Skip to main content

Advertisement

SpringerLink
Sensory Experiences as Cryptic Symbols of a Multimodal User Interface
Download PDF
Download PDF
  • Review Article
  • Open Access
  • Published: 21 February 2017

Sensory Experiences as Cryptic Symbols of a Multimodal User Interface

  • Donald D. Hoffman1 

Activitas Nervosa Superior volume 52, pages 95–104 (2010)Cite this article

  • 1060 Accesses

  • 2 Citations

  • 4 Altmetric

  • Metrics details

Abstract

According to current theories of perception, our visual experiences match or approximate the true properties of an objective physical world. Ecological optics claims this match is direct, unmediated by psychological or computational processes. Computational theories claim that this match is indirect, the result of sophisticated algorithms that instantiate, e.g., the inferential methods of Bayesian estimation. The assumption of all of these theories that there is an objective, i.e., mind independent, physical world has proved incapable, so far, of yielding a scientific theory for the mind-body problem, a scientific theory of the relationship between conscious experiences and the brain. Therefore I explore, instead, the pos-sibility that sensory experiences constitute a multimodal user interface (MuI) between the perceiver and an objective world, an interface useful precisely because it does not match, approximate, or resemble that world. I also explore conscious realism, the ontological claim that the objective world itself is comprised entirely of conscious agents. Together, MUI theory and conscious realism provide a straightforward solution to the mind-body problem, and entail epiphysicalism: physical objects, such as quarks and brains and stars, are constructed by conscious agents, but such physical objects have no causal powers.

Download to read the full article text

Working on a manuscript?

Avoid the most common mistakes and prepare your manuscript for journal editors.

Learn more

References

  • Bennett, B.M., Hoffman, D.D., & Kakarala, R.. (1993). Modeling performance in observer theory. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 37, 220–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, B.M., Hoffman, D.D., & Murthy, P. (1993). Lebesgue logic for probabilistic reasoning, and some applications to perception. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 37, 63–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, B.M., Hoffman, D.D., & Prakash, C. (1989). Observer mechanics: A formal theory ofperception. San Diego: Academic Press. Available free: http://www.cogsci.uci.edu/%7Eddhoff/ompref.html

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, B.M., Hoffman, D.D., & Prakash, C. (1991). Unity of perception. Cognition, 38, 295–334.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, B.M., Hoffman, D.D., Prakash, C., Richman, S. 1996. Observer theory, Bayes theory, and psychophysics. In D. Knill and W. Richards (Eds) Perception as Bayesian inference. Cambridge University Press, pp. 163–212.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N., & Fodor, J. (1972). What psychological states are not. Philosophical Review, 81, 159–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bradley, D.R., & Petry, H.M. (1977). Organizational determi-nants of subjective contour: The subjective Necker cube. American Journal of Psychology, 90, 253–262.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D.J. (1995). The conscious mind: In search of a fundamental theory. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P.M. (1995). The engine of reason, the seat of the soul: A philosophical journey into the brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P.S. (2002). Brain-wise: Studies in neurophilosophy. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crick, F., & Koch, C. (1998). Consciousness and neuroscience. Cerebral Cortex, 8, 97–107.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, R. (1641/1984). The philosophical writings of Descartes. Translated by J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, and D. Murdoch. Cambridge University Press.

  • Dennett, D. (1983). Consciousness explained. Boston: Little, Brown and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edelman, G. (1992). Bright air, brilliant fire. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edelman, G. (2004). Wider than the sky: The phenomenal gift of consciousness. Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edelman, G., & Tononi, G. (2000). A universe of conscious-ness: How matter becomes imagination. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foster, J. (1991). The immaterial self: A defence of the Carte-sian dualist conception of the mind. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J.J. (1986). The ecological approach to visual perception. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffin, D.R. (1998). Unsnarling the world knot: Conscious-ness, freedom, and the mind-body problem. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Helmholtz, H.L.F. (1910/1962). Handbook of physiological optics, Volume III. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffman, D.D. (1998). Visual intelligence: How we create what we see. New York: W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1982). Epiphenomenal qualia. Philosophical Quarterly, 32, 127–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1781/2003). Critique of pure reason. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knill, D., & Richards, W. (Eds) (1996). Perception as Baye-sian inference. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koch, C. (2004). The quest for consciousness: A neurobiological approach. Englewood, CO: Roberts and Company Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marr, D. (1982). Vision. San Francisco: Freeman Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maynard-Smith, J. (1982). Evolution and the Theory of Games. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Penrose, R. (1994). Shadows of the mind. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poggio, T., Torre, V., & Koch, C. (1985). Computational vision and regularization theory. Nature, 317, 314–319.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Sabra, A.I. 1978. Sensation and inference in Alhazen’s theory of visual perception. In Machamer, P.K. & Turnbull, R.G. (Eds) Studies in perception: Interrelations in the history of philosophy and science. Columbus: Ohio State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schneiderman, B. (1998). Designing the user interface: Strat-egies for effective human-computer interaction. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms, B. (2000). Game Theory, Rationality and Evolution of the Social Contract. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 7, 269–284.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (1996). Ten Problems of Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (2000). Consciousness, Color, and Content. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, J.A., & Zurek, W.H. (1983). Quantum theory and measurement. Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Whitehead, A.N. (1929/1979). Process and reality: An essay in cosmology. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

  1. Department of Cognitive Science, University of California, Irvine, California, 92697, USA

    Donald D. Hoffman

Authors
  1. Donald D. Hoffman
    View author publications

    You can also search for this author in PubMed Google Scholar

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Donald D. Hoffman.

Rights and permissions

Open Access  This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if changes were made.

The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article’s Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the article’s Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder.

To view a copy of this licence, visit https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/.

Reprints and Permissions

About this article

Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Hoffman, D.D. Sensory Experiences as Cryptic Symbols of a Multimodal User Interface. Act Nerv Super 52, 95–104 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF03379572

Download citation

  • Received: 22 June 2010

  • Accepted: 02 July 2010

  • Published: 21 February 2017

  • Issue Date: September 2010

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF03379572

Share this article

Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:

Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.

Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative

Key words

  • Consciousness
  • Computation
  • Sensory Experience
  • Mind-Body Problem
Download PDF

Working on a manuscript?

Avoid the most common mistakes and prepare your manuscript for journal editors.

Learn more

Advertisement

Over 10 million scientific documents at your fingertips

Switch Edition
  • Academic Edition
  • Corporate Edition
  • Home
  • Impressum
  • Legal information
  • Privacy statement
  • California Privacy Statement
  • How we use cookies
  • Manage cookies/Do not sell my data
  • Accessibility
  • FAQ
  • Contact us
  • Affiliate program

Not affiliated

Springer Nature

© 2023 Springer Nature Switzerland AG. Part of Springer Nature.