Skip to main content
Log in

Hypothetical contractarianism and the disclosure requirement problem in informed consent

  • Published:
Journal of Medical Humanities Aims and scope Submit manuscript

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Reference notes

  1. Cf John Rawls,A Theory of Justice Harvard University Press, Cambridge, 1971.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Cf David Gauthier,Morals By Agreement Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1986.

    Google Scholar 

  3. A Theory of Justice, op cit., pp. 260–263.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Morals by Agreement, op cit., p. 233.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Cf Thomas Nagel's,The View From Nowhere Oxford University Press, New York, 1986, and Bernard Williams'Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, 1985, esp. Chapter 2, which is entitled “The Archimedean Point.”

    Google Scholar 

  6. Morals By Agreement, op cit., p. 233.

    Google Scholar 

  7. For a more detailed presentation of the arguments for these standards of disclosure, and from which this summary account is taken, see Ruth R. Faden and Tom L. Beauchamp,A History and Theory of Informed Consent Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1986, pp. 30–34. In this book Faden and Beauchamp argue for what they call “effective communication.” This is not really a new standard of disclosure but rather a principle one could use in order to meet the demands of the subjective standard of disclosure. For details of their argument see pp. 298–336.

    Google Scholar 

  8. This problem is more difficult for Gauthier than Rawls for in Rawls' case—given the restricted nature of our inquiry—it might be the case that we end up viewing those who are unable to engage in the practice of informed consent as the least advantaged. Gauthier, on the other hand, tells us explicity that his theory does not apply to those who are, unfortunately, less fortunate than the rest of us.Cf Morals by Agreement, op cit., p. 17.

    Google Scholar 

  9. For an account of the distinction between justice and charity, and from which the following arguments are drawn see Allen Buchanan's “Justice and Charity,”Ethics Vol. 97, No. 3, April 1987, pp. 558–575.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Cf Immanuel Kant'sFoundations of the Metaphysics of Morals (trans. Lewis White Beck), Bobbs-Merrill Co., Indianapolis, 1980.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Cf J. S. Mill'sUtilitarianism (ed. O. Piest), Bobbs-Merrill Co., Indianapolis, 1957, p. 61.

    Google Scholar 

  12. For an account of rights and correlative duties see Wesley Newcomb Hohfeld'sFundamental Legal Conceptions As Applied in Judicial Reasoning Yale University Press, New Haven, 1919, esp. pp. 35–64.

    Google Scholar 

  13. For an account of a pluralist approach—that is combining what the author takes to be the best in each of the utilitarian, egalitarian, libertarian and Rawlsian contractarianism—not to the problem of disclosure requirements in informed consent but rather to the problem of rights to health care see Charles J. Dougherty'sAmerican Health Care Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1988.

    Google Scholar 

  14. For an overview of these competing theories of justice see Allen Buchanan's “Justice: A Philosophical Review,” inJustice and Health Care, (ed. Earl E. Shelp) D. Reidel Publishing Co., Dordrecht, Holland, 1981. For an overview of these theories as applied to the problem of triage—that is the distribution of medical resources under conditions of dire scarcity—see Gerald R. Winslow's excellent bookTriage and Justice, University of California Press, Berkeley, 1982.

    Google Scholar 

  15. As far as I know no one has attempted to apply Rawls' theory to this problem although some have applied the theory to other problems in medical ethics. The two most recent applications of Rawls' theory have been by Norman Daniels in hisJust Health Care (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1985) and hisAm I My Parents' Keeper? An Essay on Justice Between the Young and Old, (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1988).

    Google Scholar 

  16. Cf A Theory of Justice, op cit, p. 12. Also see pp. 136–150.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Ibid, p. 62.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Ibid, p. 152–153.

    Google Scholar 

  19. For the exact formulation of the three principles of justice seeA Theory of Justice, op cit. p. 302.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Ibid, pp. 42–45. Allen Buchanan offers the best explication of Rawls' concept of lexical ordering when he says “A principle ‘P’ is lexically prior to a principle ‘Q’ if and only if we are first to satisfy all the requirements of ‘P’ before going on to satisfy the requirements of ‘Q’. Lexical priority allows no trade-offs between the demands of conflicting principles: the lexically prior principle takes absolute priority.”Cf Buchanan “Justice: A Philosophical Review,”op cit, p. 6.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Cf Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals, op cit, p. 73. Also see Rawls' section on the “The Kantian Interpretation of Justice as Fairness” inA Theory of Justice, op cit, pp. 251–257.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals, op cit, p. 73. Also see p. 51.

    Google Scholar 

  23. A Theory of Justice, op cit, p. 102. Both Nozick and Gauthier object to Rawls' argument that people cannot be said to deserve their share of the natural lottery.Cf Morals By Agreement, op cit, p. 220, and Robert Nozick'sAnarchy, State, and Utopia, Basic Books, New York, 1974, pp. 213–216.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Morals by Agreement, op cit, p. 7.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Ibid, pp. 235–236.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Ibid, pp. 253–254. Also see p. 256 where Gauthier says that this is the “second key that unlocks the door screening our moral understanding ...” The “first key” is, as I will indicate shortly, that the ideal actor must choose as if she were each of the persons affected by her choice.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Ibid, p. 255.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Ibid, p. 257.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Ibid, pp. 257–258.

    Google Scholar 

  30. For Gauthier's discussion of the Lockean Proviso see Chapter 7, “The Initial Bargaining Position: Rights and the Proviso, pp. 190–232. Gauthier's ideal actor also chooses “the market in conditions of perfect competition,” (p. 261), and the “principle of minimax relative concession,” (p. 265) but these need not concern us here.

  31. Ibid, pp. 258–259.

  32. John Locke,Two Treatises of Government, ch. v, para. 25. There is an important problem concerning what Locke meant when he said that God gave the world to man “in common.” One can interpret this in either of two ways. On the one hand, one could interpret “in common” to mean that the world is unowned and therefore Locke's task is to show how people can come to have private property rights in a world where, initially, no one owns anything. On the other hand, one could interpret “in common” to mean that the world is jointly owned by everyone and therefore Locke's task is to show how one can come to have private property rights where, initially, everyone jointly owns everything. We will not concern ourselves with this problem other than to note, for it is important in what follows, that both Nozick and Gauthier accept the former interpretation.

  33. Two Treatises of Government, ch. v, para. 33.

  34. Anarchy, State, and Utopia, op cit, p. 175.

  35. Morals by Agreement, op cit, p. 203.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Cf J. J. C. Smart and Bernard Williams,Utilitarianism For and Against Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1973, pp. 116–117.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Cf A Theory of Justice, op cit, p. 27.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Cf Morals by Agreement, op cit, p. 254.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Ibid, pp. 2–3.

    Google Scholar 

  40. A Theory of Justice, op cit, pp. 48–51.

    Google Scholar 

  41. For a comparison of these ignorance conditions seeA Theory of Justice pp. 136–142 andMorals By Agreement, pp. 235–236, 253–257.

  42. Loren Lomasky,Persons, Rights, and the Moral Community, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1987, p. 47.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Ibid.,, p. 26.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Ibid.,, p. 31.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Ibid.,, p. 26.

    Google Scholar 

  46. A Theory of Justice, op cit, pp. 407–416.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Utilitarianism: For and Against, op cit, p. 117.

  48. Joseph Raz,The Morality of Freedom Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1986, pp. 288–320.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Josiah Royce,The Philosophy of Loyalty The Macmillan Company, New York, 1924, p. 168.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Cust, K.F.T. Hypothetical contractarianism and the disclosure requirement problem in informed consent. J Med Hum 12, 119–138 (1991). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF01145832

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF01145832

Keywords

Navigation