Skip to main content
Log in

From filters to fillers: an active inference approach to body image distortion in the selfie era

  • Original Article
  • Published:
AI & SOCIETY Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Advances in artificial intelligence, as well as its increased presence in everyday life, have brought the emergence of many new phenomena, including an intriguing appearance of what seems to be a variant of body dysmorphic disorder, coined “Snapchat dysmorphia”. Body dysmorphic disorder is a DSM-5 psychiatric disorder defined as a preoccupation with one or more perceived defects or flaws in physical appearance that are not observable or appear slight to others. Snapchat dysmorphia is fueled by automated selfie filters that reflect unrealistic sociocultural standard. In this paper, we discuss how body dysmorphic disorder and related body image distortions could arise, using the conceptual resources provided by the active inference framework. We suggest that these disorders involve dysfunctional self-modelling which entails maladaptive internalization of sociocultural preferences during adolescent identity formation. Identity formation is hereby described as cycles of interpersonal active inference that arbitrate between identity exploration and commitment. We propose that impaired self-modelling is unable to reduce interpersonal uncertainty during identity exploration, which, over time, degenerates into uncontrollable epistemic habits that isolate the body image from corrective sensory evidence. In light of these insights, we subsequently explore some of the consequences of image-centered social media platforms on the identity formation process. We conclude that heightened interpersonal uncertainty in this novel context could precipitate the onset of body dysmorphic disorder and related body image distortions, particularly when selfie filters are involved.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. However, this would be compatible with the notion of pre-reflective bodily intentionality that accompanies the habitual body (Merleau-Ponty 2013; Reuter 1999). According to this view, habitual actions are not directed toward anything specific, but they are nonetheless directed toward something in general (the lived world).

  2. The criteria used in various taxonomies vary greatly. They comprise things such as availability to consciousness, dynamics, functional role, format, perspective, etc. (de Vignemont 2018).

  3. It should be noted that, in the active inference framework, representations are always in the service of action.

  4. Phenomenal transparency is a property of phenomenal representations where only the content is introspectively accessible, but not the process underlying its constitution (i.e. its vehicle) (Blanke and Metzinger 2009). The more the process of constitution (i.e. earlier processing stages) is accessible to introspective attention, the more a representation is opaque. Phenomenal transparency and opacity can be placed along a gradient of phenomenal “epistemic reliability” or “realness” (Metzinger 2014): transparency is experienced as mind-independent (external) reality while opacity is experienced as mind-dependent (internal) abstraction.

  5. This follows from Metzinger’s “principle of virtual identity formation,” which explains transtemporal personal identity as nothing more than an adaptive form of (narrative) self-deception, a virtual simulation that enables long-term planning and motivation (Metzinger 2013, p. 5). It should be noted that this refers to a rather broad conception of narratives as sequences of representations that include subpersonal processes (e.g. automatic narratives) and non-linguistic representations (e.g. mental imagery).

  6. Note that prediction can be understood in two different ways in active inference: First, in the correlational sense that involves one value “predicting” another. This type of inference can be considered “belief-free.” Second, in the abductive sense that involves hypothesis testing. This type of inference can be considered “belief-based.”.

  7. With Clark (2017), we see the predictive system as a series of nested Markov blankets, each with its own set of inputs and outputs. Although the Markov blanket that marks the separation between the biological organism and its physical environment is interesting for many reasons, its inputs and outputs should not be viewed as the inputs and outputs to the system.

  8. In this paper, “representations” is used in a rather liberal fashion and refers to various constructs that depend on the type of generative model employed. Representations involve generative models that correlate with states (continuous or discrete) in the (internal or external) environment. A suggestion as to what distinguishes them is that continuous representations involved in “belief-free” inferences are not representational in a strong sense (i.e. without involving the internal manipulation of content) while discrete representations involved in “belief-based” inferences are representational in a stronger sense (i.e. involving the internal manipulation of content) (for a similar proposal, see Constant et al. 2019, 2020). Of course, in this framework, “belief-free” and “belief-based” are understood as poles of a hierarchical continuum.

  9. Under active inference, there is no competition between distinct model-free and model-based controllers. Instead, it is the hierarchical depth of the planning process that arbitrates between belief-free (shallow) and belief-based (deep) planning (Miller et al. 2018).

  10. Because prediction errors are almost instantly resolved in the lower levels through unconscious peripheral reflexes, they almost never reach the motor cortex. As a consequence, there are very few error units (superficial pyramidal cells) in the primary motor cortex.

  11. It should be noted that bodily agency is a causally enabling factor, but not a constitutive condition for minimal selfhood (Blanke and Metzinger 2009).

  12. According to Metzinger’s “self-deception model of goal selection and action initiation”, the self-model integrates counterfactual misrepresentations of goal-states with intrinsic normativity (Metzinger 2017). Intrinsically normative goal-states are always organism-relative hallucinations, they provide an adaptive form of self-deception that continuously drives the organism forward.

  13. Legault et al. (2019) explain that in the kind of 4E models of cognition that we deem compatible with our account, cognitive deficits, such as mentalization deficits, may be understood as mismatches between environmental resources and the particular form of neurological functioning of individuals.

  14. Planning the future is remembering the past to survive the present. This is because the future tends to resemble the past in a world characterized by causal regularities.

References

  • American Academy of Facial Plastic and Reconstructive Surgery (2018) Annual survey statistics. https://www.aafprs.org/media/stats_polls/m_stats.html. Accessed 28 March 2019

  • Anderson ML (2018) What phantom limbs are. Conscious Cogn 64:216–226

    Google Scholar 

  • Badoud D, Tsakiris M (2017) From the body’s viscera to the body’s image: is there a link between interoception and body image concerns? Neurosci Biobehav Rev 77:237–246

    Google Scholar 

  • Blanke O, Metzinger T (2009) Full-body illusions and minimal phenomenal selfhood. Trends Cogn Sci 13(1):7–13

    Google Scholar 

  • Brooks SJ, Funk SG, Young SY, Schiöth HB (2017) The role of working memory for cognitive control in anorexia nervosa versus substance use disorder. Front Psychol 8:1651

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers G (2008) Types of body representation and the sense of embodiment. Conscious Cogn 17(4):1302–1316

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (2016) Surfing uncertainty: prediction, action and the embodied mind. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (2017) How to knit your own markov blanket: resisting the second law with metamorphic minds. In: Metzinger T, Wiese W (eds) Philosophy and predictive processing. MIND Group, Frankfurt

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark JE, Watson S, Friston KJ (2018) What is mood? A computational perspective. Psychol Med 48(14):2277–2284

    Google Scholar 

  • Constant A, Ramstead MJ, Veissière SP, Friston K (2019) Regimes of expectations: an active inference model of social conformity and decision making. Front Psychol 10:679

    Google Scholar 

  • Constant A, Clark A, Friston KJ (2020) Representation Wars: Enacting an Armistice through Active Inference. Manuscript submitted for publication

  • Cusumano DL, Thompson JK (1997) Body image and body shape ideals in magazines: exposure, awareness, and internalization. Sex Roles 37(9–10):701–721

    Google Scholar 

  • Daw ND, Niv Y, Dayan P (2005) Uncertainty-based competition between prefrontal and dorsolateral striatal systems for behavioral control. Nat Neurosci 8(12):1704

    Google Scholar 

  • Daw ND, Gershman SJ, Seymour B, Dayan P, Dolan RJ (2011) Model-based influences on humans’ choices and striatal prediction errors. Neuron 69(6):1204–1215

    Google Scholar 

  • De Vignemont F (2009) Body schema and body image—pros and cons. Neuropsychologia 48(3):669–680

    Google Scholar 

  • De Vignemont F (2018) Mind the body: an exploration of bodily self-awareness. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Decker JH, Otto AR, Daw ND, Hartley CA (2016) From creatures of habit to goal-directed learners: tracking the developmental emergence of model-based reinforcement learning. Psychol Sci 27(6):848–858

    Google Scholar 

  • Dietrich E, Markman AB (2003) Discrete thoughts: why cognition must use discrete representations. Mind Lang 18(1):95–119

    Google Scholar 

  • Dyl J, Kittler J, Phillips KA, Hunt JI (2006) Body dysmorphic disorder and other clinically significant body image concerns in adolescent psychiatric inpatients: prevalence and clinical characteristics. Child Psychiatry Hum Dev 36(4):369–382

    Google Scholar 

  • Erikson EH (1959) Identity and the life cycle. International Universities Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Erikson EH (1968) Identity: youth and crisis. Norton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Friston K (2005) A theory of cortical responses. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci 360(1456):815–836

    Google Scholar 

  • Friston K (2010) The free-energy principle: a unified brain theory? Nat Rev Neurosci 11(2):127–138

    Google Scholar 

  • Friston KJ (2018) Am I self-conscious? (or does self-organization entail self-consciousness?). Front Psychol 9(579):1–10

    Google Scholar 

  • Friston KJ, Kilner J, Harrison L (2006) A free energy principle for the brain. Physiol Paris 100(1–3):70–87

    Google Scholar 

  • Friston KJ, Daunizeau J, Kiebel SJ (2009) Reinforcement learning or active inference? PLoS ONE 4(7):e6421

    Google Scholar 

  • Friston KJ, Daunizeau J, Kilner J, Kiebel SJ (2010) Action and behavior: a free-energy formulation. Biol Cybern 102:227–260

    Google Scholar 

  • Friston K, Rigoli F, Ognibene D, Mathys C, Fitzgerald T, Pezzulo G (2015) Active inference and epistemic value. Cogn Neurosci 6(4):187–214

    Google Scholar 

  • Friston K, FitzGerald T, Rigoli F, Schwartenbeck P, Pezzulo G (2016) Active inference and learning. Neurosci Biobehav Rev 68:862–879

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Friston KJ, Parr T, de Vries B (2017) The graphical brain: belief propagation and active inference. Netw Neurosci 1(4):381–414

    Google Scholar 

  • Friston KJ, Rosch R, Parr T, Price C, Bowman H (2018) Deep temporal models and active inference. Neurosci Biobehav Rev 90:486–501

    Google Scholar 

  • Frith CD, Metzinger T (2016) How the stab of conscience made us really conscious. In: Angel AK, Friston KJ, Kragic D (eds) The pragmatic turn: toward action-oriented views in cognitive science. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 193–214

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S (1986) Body image and body schema: a conceptual clarification. Journal of Mind and Behavior 7(4):541–554

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S (2005) Dynamic models of body schematic processes. In: De Preester H, Knockaert V (eds) Body image and body schema. John Benjamins Publishing Co., Amsterdam, pp 233–250

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S (2006) How the body shapes the mind. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S, Cole J (1995) Body schema and body image in a deafferented subject. Journal of Mind and Behaviour 16:369–390

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S, Zahavi D (2013) The phenomenological mind. Routledge, Abingdon

    Google Scholar 

  • Grabe S, Ward LM, Hyde JS (2008) The role of the media in body image concerns among women: a meta-analysis of experimental and correlational studies. Psychol Bull 134(3):460–476

    Google Scholar 

  • Groesz LM, Levine MP, Murnen SK (2002) The effect of experimental presentation of thin media images on body satisfaction: a meta-analytic review. Int J Eat Disord 31(1):1–16

    Google Scholar 

  • Grotheer M, Kovács G (2016) Can predictive coding explain repetition suppression? Cortex 80:113–124

    Google Scholar 

  • Gunstad J, Phillips KA (2003) Axis I comorbidity in body dysmorphic disorder. Compr Psychiatry 44(4):270–276

    Google Scholar 

  • Hatoum ID, Belle D (2004) Mags and abs: media consumption and bodily concerns in men. Sex Roles 51:397–407

    Google Scholar 

  • Hogan MJ, Strasburger VC (2008) Body image, eating disorders, and the media. Adolesc Med State Art Rev 19:521–546

    Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy J (2013) The predictive mind. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy J (2016) The self-evidencing brain. Noûs 50(2):259–285

    Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy J, Michael J (2017) Why should any body have a self? In: De Vignemont F, Alsmith AJT (eds) The subject’s matter: self-consciousness and the body. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Holland O (2004) The future of embodied artificial intelligence: machine consciousness? In: Iida F, Pfeifer R, Steels L, Kuniyoshi Y (eds) Embodied artificial intelligence, vol 3139. Lecture notes in computer science. Springer, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurley SL (2002) Consciousness in action. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirchhoff M (2018) Predictive brains and embodied, enactive cognition: an introduction to the special issue. Synthese 195:2355–2366

    Google Scholar 

  • Legault M, Bourdon JN, Poirier P (2019) Neurocognitive variety in neurotypical environments: the source of “Deficit” in Autism. J Brain Behav Sci 9(6):246–272

    Google Scholar 

  • Limanowski J, Blankenburg F (2013) Minimal self-models and the free energy principle. Front Hum Neurosci 7(547):1–12

    Google Scholar 

  • Limanowski J, Friston K (2018) ‘Seeing the dark’: Grounding phenomenal transparency and opacity in precision estimation for active inference. Front Psychol 9(643):1–9

    Google Scholar 

  • Maisto D, Friston K, Pezzulo G (2019) Caching mechanisms for habit formation in active inference. Neurocomputing 359:298–314

    Google Scholar 

  • Marcia JE (1966) Development and validation of ego identity status. J Pers Soc Psychol 3:551–558

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty M (2013) Phenomenology of perception. Routledge, Abingdon

    Google Scholar 

  • Metzinger T (2004) Being no one: the self-model theory of subjectivity. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Metzinger T (2008) Empirical perspectives from the self-model theory of subjectivity: a brief summary with examples. Prog Brain Res 168:215–278

    Google Scholar 

  • Metzinger T (2009) The ego tunnel: the science of the mind and the myth of the self. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Metzinger TK (2013) The myth of cognitive agency: subpersonal thinking as a cyclically recurring loss of mental autonomy. Front Psychol 4(931):1–19

    Google Scholar 

  • Metzinger T (2014) How does the brain encode epistemic reliability? Perceptual presence, phenomenal transparency, and counterfactual richness. Cogn Neurosci 5(2):122–124

    Google Scholar 

  • Metzinger T (2017) The problem of mental action: predictive control without sensory sheets. In: Metzinger T, Wiese W (eds) Philosophy and predictive processing. MIND Group, Frankfurt

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller KJ, Ludvig EA, Pezzulo G, Shenhav A (2018) Realigning models of habitual and goal-directed decision-making. In: Morris R, Bornstein A, Shenhav A (eds) Goal-directed decision making. Academic Press, Cambridge, pp 407–428

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan RG (1996) Pushmi-pullyu representations. In: May L, Friedman M, Clark A (eds) Mind and morals: essays on cognitive science and ethics. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Mufaddel M, Osman OT, Almugaddam F (2013) A review of body dysmorphic disorder and its presentation in different clinical settings. Prim Care Companion CNS Disord. https://doi.org/10.4088/PCC.12r01464

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Neil C (2016) Weapons of math destruction. Crown Books, New York

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Paillard J (1999) Body schema and body image: a double dissociation. In: Gantchev GN, Mori S, Massion J (eds) Motor control, today and tomorrow. Academic Publishing House, Sophia, pp 197–214

    Google Scholar 

  • Pariser E (2011) The filter bubble: what the internet is hiding from you. The Penguin Group, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Parr T, Benrimoh DA, Vincent P, Friston KJ (2018) Precision and false perceptual inference. Front Integr Neurosci 12(39):1–13

    Google Scholar 

  • Peters SK, Dunlop K, Downar J (2016) Cortico-striatal-thalamic loop circuits of the salience network: a central pathway in psychiatric disease and treatment. Front Syst Neurosci 10(104):1–23

    Google Scholar 

  • Pezzulo G, Rigoli F, Chersi F (2013) The mixed instrumental controller: using value of information to combine habitual choice and mental simulation. Front Psychol 4(92):1–15

    Google Scholar 

  • Pezzulo G, Rigoli F, Friston K (2015) Active Inference, homeostatic regulation and adaptive behavioural control. Prog Neurobiol 134:17–35

    Google Scholar 

  • Pezzulo G, Cartoni E, Rigoli F, Pio-Lopez L, Friston K (2016) Active inference, epistemic value, and vicarious trial and error. Learn Memory 23(7):322–338

    Google Scholar 

  • Pezzulo G, Rigoli F, Friston KJ (2018) Hierarchical active inference: a theory of motivated control. Trends Cogn Sci 22(4):294–306

    Google Scholar 

  • Phillips KA, Diaz SF (1997) Gender differences in body dysmorphic disorder. J Nerv Ment Dis 185(9):570–577

    Google Scholar 

  • Phillips KA, Dufresne RG (2000) Body dysmorphic disorder: A guide for dermatologists and cosmetic surgeons. Am J Clin Dermatol 1(4):235–243

    Google Scholar 

  • Pitron V, Alsmith A, de Vignemon F (2018) How do the body schema and the body image interact? Conscious Cogn 65:352–358

    Google Scholar 

  • Poeck K, Orgass B (1971) The concept of the body schema: a critical review and some experimental results. Cortex 7:254–277

    Google Scholar 

  • Powers WT (1973) Behavior: the control of perception. Aldine, Chicago

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Rajanala S, Maymone MBC, Vashi NA (2018) Selfies living in the era of filtered photographs. JAMA Facial Plast Surg 20(6):443–444

    Google Scholar 

  • Reuter M (1999) Merleau-Ponty’s notion of pre-reflective intentionality. Synthese 118(1):69–88

    Google Scholar 

  • Riva G (2012) Neuroscience and eating disorders: the allocentric lock hypothesis. Med Hypotheses 78(2):254–257

    Google Scholar 

  • Riva G, Gaudio S (2018) Locked to a wrong body: eating disorders as the outcome of a primary disturbance in multisensory body integration. Conscious Cogn 59:57–59

    Google Scholar 

  • Riva G, Gaudio S, Dakanalis A (2014) I’m in a virtual body: a locked allocentric memory may impair the experience of the body in both obesity and anorexia nervosa. Eat Weight Disord-Stud Anorex Bulim Obes 19(1):133–134

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson E (2017) Overweight but unseen: a review of the underestimation of weight status and a visual normalization theory. Obes Rev 18(10):1200–1209

    Google Scholar 

  • Rougier NP, Noelle DC, Braver TS, Cohen JD, O’Reilly RC (2005) Prefrontal cortex and flexible cognitive control: rules without symbols. Proc Natl Acad Sci 102(20):7338–7343

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz SJ, Beyers W, Luyckx K, Soenens B, Zamboanga BL, Forthun LF et al (2011) Examining the light and dark sides of emerging adults’ identity: a study of identity status differences in positive and negative psychosocial functioning. J Youth Adolesc 40(7):839–859

    Google Scholar 

  • Serino S, Pedroli E, Keizer A, Triberti S, Dakanalis A, Pallavicini F, Chirico A, Riva G (2016) Virtual reality body swapping: a tool for modifying the allocentric memory of the body. Cyberpsychol Behav Soc Netw 19(2):127–133

    Google Scholar 

  • Seth AK (2013) Interoceptive inference, emotion, and the embodied self. Trends Cogn Sci 17(11):565–573

    Google Scholar 

  • Seth AK (2014) The cybernetic Bayesian brain. Open MIND. MIND Group, Frankfurt

    Google Scholar 

  • Shea N (2013) Perception vs action: the computations may be the same but the direction of fit differs. Behav Brain Sci 36(3):228–229

    Google Scholar 

  • Spreng RN, Grady CL (2010) Patterns of brain activity supporting autobiographical memory, prospection, and theory of mind, and their relationship to the default mode network. J Cogn Neurosci 22(6):1112–1123

    Google Scholar 

  • Talsma D (2015) Predictive coding and multisensory integration: an attentional account of the multisensory mind. Front Integr Neurosci 9:19

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello M, Carpenter M, Call J, Behne T, Moll H (2005) Understanding and sharing intentions: the origins of cultural cognition. Behav Brain Sci 28(5):675–691

    Google Scholar 

  • Verschueren M, Rassart J, Claes L, Moons P, Luyckx K (2017) Identity statuses throughout adolescence and emerging adulthood: a large-scale study into gender, age, and contextual differences. Psychol Belgica 57(1):32

    Google Scholar 

  • Verschueren M, Claes L, Bogaerts A, Palmeroni N, Gandhi A, Moons P, Luyckx K (2018) Eating disorder symptomatology and identity formation in adolescence: a cross-lagged longitudinal approach. Front Psychol 9(816):1–11

    Google Scholar 

  • Verschure PF (2016) Synthetic consciousness: the distributed adaptive control perspective. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci 371(20150448):1–23

    Google Scholar 

  • Ward B, Ward M, Fried O, Paskhover B (2018) Nasal distortion in short-distance photographs: the selfie effect. JAMA Facial Plast Surg 20(4):333–335

    Google Scholar 

  • Weiffenbach A, Kundu RV (2015) Body dysmorphic disorder: etiology and pathophysiology. In: Neelam AV (ed) Beauty and body dysmorphic disorder. Springer, Cham, pp 115–125

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiese W, Metzinger T (2017) Vanilla PP for philosophers: a primer on predictive processing. In: Metzinger T, Wiese W (eds) Philosophy and predictive processing. MIND Group, Frankfurt

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We wish to thank Jeffrey White for his insightful comments, as well as Michael L. Anderson and Thomas Metzinger for the helpful discussions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Safae Essafi Tremblay.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Tremblay, S.C., Essafi Tremblay, S. & Poirier, P. From filters to fillers: an active inference approach to body image distortion in the selfie era. AI & Soc 36, 33–48 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00146-020-01015-w

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00146-020-01015-w

Keywords

Navigation