Skip to main content
Log in

“Because a robot's brain hasn't got a brain, it just controls itself” — Children's attributions of brain related behaviour to intelligent artefacts

  • Published:
European Journal of Psychology of Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Educational settings have seen an increased presence of intelligent artefacts. Objects such as computers and robots take up new positions along the animate-inanimate continuum due to their substantive “cognitive” and “sensori-motor” repertoires including for example an ability to engage with a diversity of problem-solving tasks and having a memory. In the present study we report children's understanding of a variety of stimulus objects with different anthropomorphic features, including a person, robot, computer and doll. Attributional judgements were elicited from 60 children aged 5–11 and a comparison group of adults. Children were asked for judgements (and justifications) whether the above objects were capable of realising a large number of items drawn from 6 major behavioural categories (e.g., involuntary activity). The data, show that the different objects did not generally elicit substantially different justification patterns. The exception to this is a clear developmental pattern in terms of an increased understanding of the nature of clever artefacts. Results are discussed in terms of different forms of causal reasoning and the specific nature of the act of programming in terms of a growing understanding of the behaviour of intelligent artefacts.

Résumé

Les situations éducatives utilisent de plus en plus d' “artefacts” intelligents. Les objets tels que les ordinateurs et les robots occupent une place particulière sur le continuum animé-inanimé du fait de leurs répertoires “cognitif” et “sensori-moteur”. Ils sont par exemple dotés d'une mémoire et capables de traiter une grande diversité de tâches en résolution de problèmes. La recherche présentée concerne la compréhension qu'ont les enfants d'une variété d'objets-stimulus présentant différentes caractéristiques anthropomorphiques: une personne, un robot, un ordinateur et une poupée. On a sollicité les jugements attributifs de 60 enfants âgés de 5 à 11 ans et comparé ces jugements à ceux d'un groupe d'adultes. On a demandé aux enfants de juger (avec justifications) la capacité des objets ci-dessus à avoir toute une série de comportements regroupés en six catégories principales (par ex. agir involontairement). Les données montrent que, d'une façon générale, les différents objets ne sont pas à l'origine de différences substantielles dans les patterns de justifications. On observe cependant une nette évolution liée à l'âge de la compréhension de la nature des “artefacts” intelligents. Les résultats sont discutés en termes de différentes formes de raisonnement causal. La nature spécifique des actes de programmation est discutée en termes d'accroissement de la compréhension du comportement des artefacts intelligents.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Astington, J.W., & Gopnick, A. (1988). Knowing you have changed your mind: Children's understanding of representational change. In J.W. Asington, P.L. Harris, & D.R. Olson (Eds.),Developmental Theories of Mind (pp. 193–207). Cambridge: CUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Backscheider, A.G., Shatz, M., & Gelman, S.A. (1993). Preschooler's ability to distinguish living kinds as a function of regrowth.Child Development, 64, 1242–1257.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boden, M.A. (1977).Artificial Intelligence and Natural Man. Hassocks: Harvester press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carey, S. (1985).Conceptual Change in Childhood. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, J. (1968). Weighted kappa: Nominal scale agreement with provision for scaled disagreement or partial credit.Psychological Bulletin, 70, 213–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Contento, I. (1981). Children's thinking about food and eating: A Piagetian based study.Journal of Nutrition Education, 13, 86–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frye, D., Rawling, P., Moore, C., & Meyers, L. (1983). Object-person discrimination at three and 10 months.Developmental Psychology, 19, 303–309.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gellert, E. (1962). Children's conceptions of the content and functions of the human body.Genetic Psychology Monographs, 65, 291–411.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gelman, R. (1979). Preschool thought.American Psychologist, 34, 900–905.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gelman, R., & Spelke, E.S. (1981). The development of thoughts about animate and inanimate objects: Implications for research on social cognition. In J.H. Flavell & L. Ross (Eds.),Social Cognitive Development: Frontiers and Possible Futures (pp. 43–67). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greenacre, M. (1985).Theory and applications of correspondence analysis. London: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hatano, G., & Inagaki, K. (1994). Young children's naive theory of biology.Cognition, 50, 171–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Inagaki, K. (1993).Young children's differentiation of plants from non-living things in terms of growth. Paper presented at the 60th meeting of the Society for Research in Child Development, New Orleans.

  • Inagaki, K., & Hatano, G. (1993). Young children's understanding of the mind-body distinction.Child development, 64, 1534–1549.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, C.N., & Wellman, H.M. (1982). Children's developing conceptions of the mind and brain.Child Development, 53, 222–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keil, F. (1991).Concepts, kinds, and cognitive development. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Legerstee, M. (1992). A review of the animate-inanimate distinction in infancy: Implications for models of social and cognitive knowing.Early Development and Parenting, 2, 59–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Massey, C., & Gelman, R. (1988). Preschoolers' ability to decide whether a photographed familiar object can move itself.Development Psychology, 24, 307–317.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oakley, M. (1995).Sharks. Loughborough: Ladybird.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piaget J. (1926).The child's conception of the world. London: Routledge & Keegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piaget J. (1954).The Construction of reality in the child. New York: Basic Books.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Resnick, M., & Martin, F. (1991). Children and Artificial Life. In I. Harel & S. Papert (Eds.),Constructionism (pp. 41–71). New Jersey: Ablex.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scaife, M., & van Duuren, M.A. (1995). Do computers have brains? What children believe about intelligent artefacts.British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 13, 367–377.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1990). Is the brain's mind a computer?Scientific American, January, 1990.

  • Turkle, S. (in press). Romantic reactions: Paradoxical responses to the computer presence. In M. Sosna & J.J. Sheehan (Eds.),Boundaries of humanity: Humans, animals, machines. (pp. 224–252). Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

  • van Duuren, M.A., & Scaife, M. (1995). How do children represent intelligent technology?European Journal of Psychology of Education, 10, 289–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van IJzendoorn, M.H., & Kroonenberg, P.M. (1988). Cross-cultural patterns of attachment: A meta-analysis of the strange situation.Child Development, 59, 147–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van IJzendoorn, M.H., Goldberg, S., Kroonenberg, P.M., & Frenkel, O.J. (1992). The relative effects of maternal and child problems on the quality of attachment: A meta-analysis of attachment in clinical samples.Child Development, 63, 840–858.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wellman, H., & Gelman, S.A. (1992). Children's understanding of the non-obvious. In R.J. Sternberg (Ed.),Advances in the Psychology of Intelligence (vol. 2, pp. 60–78). Hillsdale: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimmer, H., & Perner, J. (1983). Beliefs about beliefs: Representations and constraining function of wrong beliefs in young children's understanding of deception.Cognition, 13, 103–128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Additional information

An ESRC linked studentship to MVD, and ESRC Research Grant No. C08250010 are gratefully acknowledged.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

van Duuren, M., Scaife, M. “Because a robot's brain hasn't got a brain, it just controls itself” — Children's attributions of brain related behaviour to intelligent artefacts. Eur J Psychol Educ 11, 365–376 (1996). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF03173278

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF03173278

Key words

Navigation