) explain, partial exclusivity contracts aim to extract value from a rival’s superior technology through termination penalties. Since in our model E has a more efficient technology than I, such a use of partial exclusivity contracts by E would be meaningless.

  13. As Mansfield (1985) points out, detailed information on a new product, or a new process, leaks out within approximately 1 year on average. However, it often leaks out in less than 6 months, although it may sometimes leak out after 18 months or even longer.

  14. For example, the well-known Standard Fashion v. Magrane-Houston antitrust case entails clothes design (see note 3). If we consider clothes design a rather simple form of innovation, original and derivative innovation may often occur almost simultaneously. Contemplating such timing, derivative (and original) innovators may be able to offer contracts to customers before the development of original innovation.

  15. Coalition-proofness formalizes the ability of customers to coordinate when they decide whether to accept the proposed contracts. Customer coordination (albeit not necessarily in the exact form of coalition-proofness) is a rather frequent assumption in the exclusive dealing literature (e.g., Hart and Tirole 1990; Innes and Sexton 1994; Segal and Whinston 2000a; Spector 2011).

  16. The contract finalization stage corresponds to a supplier’s ability to assess customer responses before it commits to sunk lump-sum payments to customers. Such an assessment of customer responses is important in our model because contracts are signed before the fixed cost of entry is incurred. In the standard naked exclusion literature (Rasmusen et al. 1991; Segal and Whinston 2000a), on the other hand, a supplier is already in the market when it offers contracts.

  17. For example, such a tie-breaking convention is reasonable if supplier I can obtain even a minimum of benefits (e.g., in terms of reputation) when it follows socially superior strategies. In any case, as we will explain in Sect. 4, our results carry through (although they become weaker) even without this convention.

  18. In pure exclusion strategies incumbent supplier I has no incentive to offer any partial exclusivity contracts in stage 1. Since E is excluded from the market, no contracts are terminated, and no termination penalties are collected in stage 7. Partial exclusivity contracts are thus meaningless.

  19. In accommodation strategies incumbent supplier I has no incentive to offer any pure exclusivity contracts in stage 1. Since E is allowed to enter the market, pure exclusivity contracts (which do not allow the extraction of surplus from E) are meaningless. Similarly, a partial exclusivity contract with \(t_i >r-\underline{c}\) effectively constitutes a pure exclusivity contract since it does not allow customer i to buy from E in equilibrium (see “Appendix” on the equilibrium of stage 7). Thus in accommodation strategies I only offers partial exclusivity contracts with \(t_i \le r-\underline{c}\).

  20. When \(F/(r-c)\ge N-\underline{F}/(r-\underline{c})\), we have a corner solution in which I’s optimal pure exclusion strategy is to offer pure exclusivity contracts with a zero lump-sum payment to all N customers (or, equivalently, to at least \(N-\underline{F}/(r-\underline{c})\) customers). All customers consent to I’s contracts, and I’s equilibrium profit is \(N(r-c)-F>0\). See note 40 in “Appendix.”

  21. Uniform contract offers imply a constant lump-sum payment \(x^*\) across the board because the product is of the same reservation value, r, to all customers. If, however, there were reservation value differences, uniform contract offers would correspond to a constant \(r_i -x_i {}^*\), \(\forall i\in \{1,\ldots ,N\}\) (rather than to a constant lump-sum payment). The same line of reasoning would apply if there were differences in the variable cost of selling to various customers.

  22. Up to the integer constraint. The integer constraint is unimportant as long the number, N, of customers is not too small.

  23. Since in an accommodation subgame I always earns a zero profit, it may be indifferent between multiple accommodation stage-1 strategies. There may thus be several possible equilibria in an accommodation subgame that lead to different levels of welfare for E and customers (although I’s profit is always zero).

  24. If I entered into the market in stage 5 without having any exclusivity contracts with customers, E would also decide to enter in stage 6. E would subsequently sell to all N customers at an equilibrium price c in stage 7, earning a strictly positive profit (\(N(c-\underline{c})-\underline{F}>0\)). Since I would not capture any customers, it would be unable to recover its fixed cost F. It follows that an outright ban on exclusivity contracts would cause I to stay out of the market.

  25. In the corner solution of note 20 a ban on lump-sum payments would have no impact on the equilibrium of the game. I would continue to successfully follow the same pure exclusion strategy in stage 1.

  26. Alternatively, such an outcome may be attained by allowing horizontal cooperation or mergers between original and derivative innovators. In this case, however, the market would become monopolized, driving customer welfare to zero and giving rise to the well-known dynamic losses from monopolization (which are not included in our model), such as the possibility of less innovation in the future.

  27. For example, Innes and Sexton (1994) discuss in detail how socially inefficient entry may be motivated by the possibility of rent transfer.

  28. Lemma 2(ii) carries through after the introduction of the antitrust policies of Proposition 3. Since in any accommodation subgame customers rationally expect derivative innovator E to enter into the market, a customer that is not pivotal for incumbent supplier I’s entry rejects I’s contract offer, avoiding the burden of the termination penalty (also given that I is unable to offer any upfront lump-sum payments). I’s profit is always zero in accommodation subgames.

  29. When \(F/(r-c)\ge N-\underline{F}/(c-\underline{c})\), we have a corner solution. After the antitrust authorities apply the combination of policies of Proposition 3, I always follows a pure exclusion strategy in equilibrium even if E’s innovation is socially beneficial. I offers pure exclusivity contracts with a zero lump-sum payment to all N customers (or, equivalently, to at least \(N-\underline{F}/(c-\underline{c})\) customers). All customers consent to I’s contracts, and I’s equilibrium profit is \(N(r-c)-F>0\). However, although in such a corner solution the antitrust policies of Proposition 3 are followed by the subsequent exclusion of E from the market, they never reduce (and also never enhance) social welfare; instead, they are neutral in that they leave social welfare unchanged. The entry of E would be blocked anyway even without such policies (see Proposition 1 and note 20).

  30. The logic of such a strategy is in the spirit of Segal and Whinston (2000a).

  31. We can see that \(\partial [\Pi _{EX}^I {}^{**}-\Pi _{AC}^I {}^{**}]/\partial \underline{F}=(r-\underline{c})/(c-\underline{c})+1>0\) and \(\partial [\Pi _{EX}^I {}^{**}-\Pi _{AC}^I {}^{**}]/\partial \underline{c}=N+\underline{F}(r-c)/(c-\underline{c})^{2}>0\).

  32. In the corner solution of note 29 the entry of E is blocked after a ban on upfront lump-sum payments is imposed. If \(N(r-c)>N(c-\underline{c})-\underline{F}\), such a corner solution occurs only when I would favor an exclusion strategy anyway, i.e., only in the range where \(\Pi _{EX}^I {}^{**}-\Pi _{AC}^I{}^{**}>0\). In particular, when \(F/(r-c)\ge N-\underline{F}/(c-\underline{c})\), we have \(\Pi _{EX}^I{}^{**}=N(r-c)-F\) (note 47 in “Appendix”), and thus \(N(r-c)>N(c-\underline{c})-\underline{F}\) implies that \(\Pi _{EX}^I {}^{**}-\Pi _{AC}^I {}^{**}>0\) in that range of the corner solution. As a result, condition \(N(r-c)>N(c-\underline{c})-\underline{F}\) ensures that a ban on upfront lump-sum payments never causes an incumbent supplier that favors accommodation strategies to resort to pure exclusion strategies, i.e., such a ban never has a negative impact on social welfare.

  33. Stage-4 lump-sum payments to customers by E are sunk and do not affect E’s stage-6 entry decision.

  34. Similar to note 33.

  35. For customers \(i\in \{N^{I}+1,\ldots ,N\}\) we effectively have \(x_i =0\).

  36. If \(\sum _{i=1}^{N^{I}} {(r-x_i -c)} -F<0\), we may have \(n<0\). In particular, in stage 2 E may relinquish its rights to sell to \(-n\) customers that were not offered contracts by I so that I is effectively granted monopoly rights over them in the stage-7 market (i.e., effectively \(x_i =0,\forall i\in \{1,\ldots ,-n\})\), allowing I’s entry to become viable, i.e., \(\sum _{i=1}^{N^{I}} {(r-x_i -c)} -F<\sum _{i=1}^{N^{I}-n} {(r-x_i -c)} -F=0\) (given that I’s entry is necessary for E’s subsequent entry).

  37. Although all the \(N-N^{I}+n\) customers would indeed buy from E, if \(z_i =x_i <r-c\), a customer \(i\in \{1,\ldots ,N-N^{I}+n\}\) could refuse to sign E’s contract in stage 3, rationally expecting to buy from E without a contract at a lower price c in stage 7 provided that customer i’s contract acceptance is not pivotal for E’s entry. Such a decision (by some of the \(N-N^{I}+n\) customers) to buy from E without a contract would not affect E’s entry; the flow of customers to lower stage-7 prices would stop short of preventing E from entering since once a customer’s stage-3 contract decision became pivotal for E’s entry, the customer would decide to sign E’s contract.

  38. If E’s lump-sum payments are more generous, suppliers may extract less total surplus from customers.

  39. If \(V+(N^{I}-n^{L})(c-\underline{c})+(N-N^{I})(r-\underline{c})-F-\underline{F}<0\), I would be able to offer strictly smaller lump-sum payments to some customers (strictly increasing its profit), while still preventing the entry of E.

  40. When, however, \(F/(r-c)\ge N-\underline{F}/(r-\underline{c})\), we have a corner solution in which I can block the entry of E by setting \(x^*=0\) (i.e., \(N(r-\underline{c}-x)-F(c-\underline{c})/(r-c-x)-F-\underline{F}\le 0\) if \(x=0\)).

  41. We have \(N(r-c)-Nx^*-F>0\) because \(x^*<r-c-F/N\).

  42. The above analysis implies that if \(\sum _{i=1}^N {x_i } =Nx^{\prime }>Nx^*\), there is at least one possible stage-1 strategy for I (i.e., \(x_i =x^{\prime }\), \(\forall i\in \{1,\ldots ,N\})\) that successfully blocks the entry of E.

  43. If in stage 1 \(N^{I}<F/(r-c)\), in stage 1 E relinquishes its rights to sell to \(F/(r-c)-N^{I}\) customers that were not offered contracts by I so that I is effectively granted monopoly rights over them in the stage-7 market. Since we effectively have \(x_i =0,\forall i\in \{1,\ldots ,F/(r-c)\})\), the entry of I is exactly ensured.

  44. If \(F/(r-c)\ge N-\underline{F}/(r-\underline{c})\), we have a corner solution where I is able to block the entry of E (note 40).

  45. It is important that I offers no exclusivity contracts at all, rather than contracts with a zero lump-sum payment, to \(\underline{F}/(c-\underline{c})\) customers although in both cases I would capture a surplus \(r-c\) per buying customer. If I offered an exclusivity contract with a zero lump-sum payment to at least one of the \(\underline{F}/(c-\underline{c})\) customers, such a customer would become I’s most lucrative potential contract participant (given the zero lump-sum payment), replacing \(n^{\prime }>1\) customers that are currently included in \(n^{L}\) and leading to \(n^{L}<N-\underline{F}/(c-\underline{c})\) so that the entry of E is not blocked.

  46. For simplicity, in this section we adopt the tie-breaking convention that if I offers partial exclusivity contracts, and E is indifferent between entering the market and not, E decides to enter.

  47. When \(F/(r-c)\ge N-\underline{F}/(c-\underline{c})\), we have a corner solution in I’s optimal pure exclusion strategy in which I offers pure exclusivity contracts with a zero lump-sum payment to all N customers (or, to at least \(N-\underline{F}/(c-\underline{c})\) customers). All customers accept, and \(\Pi _{EX}^I {}^{**}=N(r-c)-F>0\). Furthermore, if \(N(c-\underline{c})-\underline{F}-F<0\), we have a corner solution in I’s optimal accommodation strategy, and \(\Pi _{AC}^I {}^{**}=0\).

References

  • Aghion, P., Bolton, P.: Contracts as a barrier to entry. Am. Econ. Rev. 77, 388–401 (1987)

    Google Scholar 

  • Anand, B.N., Khanna, T.: The structure of licensing contracts. J. Ind. Econ. 48, 103–135 (2000)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anton, J.J., Yao, D.A.: Expropriation and inventing: appropriable rents in the absence of property rights. Am. Econ. Rev. 84, 190–209 (1994)

    Google Scholar 

  • Anton, J.J., Yao, D.A.: The sale of ideas: strategic disclosure, property rights, and contracting. Rev. Econ. Stud. 69, 513–531 (2002)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anton, J.J., Yao, D.A.: Attracting skeptical buyers: negotiating for intellectual property rights. Int. Econ. Rev. 49, 319–348 (2008)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, M., Wright, J.: Two-sided markets, competitive bottlenecks, and exclusive contracts. Econ. Theory 32, 353–380 (2007)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernheim, D.B., Peleg, B., Whinston, M.D.: Coalition-proof Nash equilibria I: concepts. J. Econ. Theory 42, 1–12 (1987)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernheim, D.B., Whinston, M.D.: Exclusive dealing. J. Polit. Econ. 106, 64–103 (1998)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bessen, J., Hunt, R.M.: An empirical look at software patents. J. Econ. Manag. Strategy 16, 157–189 (2007)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bessen, J., Maskin, E.: Sequential innovation, patents, and imitation. RAND J. Econ. 40, 611–635 (2009)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Biais, B., Perotti, E.: Entrepreneurs and new ideas. RAND J. Econ. 39, 1105–1125 (2008)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Meza, D., Selvaggi, M.: Exclusive contracts foster relationship-specific investment. RAND J. Econ. 38, 85–97 (2007)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dewatripont, M., Maskin, E.: Contract renegotiation in models of asymmetric information. Eur. Econ. Rev. 34, 311–321 (1990)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Federal Trade Commission: Slotting Allowances in the Retail Grocery Industry: Selected Case Studies in Five Product Categories (2003)

  • Flannery, R.: Why imitation bests innovation. Forbes. http://www.forbes.com/2010/05/11/china-america-innovation-leadership-mangement-imitation-book.html (May 11th, 2010). Accessed 15 Mar 2017

  • Fumagalli, C., Motta, M.: Exclusive dealing and entry, when buyers compete. Am. Econ. Rev. 96, 785–795 (2006)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fumagalli, C., Motta, M.: Buyers’ miscoordination, entry and downstream competition. Econ. J. 118, 1196–1222 (2008)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fumagalli, C., Motta, M., Ronde, T.: Exclusive dealing: investment promotion may facilitate inefficient foreclosure. J. Ind. Econ. 60, 599–608 (2012)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Green, J.R., Scotchmer, S.: On the division of profit in sequential innovation. RAND J. Econ. 26, 20–33 (1995)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grossman, G.M., Lai, E.L.C.: International protection of intellectual property. Am. Econ. Rev. 94, 1635–1653 (2004)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hart, O., Tirole J.: Vertical integration and market foreclosure. Brookings Papers on Economic Activity: Microeconomics, pp. 205–286 (1990)

  • Ide, E., Montero, J.P., Figueroa, N.: Discounts as a barrier to entry. Am. Econ. Rev. 106, 1849–1877 (2016)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Inderst, R., Shaffer, G.: Market-share contracts as facilitating practices. RAND J. Econ. 41, 709–729 (2010)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Innes, R., Sexton, R.: Strategic buyers and exclusionary contracts. Am. Econ. Rev. 84, 566–584 (1994)

    Google Scholar 

  • Iwaisako, T., Futagami, K.: Patent protection, capital accumulation, and economic growth. Econ. Theory 52, 631–668 (2013)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levitt, T.: Innovative imitation. Harvard Business Review. https://hbr.org/1966/09/innovative-imitation (1966). Accessed 15 Mar 2017

  • Mansfield, E.: How rapidly does new industrial technology leak out? J. Ind. Econ. 34, 217–223 (1985)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marvel, H.P.: Exclusive dealing. J. Law Econ. 25, 1–25 (1982)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marx, L.M., Shaffer, G.: Upfront payments and exclusion in downstream markets. RAND J. Econ. 38, 823–843 (2007)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moser, P.: Patents and innovation: evidence from economic history. J. Econ. Perspect. 27, 23–44 (2013)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rajan, R.G., Zingales, L.: The firm as a dedicated hierarchy. Q. J. Econ. 116, 805–852 (2001)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rasmusen, E., Ramseyer, M., Wiley Jr., J.: Naked exclusion. Am. Econ. Rev. 81, 1137–1145 (1991)

    Google Scholar 

  • Rasmusen, E., Ramseyer, M., Wiley Jr., J.: Naked exclusion: reply. Am. Econ. Rev. 90, 310–311 (2000)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Segal, I.R., Whinston, M.D.: Naked exclusion: comment. Am. Econ. Rev. 90, 296–309 (2000a)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Segal, I.R., Whinston, M.D.: Exclusive contracts and protection of investments. RAND J. Econ. 31, 603–633 (2000b)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shaffer, G.: Slotting allowances and retail price maintenance: a comparison of facilitating practices. RAND J. Econ. 22, 120–135 (1991)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shenkar, O.: Copycats: How Smart Companies Use Imitation to Gain a Strategic Edge. Harvard Business Review Press, Boston (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  • Simpson, J., Wickelgren, A.L.: Naked exclusion, efficient breach, and downstream competition. Am. Econ. Rev. 97, 1305–1320 (2007)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spector, D.: Exclusive contracts and demand foreclosure. RAND J. Econ. 42, 619–638 (2011)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stefanadis, C.: Naked exclusion and the volatility of innovation. Am. Econ. J. Microecon. 8, 39–50 (2016)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • U.S. Senate: Slotting: Fair for Small Business and Consumers? Hearing before the Senate Committee on Small Business, 106th Congress, 1st Session 388 (1999)

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Christodoulos Stefanadis.

Additional information

We thank Masaki Aoyagi, an anonymous co-editor and four anonymous referees for helpful suggestions. We are especially grateful to Justin Johnson for extensive comments. An earlier (and substantially different) version of the paper circulated under the title of “Innovation, Uniform Pricing, and Exclusivity Contracts”.

Appendices

Appendix

1.1 Equilibrium in the subgames of stages 3, 4, 5, 6 and 7

To solve the game we proceed by backward induction. In stage 7 a customer that is bound by a pure exclusivity contract purchases the product from its exclusive supplier (if the latter has entered the market) at the monopoly price, r. If in stage 7 only incumbent supplier I has entered the market, it sells to all free customers that have not signed exclusivity contracts at the monopoly price, r. If, on the other hand, both suppliers I and E have entered into the market, they compete in the stage-7 market for such free customers; in equilibrium a free customer buys from low-cost supplier E at a price c. Suppose now that in stage 7 a customer i has already signed I’s (finalized) partial exclusivity contract with a termination penalty \(t_i \) and is now offered unit prices \(p_i \) by incumbent I and \({p_{i}^{\prime }}\) by derivative innovator E. Then, customer i decides to buy from E if \(p_i^{\prime }\le p_i -t_i\) and from I otherwise. Competition between I and E for such a customer drives the stage-7 price that customer i pays to E to \(\min \{c,r-t_i \}\). Of course, in case \(r-t_i <\underline{c}\), such a customer does not terminate its contract with I.

In stage 6 E enters into the market when first, I has entered into the market in stage 5 (which is a precondition for E’s entry), and second, E can recoup its upfront fixed cost \(\underline{F}\).Footnote 33 Suppose, for example, that in stage 4 I and E finalized \(n^{I}\) and \(n^{E}\) pure exclusivity contracts with customers, respectively (\(n^{I}+n^{E}\le N\)). Then, E enters into the market in stage 6 if \(n^{E}(r-\underline{c})+(N-n^{I}-n^{E})(c-\underline{c})>\underline{F}\). Suppose now that I finalized \(n^{I}\) partial (rather than pure) exclusivity contracts with customers in stage 4 with \(r-t_i \ge \underline{c}\), \(\forall i\in \{1,\ldots ,n^{I}\}\). Then, E enters the market in stage 6 if \(\sum _{i=1}^{n^{I}} {(\min \{c,r-t_i \}-\underline{c})} +n^{E}(r-\underline{c})+(N-n^{I}-n^{E})(c-\underline{c})>\underline{F}\).

Similarly, in stage 5 I enters into the market when it can recover its upfront fixed cost F.Footnote 34 In case I expects E not to enter in subsequent stage 6, and E has finalized \(n^{E}\) exclusivity contracts with customers, I expects to monopolize the remaining \(N-n^{E}\) customers and thus decides to enter if \((N-n^{E})(r-c)\ge F\). Suppose now that I expects E to enter. If I has finalized \(n^{I}\) pure exclusivity contracts in stage 4, it enters into the market in stage 5 if \(n^{I}(r-c)\ge F\). If, however, I has finalized \(n^{I}\) partial exclusivity contracts in stage 4 with \(r-t_i \ge \underline{c}\), \(\forall i\in \{1,\ldots ,n^{I}\}\), I enters in stage 5 if \(\sum _{i=1}^{n^{I}} {t_i } \ge F\).

In stage 4 I decides to finalize its contracts that have been accepted (in stage 3) by customers if first, I expects to subsequently enter in stage 5 (i.e., if it expects to be able to recover its fixed cost F, as we explained above), and second, I also expects to recoup the stage-4 upfront lump-sum payments, \(\sum _{i=1}^{n^{I}} {x_i } \), that it makes to customers when contracts are finalized; such lump-sum payments are sunk. Similarly, E decides to finalize the contracts that have been accepted (in stage 3) by customers if first, E expects to subsequently enter in stage 6 (as we explained above) and second, E also expects to recover the stage-4 (sunk) upfront lump-sum payments, \(\sum _{i=1}^{n^{E}} {z_i }\).

In stage 3, given that customers can coordinate as in Bernheim et al. (1987), a sufficient number of customers accept I’s contracts so that the subsequent entry of I is ensured (if, of course, the contracts that I offered in stage 1 make such an accommodation of I’s entry by at least one group of consenting customers possible). There can be no stage-3 equilibrium in which an insufficient number of customers accept I’s contracts so that I’s entry is rendered non-viable. In such a hypothetical equilibrium an improving self-enforcing coalition of non-signing customers would deviate, signing I’s contracts and securing I’s entry; otherwise, there would be no available products (by I or E), and customer payoffs would be zero. Once the entry of I is secured, a sufficient number of customers consent to derivative innovator E’s contracts to ensure the subsequent entry of E provided that first, E’s proposed contracts are more favorable to such customers than I’s proposed contracts and second, it is indeed feasible to ensure E’s entry given the proposed contracts. If, however, E is expected to stay out of the market each customer i consents to I’s contract, subsequently earning a surplus \(x_i \ge 0\) (as compared to a zero surplus if the customer does not consent).

Proof of Lemma 1

Suppose that in stage 2 E sets its lump-sum payments equal to \(z_i =x_i \), \(\forall i\in \{1,\ldots ,N^{I}\}\), and \(z_i =0\), \(\forall i\in \{N^{I}+1,\ldots ,N\}\). For E this is the minimum level of lump-sum payments that is necessary for eliciting contract acceptance from customers; if E offered a strictly smaller lump-sum payment to a customer, it would never convince the customer to consent to E’s contract (given I’s competing contracts).Footnote 35 Then, I’s contracts fail to block the subsequent entry of E if and only if in stage 3 there exists a subgroup of \(n\in \{0,1,\ldots ,N^{I}-1\}\) customers that are able to allow the finalization of E’s contracts and the realization of E’s entry by consenting to E’s (rather than to I’s) contracts (\(\sum _{i=1}^n {(r-x_i -\underline{c})} +(N-N^{I})(r-\underline{c})-\underline{F}=\sum _{i=1}^n {(r-x_i -c)} +n(c-\underline{c})+(N-N^{I})(r-\underline{c})-\underline{F}>0\)), while also ensuring the finalization of I’s contracts and the realization of I’s entry (\(\sum _{i=1}^{N^{I}-n} {(r-x_i -c)} -F\ge 0\)).Footnote 36

If such a group of n customers existed and indeed signed E’s contracts, its members would have no incentive to deviate (and buy from I, rather than from E) individually or jointly since I’s entry would be ensured anyway (by the \(N^{I}-n\) customers), and according to the tie-breaking convention, if a customer is indifferent between I and E, it chooses E.Footnote 37 If a subcoalition of those n customers deviated from buying from E, its members would be made strictly worse off. Furthermore, at least a subcoalition of the remaining \(N^{I}-n\) customers would indeed sign I’s contracts so that I’s entry is ensured; otherwise, I (as well as E) would stay out of the market, and no products would be offered to customers. Thus given the above I’s and E’s contract offers in stages 1 and 2, there exists at least one coalition-proof equilibrium in the stage-3 subgame that allows E to enter into the market. Similarly, in case E’s entry was prevented (so that all the \(N^{I}\) customers signed I’s contracts, and no customer signed E’s contracts, expecting E to stay out of the market), at least one possible improving self-enforcing coalition—i.e., the above group of n customers—would have an incentive to jointly deviate and sign E’s contracts, accommodating the entry of E. It follows that there exists no coalition-proof equilibrium in the stage-3 subgame that entails the exclusion of E from the market.

As a result, I’s contracts are successful in blocking the subsequent entry of E if and only if there exists no such group of n customers that are able to allow the entry of both suppliers by signing E’s contracts. In particular, given I’s contract offers, the maximum surplus that the two suppliers, I and E, together can extract from all the N customers is \(Nr-\sum _{i=1}^{N^{I}} {x_i } \); as we explained above, such maximum surplus extraction is attained when E sets its lump-sum payments equal to \(z_i =x_i \), \(\forall i\in \{1,\ldots ,N^{I}\}\), and \(z_i =0\), \(\forall i\in \{N^{I}+1,\ldots ,N\}\).Footnote 38 Then, if even in the presence of such maximum surplus extraction on the part of the two suppliers, there exists no possible group of n customers that (by signing E’s contracts) can ensure the viability of both E’s and I’s entry, I’s contracts can successfully block the entry of E on any occasion. It follows that the entry of E is blocked if there is no group of n customers so that \(\sum _{i=1}^n {(r-x_i -c)} +n(c-\underline{c})+(N-N^{I})(r-\underline{c})-\underline{F}>0\) and \(\sum _{i=1}^{N^{I}-n} {(r-x_i -c)} -F=0\), or so that \(V+n(c-\underline{c})+(N-N^{I})(r-\underline{c})-F-\underline{F}>0,\) where \(V=\sum _{i=1}^{N^{I}} {(r-c-x_i )} \) and \(\sum _{i=1}^{N^{I}-n} {(r-x_i -c)} -F=0\).

In stage 3 let \(n^{L}\) be the number of customers that have been offered the lowest lump-sum payments \(x_i\) by I (i.e., I’s most lucrative potential contract participants) and that can accommodate I’s entry by consenting to I’s contracts, i.e., \(\sum _{i=1}^{n^{L}} {(r-c-x_i )} -F=0\). Since \(\partial [V+n(c-\underline{c})+(N-N^{I})(r-\underline{c})-F-\underline{F}]/\partial n=c-\underline{c}>0\), the preferable (or most profitable) coalition of customers that E can capture in its effort to ensure the viability of its entry (without preventing the entry of I) is the group of \(N-n^{L}\) customers. In particular, E maximizes its profit when I ensures the viability of its entry by selling to a small number, \(n^{L}\), of lucrative customers so that E can sell to the largest possible number of remaining customers, thereby taking full advantage of its lower unit cost; thus E can earn the largest possible \((N-n^{L})(c-\underline{c})\) in addition to stealing I’s potential rent from those \(N-n^{L}\) customers. It follows that I successfully blocks the entry of E if and only if \(V+(N^{I}-n^{L})(c-\underline{c})+(N-N^{I})(r-\underline{c})-F-\underline{F}\le 0\).

Thus in an exclusion subgame I offers pure exclusivity contracts in stage 1 so that \(V+(N^{I}-n^{L})(c-\underline{c})+(N-N^{I})(r-\underline{c})-F-\underline{F}=0\).Footnote 39 If in stage 3 customers rationally expect E to stay out of the market, all the \(N^{I}\) customers consent to I’s contracts (as we explain in Appendix on the equilibrium of stage 3), and I’s profit is \(N(r-c)-\sum _{i=1}^{N^{I}} {x_i } -F\). Suppose now that I makes uniform contract offers to all N customers, i.e., \(x_i =x\), \(\forall i\in \{1,\ldots ,N\}\), which implies that \(n^{L}=F/(r-c-x)\). Then, \(V+(N^{I}-n^{L})(c-\underline{c})+(N-N^{I})(r-\underline{c})-F-\underline{F}\), or \(N(r-\underline{c}-x)-F(c-\underline{c})/(r-c-x)-F-\underline{F}\), is strictly decreasing in x (since \(-N-F(c-\underline{c})/(r-c-x)^{2}<0)\). Furthermore, \(N(r-\underline{c}-x)-F(c-\underline{c})/(r-c-x)-F-\underline{F}\) is strictly positive when \(x=0\) and strictly negative when \(x=r-c-F/N\). There thus exists a unique \(x^*\in (0,r-c-F/N)\) so that \(N(r-\underline{c}-x)-F(c-\underline{c})/(r-c-x)-F-\underline{F}=0\).Footnote 40 It follows that if in stage 1 I offers pure exclusivity contracts \(x_i =x^*\), \(\forall i\in \{1,\ldots ,N\}\), E’s entry is blocked (regardless of E’s strategy in stage 2), and all N customers sign I’s contracts in stage 3. In such an exclusion strategy, I’s profit is \(N(r-c)-Nx^*-F>0\).Footnote 41 Overall, such contract offers (i.e., \(x_i =x^*\), \(\forall i\in \{1,\ldots ,N\})\) constitute I’s optimal stage-1 pure exclusion strategy, i.e., the unique strategy that maximizes I’s profit while also preventing E’s entry.

In particular, suppose that although I still offers the same total amount of lump-sum payments to customers, i.e., \(\sum _{i=1}^N {x_i } =Nx^*\), it does not make uniform contract offers, i.e., there exist at least two customers i and j so that \(x_i \ne x_j \). This implies that \(n^{L}\) is strictly smaller than under the uniform contract arrangement, i.e., \(n^{L}<F/(r-c-x^*)\). The average lump-sum payment in the group of the \(F/(r-c-x^*)\) customers that have been offered the smallest lump-sum payments is strictly smaller than the average, \(x^*\), in the group of all N customers; I’s entry can be accommodated if strictly less then \(F/(r-c-x^*)\) customers consent to I’s contracts. Thus if \(\sum _{i=1}^N {x_i } =Nx^*\) and I’s contract offers are not uniform, the entry of E is not blocked. Similarly, if I does not make contract offers to all customers, i.e., if \(N^{I}<N\) (although we still have \(\sum _{i=1}^{N^{I}} {x_i } =Nx^*)\), E has the opportunity to relinquish its right to sell to the \(N-N^{I}\) customers, effectively granting I monopoly power over them (i.e., effectively setting \(x_i =0\), \(\forall i\in \{1,\ldots ,N-N^{I}\})\). Then, the average lump-sum payment in the group of the \(F/(r-c-x^*)\) customers that have been offered the smallest lump-sum payments (including the \(N-N^{I}\) customers for which \(x_i \) is effectively zero) is strictly smaller than the average, \(x^*\), in the group of all N customers. As before, the entry of E is not blocked.

Suppose now that \(\sum _{i=1}^N {x_i } =Nx^{\prime }>Nx^*\), and that the entry of E is successfully blocked.Footnote 42 I’s profit will be strictly smaller than in the optimal exclusion strategy, i.e., \(N(r-c)-Nx^{\prime }-F<N(r-c)-Nx^*-F\). Furthermore, suppose that \(\sum _{i=1}^N {x_i } =Nx^{\prime }<Nx^*\). Then, the above analysis implies that I is unable to block the entry of E even if I makes uniform contract offers \(x_i =x^{\prime }\), \(\forall i\in \{1,\ldots ,N\}\) (and, of course, if I does not make uniform offers). It follows that I’s unique optimal exclusion strategy is offering \(x_i =x^*\), \(\forall i\in \{1,\ldots ,N\}\) in stage 1. Lemma 1 follows.

Proof of Lemma 2

(i) Suppose that in stage 1 I offers partial exclusivity contracts with \(x_i =0\), \(t_i =r-c\), \(\forall i\in \{1,\ldots ,N\}\). Suppose also that in stage 2 E does not offer any contracts to customers. Then, in the equilibrium of the stage-3 subgame \(F/(r-c)\) customers sign I’s contracts, while the remaining \(N-F/(r-c)\) do not sign. In stage 4 I decides to finalize the contracts (and in stage 5 I decides to enter into the market) since \(t_i F/(r-c)-F=F-F=0\). In stage 6 E also decides to enter since \(N(c-\underline{c})-\underline{F}>0\). We can see that given the contract offers of I and E in stages 1 and 2, the unique stage-3 coalition-proof equilibrium indeed entails \(F/(r-c)\) signing customers.

In particular, in stage 3 each of the \(F/(r-c)\) customers that consent to I’s contracts earns a zero surplus, while each of the \(N-F/(r-c)\) customers that do not consent earns a strictly positive surplus (\(r-c>0\)). Thus no subcoalition of the group of the \(N-F/(r-c)\) non-signing customers would have an incentive to deviate (and consent to I’s contract) since its members would be made strictly worse off, earning a zero surplus. Furthermore, even if one of the \(F/(r-c)\) signing customers deviated (refusing to consent to I’s contract), I would be unable to recover its fixed cost F and would stay out of the market; no products would be offered to customers. Thus no subcoalition of the \(F/(r-c)\) signing customers would have an incentive to deviate. Similarly, in case strictly less (strictly more) than \(F/(r-c)\) customers consented to I’s contracts, an improving self-enforcing coalition of customers would have an incentive to deviate by signing (not signing) I’s contracts so that there are exactly \(F/(r-c)\) signing customers.

We can also see that given I’s contract offers in stage 1, E’s optimal stage-2 strategy is to offer no contracts to customers; E is unable to earn a strictly larger profit by choosing any other stage-2 strategy. In particular, to elicit contract acceptance by one of the \(N-F/(r-c)\) customers that are expected to decline I’s contracts and buy in the stage-7 market (at a price c), E would have to offer a lump-sum payment \(z_i \ge r-c\), which leads to a weakly smaller profit for E than the strategy above. Overall, it follows that if I offers partial exclusivity contracts with \(x_i =0\), \(t_i =r-c\), \(\forall i\in \{1,\ldots ,N\}\) in stage 1, the entry of both I and E is always accommodated in the equilibrium of the subgame. Thus there exists at least one feasible accommodation strategy for I (i.e., the above strategy) in stage 1. Lemma 2(i) follows.

(ii) Suppose that given I’s offers of partial exclusivity contracts in stage 1 and E’s offers of pure exclusivity contracts in stage 2, n customers consent to I’s contracts in stage 3, all contracts are finalized in stage 4, and both I and E decide to enter into the market in stages 5 and 6. Furthermore, suppose that \(\sum _{i=1}^n {(t_i -x_i )} >F\), i.e., I earns a strictly positive profit. In such a subgame equilibrium, although each of the n customers is not individually pivotal for the finalization of I’s contracts and the realization of I’s entry (since \(\sum _{i=1}^n {(t_i -x_i )} >F)\), it is apparently better off buying from I under the terms of I’s offered contract than buying from E under the terms of E’s offered contract or buying from E without a contract at a price c in the stage-7 market.

Suppose now that in stage 2 E deviates by offering a contract with a lump-sum payment \(z_i =\max \{r-c-t_i +x_i, x_i \}\) to one of the above n customers. In stage 3 such a customer would choose to consent to E’s contract since according to the tie-breaking convention, if a customer is indifferent between I and E, it chooses to buy from E, and I’s entry is ensured anyway by the remaining \(n-1\) customers (given that \(\sum _{i=1}^n {(t_i -x_i )} >F)\). Furthermore, E’s profit is increased by capturing such a customer (i.e., \(r-z_i -\underline{c}=\min \{c+t_i -x_i, r-x_i \}-\underline{c}\ge 0)\) as long as \(t_i \ge x_i \), i.e., as long as the customer’s contract with I was not loss-making for I. Thus E indeed has an incentive to make such a deviation in stage 2 to “steal” I’s non-loss-making customer, which implies that initial player strategies after stage 1 did not constitute an equilibrium. We can also see that since all other contracts offers by I and E are unchanged, the remaining \(n-1\) customers indeed continue to consent to I’s contracts as before (since I’s contracts are still preferable to E’s contracts or to no contracts at all), ensuring the entry of I. Overall, it follows that there exists no possible accommodation strategy for I in stage 1 that leads to a strictly positive profit for I in the equilibrium of the subgame. Lemma 2(ii) follows.

Proof of Proposition 2

Suppose that in stage 1 I offers pure exclusivity contracts with \(x_i =0\), \(\forall i\in \{1,\ldots ,N^{I}\}\), \(N^{I}\le N\) (since \(x_i >0\) are banned). By following the same procedure as the proof of Lemma 1, we can see that E is always able to secure its entry. There exist feasible stage-2 strategies for E (e.g., offering pure exclusivity contracts with \(z_i =x_i =0\), \(\forall i\in \{1,\ldots ,N\})\) so that a self-enforcing coalition of \(n\le N-F/(r-c)\) customers always ensures E’s entry by accepting E’s contracts in stage 3. Similar to the proof of Lemma 2(i) \(F/(r-c)\) customers consent to I’s contracts in stage 3, while the remaining \(N-F/(r-c)\) buy from E (either by signing E’s contracts or by waiting to buy from E without a contract in stage 7). It follows that if lump-sum payments are banned, there are no feasible exclusion strategies for I in stage 1.Footnote 43 Furthermore, along the lines of the proof of Lemma 2(ii), since the entry of E is accommodated, the equilibrium profit of I is zero.Footnote 44 In this subgame social welfare—i.e., the sum of I’s profit (\(F(r-c)/(r-c)-F=0\)), E’s profit (\(n^{E}(r-\underline{c})+[N-F/(r-c)-n^{E}](c-\underline{c})-\underline{F}\), where \(n^{E}\) customers have finalized contracts with E) and customer surplus (\([N-F/(r-c)-n^{E}](r-c)\))—is \([N-F/(r-c)](r-\underline{c})-\underline{F}\).

As the proof of Lemma 2(i) shows, even after a prohibition on upfront lump-sum payments, there exists at least one feasible accommodation strategy (i.e., the strategy outlined in the proof of Lemma 2(i)) for I that entails the use of partial exclusivity contracts with \(t_i \le r-\underline{c}\), \(\forall i\in \{1,\ldots ,N\}\) (see note 19) and \(N^{I}\le N\), in which all N customers buy from E in equilibrium. As Lemma 2(ii) also shows, in all such accommodation subgames the equilibrium profit of I is zero. Suppose that in such a subgame I and E finalize contracts with \(n^{I}\) and \(n^{E}\) customers, respectively. Then, social welfare—i.e., the sum of I’s profit (\(\sum _{i=1}^{n^{I}} {t_i } -F\)), E’s profit (\(\sum _{i=1}^{n^{I}} {[\min \{c,r-t_i \}-\underline{c}]} +\sum _{i=1}^{n^{E}} {(r-\underline{c})} +(N-n^{I}-n^{E})(c-\underline{c})-\underline{F}\) and customer surplus (\(\sum _{i=1}^{n^{I}} {[r-\min \{c+t_i, r\}]} +(N-n^{I}-n^{E})(r-c)\)—is \(N(r-\underline{c})-F-\underline{F}\), which is strictly larger than social welfare in the subgame where I offers pure exclusivity contracts (\(N(r-\underline{c})-F-\underline{F}>[N-F/(r-c)](r-\underline{c})-\underline{F}\)). Since a ban on upfront lump-sum payments always leads to a zero equilibrium profit for I anyway, I chooses to offer partial exclusivity contracts in stage 1 so that E sells to all N customers in equilibrium (given that according to the tie-breaking convention, if I is indifferent between two strategies, it chooses the strategy with the larger social welfare). Proposition 2 follows.

Proof of Proposition 3

(i) As the appendix on the equilibrium of stage 7 implies, if in stage 6 E enters into the market without having any exclusivity contracts with customers, in stage 7 it obtains a price c from each free customer without any contract and a price \(\min \{c,r-t_i \}\) from a customer i that has a partial exclusivity contract with I. Thus E’s profit is always weakly smaller than \(N(c-\underline{c})\). It follows that if E is banned from offering exclusivity contracts, it never decides to enter into the market in stage 6 if \(N(c-\underline{c})-\underline{F}\le 0\).

(ii) Similar to the proof of Proposition 2.

Equilibrium if only incumbent supplier I is able to offer exclusivity contracts

Suppose that in stage 1 I offers pure exclusivity contracts to \(N^{I}\le N\) customers. Along the lines of the proof of Lemma 1, let \(n^{L}\) be the number of customers that have been offered the lowest lump-sum payments \(x_i \) by I and that can accommodate I’s entry by consenting to I’s contracts, i.e., \(\sum _{i=1}^{n^{L}} {(r-c-x_i )} -F=0\). I can successfully block the entry of E if and only if \((N-n^{L})(c-\underline{c})-\underline{F}\le 0\); in this case, I sells to all N customers and earns a profit that is equal to \(N(r-c)-\sum _{i=1}^{N^{I}} {x_i } -F=(N-n^{L})(r-c)-\sum _{i=1}^{N^{I}-n^{L}} {x_i } \). Then, in an exclusion subgame I maximizes its profit if \(n^{L}\) is minimized subject to the constraint \((N-n^{L})(c-\underline{c})-\underline{F}=0\), and also \(N^{I}=n^{L}\), i.e., if \(n^{L}=N-\underline{F}/(c-\underline{c})=N^{I}\). Therefore, I’s optimal pure exclusion strategy in stage 1 entails the offer of pure exclusivity contracts to \(N-\underline{F}/(c-\underline{c})\) customers so that \(\sum _{i=1}^{N-\underline{F}/(c-\underline{c})} {x_i } =[N-\underline{F}/(c-\underline{c})](r-c)-F\) and no offers to the remaining \(\underline{F}/(c-\underline{c})\) customers.Footnote 45 Along the lines of the proof of Lemma 1, we can see that in stage 3 each of the \(N-\underline{F}/(c-\underline{c})\) customers consents to I’s contracts. I’s profit is \(\Pi _{EX}^I {}^{**}=\underline{F}(r-c)/(c-\underline{c})>0\).

Suppose now that in stage 1 Ioffers partial exclusivity contracts to customers, and in stage 3 customers expect that both I and E will subsequently enter into the market.Footnote 46 \(n^{1}\) customers are offered \(t_i \le r-c\), while \(N-n^{1}\) customers are offered \(t_i \in (r-c,r-\underline{c}]\) (and effectively \(t_i =0\) for customers that are not offered contracts). Furthermore, \(x_i =\min \{t_i, r-c\}\) since for strictly smaller \(x_i \), a customer i would refuse to accept I’s contract in stage 3 (buying instead without a contract at a price c in stage 7). As the appendix on the equilibrium of stage 7 shows, the stage-7 price that customer i pays to E is \(\min \{c,r-t_i \}\); E’s profit is \(\Pi ^{E}=\sum _{i=1}^N {[\min \{c,r-t_i \}-\underline{c}]} -\underline{F}\). Given that all I’s contracts are accepted by customers and also I’s entry is secured, the entry of E is accommodated (\(\Pi ^{E}\ge 0\)) if and only if \(n^{1}(r-c)+\sum _{i=1}^{N-n^{1}} {t_i } \le N(r-\underline{c})-\underline{F}\). In such a subgame all customers accept I’s partial exclusivity contracts. In particular, along the lines of previous proofs, a sufficient number of customers always consent to I’s contracts to secure I’s entry. In addition, given that the entry of both I and E is secured, each customer consents to I’s partial exclusivity contract since \(x_i =\min \{t_i, r-c\}\) (and in case of a tie a customer decides to consent to a contract). The profit of I is \(\sum _{i=1}^N {(t_i -x_i )} -F=\sum _{i=1}^{N-n^{1}} {t_i } -(N-n^{1})(r-c)-F\).

It follows that the maximum profit of I in an accommodation subgame is \(\Pi _{AC}^I {}^{**}=N(c-\underline{c})-\underline{F}-F\) and is attained when I offers partial exclusivity contracts with \(t_i \le r-\underline{c}\) and \(x_i =\min \{t_i, r-c\}\) so that \(n^{1}(r-c)+\sum _{i=1}^{N-n^{1}} {t_i } =N(r-\underline{c})-\underline{F}\), or so that E’s entry is exactly accommodated. Such a strategy allows I to extract the entire surplus from E’s derivative innovation through the collection of termination penalties after customers breach their contracts with I.Footnote 47 I chooses to follow the optimal pure exclusion (accommodation) strategy when \(\Pi _{EX}^I {}^{**}-\Pi _{AC}^I {}^{**}>0\) (\(\Pi _{EX}^I{}^{**}-\Pi _{AC}^I {}^{**}\le 0\)).

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Choi, J.P., Stefanadis, C. Sequential innovation, naked exclusion, and upfront lump-sum payments. Econ Theory 65, 891–915 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-017-1042-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-017-1042-3

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation