Skip to main content
Log in

Moral reasoning without rules

  • Articles
  • Section on “Commonsense and Scientific Reasoning”
  • Published:
Mind & Society Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Genuine rules cannot capture our intuitive moral judgments because, if usable, they mention only a limited number of factors as relevant to decisions. But morally relevant factors are both numerous and unpredictable in the ways they interact to change priorities among them. Particularists have pointed this out, but their account of moral judgment is also inadequate, leaving no room for genuine reasoning or argument. Reasons must be general even if not universal. Particularists can insist that our judgments be reflective, unbiased, informed, and sensitive, requiring a background of experiences that expand sympathy and empathy for others. But beyond this, our judgments must be coherent. This requirement provides a way to reason to the correct answer to a controversial issue—the answer most coherent with or body of settled judgments. Rawls' account of coherence in terms of reflective equilibrium, where we adjust particular judgments to match rules and adjust rules to match judgments, is rejected since rules have no independent force. Instead, the central requirement is that we not judge cases differently without being able to cite a morally relevant difference between them. Such differences must make a difference else-where as well, although they need not do so universally. Factors cannot be relevant in only one context because they reflect values that must recur to be maintained. The method of moral reasoning based on this requirement is specified as follows: first, the specification of competing values or interests in the problematic case; second, the location of paradigm cases in which these competing values are prioritized, making sure that these settled judgments are reflective, informed, and sensitive; third, the search for relevant differences between the settled and problematic cases or the location of alternative, more closely analogous paradigms. The paper ends with an illustration of the method applied to the issue of doctor assisted suicide.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Blum, Lawrence (1994)Moral Perception and Particularity (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Dancy, Jonathan (1985) The Role of Imaginary Cases in Ethics,Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 66, pp. 141–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, Alan (1988)Moral Knowledge (London, Routledge).

    Google Scholar 

  • Hampshire, Stuart (1983),Morality and Conflict (Cambridge MA, Harvard University Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Millgram, Elijah (1999)Practical Induction, (Cambridge MA, Harvard University Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Rachels, James (1975) Active and Passive Euthanasia,New England Journal of Medicine, 292, pp. 78–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John (1971)A Theory of Justice (Cambridge MA, Harvard University Press).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Goldman, A.H. Moral reasoning without rules. Mind & Society 2, 105–118 (2001). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02512362

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02512362

Keywords

Navigation