Skip to main content
Log in

The dissolution of goodness:Measure for Measure and classical ethics

  • Published:
International Journal of the Classical Tradition Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article argues that the Duke inMeasure for Measure undertakes an ethical experiment designed to show the superiority of classical—particularly—Aristotelian ethics over ‘puritan’ conceptions of morality. The sources of Shakespeare’s knowledge of classical ethics are investigated, and the interpretation is shown to dissolve many of the play’s central conundrums.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  1. J. A. K. Thompson,Shakespeare and the Classics (London: George Allen and Unwin, 1952), p. 129. Now see also J. W. Velz, ‘The Ovidian Soliloquy in Shakespeare,’Shakespeare Studies 18 (1986), pp. 1–24 and cf. Ch. and M. Martindale,Shakespeare and the Uses of Antiquity (London and New York: Routledge, 1990), p. 83; J. Bate,Shakespeare and Ovid (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1993), p. 70–71, p. 116, p. 154.

    Google Scholar 

  2. See, for example,Measure for Measure, The Arden Edition, ed. J. W. Lever (London: Routledge, 1988), p. 67.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Donald A. Stauffer,Shakespeare’s World of Images. The Development of his Moral Ideas (New York: Norton, 1949; repr. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 1966), p. 156. Quoted in Lever, Arden Edition, p. xci. Also Lever’s own remarks, ibid. (London: Routledge, 1988), p. 67.

    Google Scholar 

  4. All quotations fromMeasure for Measure are from Lever’s Arden Edition.

  5. G. Wilson Knight, ‘Measure for Measure and the Gospels,,’ in:Measure for Measure: A Casebook, ed. G. K. Stead (London: MacMillan, 1971), pp. 91–121.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Measure for Measure and the Gospels’, pp. 91 and 94.

  7. Schlegel’s word is ‘Gesindel.’ August Wilhelm Schlegel,Vorlesungen über dramatische Kunst und Literatur [1808, publ. 1809–11], vol. 2=Id.,Kritische Schriften und Briefe, ed. Edgar Lohner, vol. 6, Sprache und Literatur 38 (Stuttgart: Kohlhammer Verlag, 1967), p. 152. The passage is translated inThe Romantics on Shakespeare, ed. Jonathan Bate (Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1992), p. 451 (John Block’s translation [1815], revised by A.J.W. Morrison [1848]).

  8. Isabella, of course, makes no verbal response to the Duke’s proposal, and exactly how she behaves is a matter for directorial decision. I have tried to steer a middle course between the ecstacy with which she reponds in some productions and the stony silence or look of horror with which she responds in others. Generally, the negative reaction—which has only been considered a possibility in the last fifteen years or so—strikes me as ingenious and topical rather than in accordance with the spirit of the play; I therefore prefer to stay with the traditional reading at this point.

  9. Stauffer,Shakespeare’s World of Images, p. 156. Quoted in Lever, Arden Edition, p. xci.

  10. Lever, Arden Edition, p. xci.

  11. Perhaps Sonnet 18, 1.2, ‘Thou art more lovely and more temperate’, comes closest to Escalus’s concept of temperance, although the primary focus here, as in theTempest, is on the climate.

  12. All quotations from Aristotle are fromThe Ethics of Aristotle. The Nicomachean Ethics, trans. J. A. K. Thompson, with an Introduction and notes by Jonathan Barnes, revised with notes and appendices by Hugh Tredennick (Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1976).

  13. All quotations from Plato, except for theRepublic, are fromPlato: The Collected Dialogues, ed. Edith Hamilton and Huntington Cairns (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1973).

    Google Scholar 

  14. Helen North,Sophrosyne: Self-knowledge and Self-restraint in Greek Literature, Cornell Studies in Classical Philology 35 (Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press, 1966), p. 102 on the relationship ofsophron andmetrios.

    Google Scholar 

  15. [Alle] Begriffe, in denen sich ein ganzer Prozess semiotisch zusammenfasst, entziehen sich der Definition; definirbar ist nur Das, was keine Geschichte hat.’ F. Nietzsche,Zur Genealogie der Moral, G. Colli and M. Montinari (eds),Nietzsche Werke, Kritische Gesamtausgabe, vol. 6.2 (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1968), p. 333. I use the translation found in Nietzsche,The Genealogy of Morals: An Attack, Second Essay: ‘“Guilt,” “Bad Conscience,” and Related Matters,’ section XIII, trans. Francis Golffing (New York: Doubleday, 1956), p. 210.

    Google Scholar 

  16. North,Sophrosyne, pp. 16–21, 124, 140, 178–9.

  17. Lines 1071–4. See North,Sophrosyn, 97–8.

  18. Martin Luther, ‘To the Christian nobility of the German nation concerning the reform of the Christian estate,’ trans. H. E. Jacobs and J. Atkinson, in:Luther’s Works, ed. J. Pelikan and H. T. Lehmann, vol. 44 (St. Louis, MO: Concordia, 1958), 201 =Luther, ‘An den christlichen Adel deutscher Nation von des christlichen Standes Besserung,’ in:Werke, Kritische Gesamtausgabe, vol. 6 (Weimar/Graz: H. Böhlau, 1888), 458. Cf. Brian P. Copenhaver and Charles B. Schmitt,Renaissance Philosophy, A History of Western Philosophy, vol. 3 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992), p. 39.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Here I rely heavily on Clifford Leech, ‘The Meaning ofMeasure for Measure,’ in: Stead (ed.),Measure for Measure: A Casebook, pp. 152–65.

  20. Divine Meditations 10, in: John Donne,The Complete English Poems, ed. A. J. Smith (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1980), p. 313.

    Google Scholar 

  21. See John Roe, “The Poetry of Sidney, Shakespeare, Chapman and Donne,’ and Stephen Medcalf, ‘Shakespeare on Beauty, Truth and Transcendence,’ in:Platonism and the English Imagination, ed. A. Baldwin and S. Hutton (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994), pp. 107–10 and 117–25. John Vyvyan,Shakespeare and Platonic Beauty (LondonL Chatto and Windus, 1961), is also relevant in this context.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Emrys Jones,The Origins of Shakespeare (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977), p. 20.

    Google Scholar 

  23. I. A. Richards, ‘Troilus and Cressida and Plato,’ in: id. I. A. Richards,Speculative Instruments (Routledge and Keegan Paul: London, 1955), pp. 205–6. These pages contain a brief discussion ofJulius Caesar. It must be pointed out that this article has been criticised for tendentious overstatement. See John Paul Russo,I. A. Richards: His Life and Work (London: Routledge, 1989), pp. 290–3.

  24. The relevant lines of Tranio’s speech (I,ii,25–45) are as follows: ‘I am .../Glad that you thus continue your resolve/To suck the sweets of sweet philosophy./Only, good master, while we do admire/This virtue and this moral discipline,/Let’s not be no Stoics nor no stocks, I pray,/Or so devote to Aristotle’s check/As Ovid is an outcast quite abjur’d (I,ii, 26–33).The Taming of the Shrew is one of Shakespeare’s earlier plays, being written in 1593–4, and this passage betrays a less sophisticated understanding of Aristotle than his later explorations inTroilus and Cressida andMeasure for Measure. In Tranio’s speech, morality is pictured as a matter of restraints (‘checks’) or eradicated feelings (‘stocks’), and Aristotle is portrayed as siding with the Stoics against the passion and sensuality of Ovid. It is part of the argument of this paper to show that, after (re)reading Aristotle forTroilus and Cressida, Shakespeare came to see that Aristotle and the Stoics donot share the same conception of morality, and that a proper understanding of Aristotle’ssophrosyne shows it to be quite compatible with intense feeling. Helen North states the correct view, and surely Shakespeare’s later view, succinctly:sophrosyne, she observes, is ‘the harmonious product of intense passion under perfect control’ (Sophrosyne, p. x), and that ‘[whereas] Aristotle required only that the appetites be moderated, the Stoics demanded that passion be extirpated’ (ibid., p. 215).

  25. Richards, ‘Troilus,’ pp. 198–213, and Medcalf, ‘Shakespeare on Beauty,’ pp. 122–5.

  26. Richards, ‘Troilus,’ pp. 122–5.

  27. Medcalf, ‘Shakespeare on Beauty’ (above, n. 21) in:, pp. 122–5.

    Google Scholar 

  28. On the relationship with Jonson, see Medcalf, ‘Shakespeare on Beauty’, pp. 118–9.

  29. Troilus and Cressida, The arden Edition, ed. Kenneth Palmer (London: Methuen, 1982), Appendix III, pp. 311–20. The relationship between theEthics and this play has recently been re-explored by W. R. Elton in ‘Aristotle’sNicomachean Ethics and Shakespeare’sTroilus and Cressida’, Journal of the History of Ideas 58 (1997), pp. 331–337.

    Google Scholar 

  30. R. Pfeiffer,History of Classical Scholarship from 1300 to 1850 (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1976), p. 29. For an account of Bruni’s translating activities, see Copenhaver and Schmitt,Renaisance Philosophy (above, n. 18), A History of Western Philosophy, vol. 3 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992), pp. 76–84.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Charles B. Schmitt,Aristotle and the Renaissance (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1983), p. 77.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Schmitt,Aristotle and the Renaissance, p. 125.

  33. T. W. Baldwin,William Shakespere’s Small Latine & Lesse Greeke (Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1944), vol. 1, p. 547.

    Google Scholar 

  34. The development of Grammar School curricula is discussed in Baldwin,William Shakespere’s Small Latine, pp. 75–185, and 285–436.

  35. Copenhaver and Schmitt,Renaissance Philosophy (above, n. 18),, p. 124, and Schmitt,Aristotle and the Renaissance (above, n. 31),Aristotle and the Renaissance (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1983), p. 53.

    Google Scholar 

  36. John Stockwood,A Sermon Preached at Paules Crosse on Barthelmew day, being the 24. of August. 1578, quoted in Baldwin,Shakespere’s Small Latine, vol. 1, p. 111.

  37. J. M. Robertson,Montaigne and Shakespeare (London: Adam and Charles Black, 1909), p. 42. Robertson uses an edition of Florio’s translation by Henry Morley (The essayes of Michael Lord of Montaigne, trans. John Florio (1603), ed. Henry Morley [London: Routledge, 1886]; hereafter=Morley); a more recent and accessible edition can be found in the ‘Everyman’s Library’ series (Montaigne’s Essays in Three Volumes, trans. John Florio, Everyman’s Library 440–42 [London: Dent 1910; repr. 1965]; hereafter=Everyman).

    Google Scholar 

  38. R. W. Church, ‘The Essays of Montaigne,’ in:Oxford Essays, contributed by Members of the University, [vol. 3] (London: John W. Parker and Son, 1857), p. 279. Cf. Robertson,Montaigne and Shakespeare, p. 194.

    Google Scholar 

  39. John Stirling,London and Westminster Review, July 1838, p. 346. Quoted in Robertson,Montaigne and Shakespeare, p. 194.

  40. Richard H. Popkin,The History of Scepticism from Erasmus to Spinoza (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1979), p. 42.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Michel de Montaigne, ‘On experience’ (Book 3, ch. 13). in:Essais, ed. and trans. J. M. Cohen (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1981), p. 389=‘De l’experience,’ in: id. Michel de Montaigne, ‘On experience’ (Book 3, ch. 13),Essais, ed. M. Rat, vol. 2 (Paris: Editions Garnier, 1962), p. 560. I have used Cohen’s translation, rather than the most recent one by Screech, because in these particular instances I think Cohen’s renderings are more idiomatic. The relevant page reference in Screech is:The Essays of Michel De Montaigne, ed. and trans. M. A. Screech (Harmondswroth: Penguin, 1987), p. 1251.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Montaigne, ‘On Experience’ (Book 3, ch. 13), in: Cohen (trans.), p. 357=id. Montaigen, ‘De l'experience’, in: Rat (ed.), vol. 2, p. 529 (Screech, p. 1221).

  43. Ralph Waldo Emerson, ‘Montaigne; Or, the Skeptic,’ in: Ralph Waldo Emerson,Selected Essays, ed. Larzer Ziff (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1982), p. 325.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Popkin,The History of Scepticism, p. 56.

  45. See Lever, Arden Edition, p. 67.

  46. Robertson,Montaigne and Shakespeare, p. 48, quoting Montaigne, ‘Of Physiognomy,’ trans. Florio, in: Morley, Book 3, ch. 12, p. 540.

  47. Hamlet’s fifth soliloquy (‘To be or not to be ... ’ [III,i,56–89]) also lacks any mention of sin. This is noted by William Kerrigan,Hamlet’s Perfection (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1994), p. 97.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Robertson,Montaigne and Shakespeare, p. 87, quoting Montaigne, ‘That to Philosophie, is to learne how to die,’ trans. Florio, in: Morley, Book 1, ch. 19, p. 33 (=Everyman, vol. 1, p. 86).

  49. Robertson,Montaigne and Shakespeare, p. 91, quoting Montaigne, ‘Of Exercise or Practice,’ trans Florio, in: Morley, Book 2, ch. 6, p. 185 (=Everyman, vol. 2, p. 51).

  50. Robertson,Montaigne and Shakespeare, p. 95, quoting Montaigne, ‘An Apologie of Raimond Sebonde,’ trans. Florio, in: Morley, Book 2, ch. 12, p. 294 (=Everyman, vol. 2, p. 291).

  51. I would like to thank Professor Wolfgang Haase for drawing my attention to the relevance of this work. Part of this passage is quoted and discussed in Lever, Arden Edition, p. xlix, and also in Elizabeth Pope, “The Renaissance Background ofMeasure for Measure,”Shakespeare Survey 2 (1970), pp. 66–82, especially 73 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Lever, Arden Edition, p. xlvii.

  53. See, for example, Donald Lloyd Stevenson, ‘The Historical Dimension inMeasure for Measure: The Role of James I in the Play,’ an appendix to id., Donald Lloyd Stevenson,The Achievement of Shakespeare’s Measure for Measure (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1966), p. 134–66, and Richard Levin, ‘The King James Version ofMeasure for Measure,’ Clio 3 (1974), pp. 129–63.

  54. William Barlow,The Summe and Substance of the Conference ... at Hampton Court (1604), p. 84. Cited by David Lloyd Stevenson,ELH. A Journal of English Literary History 26 (1959), p. 200 and quoted in Lever, Arden Edition, p. xlvii.

  55. See the account in Lever, Arden Edition, p. l, of James’s late pardoning of several men condemned to hang in Winchester for their part in Raleigh’s conspiracy in the winter of 1603–4.

  56. James VI and I,Political Writings, ed. Johann P. Sommerville, ser. Cambridge Texts in the History of Political Thought, (Cambridge, New York, Oakleigh, and Melbourne: Cambridge University Press, 1994), pp. 45–6. Elizabeth Pope, ‘The Renaissance Background ofMeasure for Measure’ (above, n. 51),Shakespeare Survey 2 (1970), pp. 66–82, also discusses this parallel.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Lever, Arden Edition, pp. xlix-1.

  58. S. Schoenbaum,William Shakespeare: A Compact Documentary Life (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987), p. 250.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Lever, Arden edition, p. xxxv.

  60. James VI and I,Political Writings, pp. 43–4.

  61. I am using the phrases ‘puritan morality’ and ‘Christian morality’ as semi-technical terms to denote the kind of views held by Angelo and Isabella. I do not intend to imply that the presuppositions I isolate are either necessary or sufficient for a Christian conception of morality. Many Christians would, of course, regard what I call ‘puritan morality’ as a complete travesty of Christianity; they would wish to emphasize purity of heart, empathy, human responsiveness, etc.

  62. In this I follow Bernard A. O. Williams,Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy (London: Collins, 1985), p. 6, and Jonathan Barnes, ‘Introduction’ to Aristotle,Ethics, p. 31. My understanding of Greek ethics has been heavily influenced by both of these works. For the view that Greek—especially Homeric—notions of morality, action, responsibility etc. are utterly remote from ours, see the interpretations of Bruno Snell and others criticized in Williams’Shame and Necessity, Sather Classical Lectures 57 (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993), especially pp. 21–49. For an opinion which is more conservative than Williams’s, and argues that Greek notions of morality and virtue are more like our own, see Julia Annas,The Morality of Happiness (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993).

    Google Scholar 

  63. My reading of Aristotle has been particularly influenced by Martha Nussbaum, ‘The Discernment of Perception: An Aristotelian Conception of Private and Public Rationality,’ in: ead.,Love’s Knowledge. Essays on Philosophy and Literature (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990), pp. 54–105.

    Google Scholar 

  64. I take this distinction from Julia Annas,An Introduction to Plato’s Republic (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991), pp. 153–69.

    Google Scholar 

  65. The Republic, ed. and trans. Desmond Lee (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1987).

    Google Scholar 

  66. Immanuel Kant,The Moral Law (Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals), ed. H. J. Paton (London: Hutchinson, 1976), pp. 63–5.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Plutarch,De Virtute Morali, 445c-d. Quoted in Annas,The Morality of Happiness, p. 53.

  68. Montaigne, ‘On Cruelty’ (Book 2, ch. 11), in: Cohen (ed.), p. 178=id., Montaigne, ‘De La Cruaute,’ in: Rat (ed.), vol. 1, p. 467 (Screech p. 476).

  69. James VI and I,Basilicon Doron, pp. 43–44.

  70. Matthew Arnold, ‘Heinrich Heine,’ in: id. Matthew Arnold,Essays Literary and Critical, ed. G. K. Chesterton (London: Dent, 1919), p. 115.

  71. A great deal of English literature can be seen as mounting a campaign against abstract rulegoverned conceptions of morals on behalf of the good heart and educated emotions.Tom Jones is an obvious example, but the following sentence from George Eliot puts the matter succinctly: ‘There is no general doctrine which is not capable of eating out our morality if unchecked by the deep-seated habit of direct fellow-feeling with individual fellow-men.’Middlemarch, Ch. 61 (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1994), p. 619.

  72. Moulding on the the island of Lesbos was ogival, i.e., took the form of a double curve. This could not be measured with a rigid ruler, and consequently builders used a leaden ruler which could be bent to the shape of the object being measured.

  73. On Mercy, see the collection of passages in Theodor Meron,Henry’s Wars and Shakespeare’s Laws: Perspectives on the Law of War in the Later Middle Ages (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1993), p. 80.

    Google Scholar 

  74. See Nussbaum, ‘The Discernment of Perception’ (above, n. 63), in: ead.,, pp. 97–101.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Samuel Taylor Coleridge,Literary Remains (1836), quoted in Bate,The Romantics on Shankespeare (above, n. 7) (Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1992), p. 453.

  76. Algernon Charles Swinburne,A Study of Shakespeare (1880), quoted in R. W. Chambers, ‘Measure for Measure,’ in:Measure for Measure, The Signet Classic Shakespeare, ed. S. Nagarajan (New York: New American Library, 1963), pp. 207–8.

  77. W. W. Lawrence,Shakepeare’s Problem Comedies (New York: Macmillan, 1931), p. 112, quoted in Chambers, ‘Measure for Measure,’ p. 192.

    Google Scholar 

  78. The Times Literary Supplement, 16 July 1931, p. 554, quoted in Chambers, ‘Measure for Measure,’ p. 192.

  79. Wilson Knight, ‘Measure for Measure and the Gospels’, p. 92.

  80. Roy W. Battenhouse, ‘Measure for Measure and the Christian Doctrine of Atonement,’Publications of the Modern Language Association 61 (1946), 1029–59. Quoted in Leech, ‘The Meaning,’ p. 157.

    Google Scholar 

  81. ‘The Renaissance Background ofMeasure for Measure’ (above, n. 51.),Shakespeare Survey 2 (1970), pp. 71.

    Google Scholar 

  82. It might be objected that, in my eagerness to demonstrate the non-Christian origins of the Duke’s morality, I overlook the occasion when Angelo says that the Duke‘...like power divine, / Hath looked upon my passes...’ (V,i,367). But this isAngelo’s interpretation of the Duke’s behaviour and he still views the Duke’s actions through the categories of the puritan worldview. He is the character whose conception of morality is most remote from temperance and self-knowledge, and, unlike Isabella (a less extreme case), he is only just beginning to arrive at a position where self-knowledge is possible. For an article which argues that Angelo’s fault is lack of self-knowledge rather than hypocrisy, see W. H. Durham, ‘What art thou, Angelo?’,University of California Publications in English VIII (2) (1951), p. 169.

    Google Scholar 

  83. For the evidence that Shakepeare’s father had Catholic sympathies see S. Schoenbaum,William Shakespeare, pp. 45–54.

  84. W. H. Auden, ‘The Joker in the Pack,’ in:Othello: A Casebook, ed. J. Wain (London: Macmillan, 1985), pp. 119–223.

    Google Scholar 

  85. S. Cavell, ‘The Avoidance of Love: A Reading ofKing Lear,’ in: id. S. Cavell,Must We Mean What We Say? A Book of Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1976 [originally New York: Scribner, 1969]), pp. 267–353.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Additional information

I would very much like to thank Marie McGinn, Stephen Wall, Ann Pasternak-Slater, Hermione Lee, A. W. Price, Alan Heaven and, above all, the editor of this journal, Wolfgang Haase, for suggestions which led to significant improvements in this paper. I would also like to record a debt to Ruth Nevo’s, ‘Measure for Measure: Mirror for Mirror,’Shakespeare Survey 40 (1988), pp. 107–22. Although she has nothing to say about classical ethics, her views of Angelo, Isabella and Escalus are similar to my own.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Rowe, M.W. The dissolution of goodness:Measure for Measure and classical ethics. Int class trad 5, 20–46 (1998). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02701310

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02701310

Keywords

Navigation