Physics in Perspective

, Volume 16, Issue 3, pp 344–370 | Cite as

Newton’s Metaphysics of Space as God’s Emanative Effect

Article

Abstract

In several of his writings, Isaac Newton proposed that physical space is God’s “emanative effect” or “sensorium,” revealing something interesting about the metaphysics underlying his mathematical physics. Newton’s conjectures depart from Plato and Aristotle’s metaphysics of space and from classical and Cambridge Neoplatonism. Present-day philosophical concepts of supervenience clarify Newton’s ideas about space and offer a portrait of Newton not only as a mathematical physicist but an independent-minded rationalist philosopher.

Keywords

emanation God metaphysics Henry More Neoplatonism Isaac Newton ontology sensorium space Stoic theocosmology time 

References

  1. 1.
    Isaac Newton, The Method of Fluxions and Infinite Series, ed. trans. John Colson (London: J. Nourse, 1736); Charles Hayes, A Treatise of Fluxions (London: Midwinter, 1704); Colin Maclaurin, A Treatise of Fluxions, in Two Books, Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, 42 (1744), 325–363 (Book I); 403–415 (Book II). Useful overviews include Florian Cajori, A History of the Conceptions of Limits and Fluxions in Great Britain from Newton to Woodhouse (Chicago: Open Court, 1919); Carl B. Boyer, The History of the Calculus and its Conceptual Development (New York: Dover, 1954).Google Scholar
  2. 2.
    Newton, General Scholium, Principia Mathematica Philosophiæ Naturalis, trans. I. Bernard Cohen and Anne Whitman (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1999), 943.Google Scholar
  3. 3.
    Plato, Timaeus 28–29a.Google Scholar
  4. 4.
    My trusted sources include R. T. Wallis, Neoplatonism, 2nd ed. (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co., Inc., 1995); Paulina Remes, Neoplatonism (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2008); Svetla Slaveva Griffin and Paulina Remes, eds., The Routledge Handbook of Neoplatonism (London: Routledge, 2014); Arthur O. Lovejoy, The Great Chain of Being: A Study in the History of an Idea (New York: Harper & Row, Publishers, 1960).Google Scholar
  5. 5.
    Alexandre Koyré, From the Closed World to the Infinite Universe (Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins Press, 1957), 126–160.Google Scholar
  6. 6.
    See Jasper William Reid, “The Evolution of Henry More’s Theory of Divine Absolute Space,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 45 (2007), 79–102.Google Scholar
  7. 7.
    Likewise, Spinoza talking about substance does not make him an Aristotelian. J. E. Power, “Henry More and Isaac Newton on Absolute Space,” Journal of the History of Ideas 31 (1970), 289–296.Google Scholar
  8. 8.
    Newton may have been weakened but did not die from his alchemical experiments, but from a kidney stone. L. W. Johnson and M. L. Wolbarsht, “Mercury Poisoning: A Probable Cause of Isaac Newton’s Physical and Mental Ills,” Notes and Records of the Royal Society of London 34 (1979), 1–9. The aftermath following Newton’s death is examined in detail by Richard S. Westfall, Never at Rest: A Biography of Isaac Newton (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1980), 815–874.Google Scholar
  9. 9.
    Among many other valuable sources on this topic, and in addition to the period philosophers mentioned, see Kasper von Geyerz, Religion and Culture in Early Modern Europe, 15001800 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007).Google Scholar
  10. 10.
    Also, why is everything in motion? Why, for that matter, is anything in motion, moving from one place to another? Neoplatonism has the interesting option of answering that it is the nature of the Good or the choice of God as Godhead or unified Principle of Being to create the physical universe by having all Being emanate forth from its single centralized ontic font, in which everything is in motion by virtue of being an emanative effect. Newton rejects this explanatory model, while retaining some of the unique Neoplatonic framework of concepts and terminology, as he also does in redefining the metaphysics of physical space as God’s sensorium.Google Scholar
  11. 11.
    Isaac Newton, De Gravitatione et æquipondio fluridorum, in Newton, Philosophical Writings, ed. Andrew Janiak, trans. A. R. Hall and Marie Boas Hall (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), 21.Google Scholar
  12. 12.
    Ibid., 25.Google Scholar
  13. 13.
    Ibid., 26. On Newton’s metaphysics and reluctance to use the word “metaphysics,” see Howard Stein, “Newton’s Metaphysics,” in I. B. Cohen and G. E. Smith, eds., The Cambridge Companion to Newton, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002), 256–307; Dale Jacquette, “Aesthetics and Natural Law in Newton’s Methodology,” Journal of the History of Ideas 51 (1990), 659–666.Google Scholar
  14. 14.
    See John Tull Baker, “Space, Time, and God,” The Philosophical Review 41 (1932), 577–593; Koyré, From the Closed World to the Infinite Universe (ref. 6), 125–272; especially his discussion of Henry More, Nicolas Malebranche, Joseph Raphson, George Berkeley and Newton. Robert Rynasiewicz, “By Their Properties, Causes and Effects: Newton’s Scholium on Time, Space, Place, and Motion — i. The Text,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science A 26 (1995), 133–153; Rynasiewicz, “By Their Properties, Causes and Effects: Newton’s Scholium on Time, Space, Place, and Motion — ii. The Context, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science B 26 (1995), 295–3221; Robert DiSalle, “Newton’s Philosophical Analysis of Space and Time,” in Cambridge Companion to Newton (ref. 15), 33–56; Andreas Blank, “Existential Dependence and the Question of Emanative Causation in Protestant Metaphysics,” Intellectual History Review 19 (2009), 1–13; Eric Schliesser, “Newtonian Emanation, Spinozism, Measurement and the Baconian Origins of the Laws of Nature,” Foundations of Science 18 (2013), 449–466.Google Scholar
  15. 15.
    Henry More, An Antidote Against Atheism, 2nd ed. (London: J. Flesher, 1655); More, The Immortality of the Soul (London: J. Flesher, 1659); More, Enchiridion Metaphysicum (London: E. Flesher, 1671). Only More’s Enchiridion would have appeared after Newton wrote De Gravitatione and certainly all of these books in More’s large repertoire would have been circulating before Newton wrote answers to the Queries in later editions of the Opticks.Google Scholar
  16. 16.
    Koyré, From the Closed World to the Infinite Universe (ref. 5) 159.Google Scholar
  17. 17.
    Ibid., 190.Google Scholar
  18. 18.
    Ibid., 220. See also J. E. McGuire, “Newton on Place, Time, and God: An Unpublished Source,” British Journal for the History of Science 11 (1978), 114–129.Google Scholar
  19. 19.
    Aristotle, Physics 194b16–195a27; Metaphysics 1013a24–1014a16, and De Partibus Animalium 639b12–15.Google Scholar
  20. 20.
    Newton, Opticks (New York: Dover, 1952), 402.Google Scholar
  21. 21.
    Ibid., 402–403.Google Scholar
  22. 22.
    Johann Wolfgang von Goethe, The Metamorphosis of Plants (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2009).Google Scholar
  23. 23.
    Thomas Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1962).Google Scholar
  24. 24.
    See Geoffrey Gorham, “God and the Natural World in the Seventeenth Century: Space, Time, and Causality,” Philosophy Compass 4 (2009), 859–872; Gorham, “Newton on God’s Relation to Space and Time: The Cartesian Framework,” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 93 (2011), 281–320; J. E. McGuire, “Predicates of Pure Existence: Newton on God’s Space and Time,” in Philosophical Perspectives on Newtonian Science, ed. Phillip Bricker and R. I. G. Hughes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), 91–108; Edward Slowik, “Newton’s Metaphysics of Space: A ‘Tertium Quid’ betwixt Substantivalism and Relationism, or Merely a 'God of the (Rational Mechanical) Gaps'?” Perspectives on Science 17 (2009), 429–456.Google Scholar
  25. 25.
    Ibid., 404–405.Google Scholar
  26. 26.
    On the concept of supervenience, with applications especially in the philosophy of mind, see Jaegwon Kim, Supervenience and Mind: Selected Philosophical Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), who distinguishes between weak and strong supervenience (53–78); see also Elias E. Savellos and Umit D. Yalcin, eds., Supervenience: New Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995).Google Scholar
  27. 27.
    Ibid., 403. See Ayval Lesham, Newton on Mathematics and Spiritual Purity (Berlin: Springer Verlag, 2003), 78–80.Google Scholar
  28. 28.
    Samuel Clarke’s Latin translation of the original English edition of Newton’s (1704) Opticks was publised as Optice: Sive de reflexionibus, refractionibus, inflexionibus & coloribus lucis (London: William and John Innys, 1706). I was originally drawn to this source by an on-line translation and commentary of the Clark edition by George MacDonald Ross, on a website that seems to have been deactivated. I hope to avoid both offending Ross and violating copyright or other intellectual property right in quoting from this part of his once public domain translation.Google Scholar
  29. 29.
  30. 30.
    I. C. Tipton, Berkeley: The Philosophy of Immaterialism (London: Taylor & Francis, 1974), 117, discusses some of the difficulties of attribution of the famous formula to any of Berkeley’s writings. Nicholas Malebranche should also be mentioned in this connection, despite essential differences from Berkeley.Google Scholar
  31. 31.
    Newton, Opticks (ref. 20), 370.Google Scholar
  32. 32.
    See Jacquette, “Zeno of Citium on the Divinity of the Cosmos,” Studies in Religion/Sciences Religieuses 24 (1995), 415–431.Google Scholar
  33. 33.
    Newton, De Gravitatione (ref. 11), 26.Google Scholar
  34. 34.
  35. 35.
    This pantheistic view goes back to the Stoics, beginning with Zeno of Citium, later maintained by Spinoza and in an idealist variant Nicolas Malebranche; see Jacquette, “Zeno” (ref. 32).Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Basel 2014

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Institute for Philosophy Logic and Theoretical PhilosophyUniversity of Bern UnitoblerBern 9Switzerland

Personalised recommendations